The Phrasal Implicature Theory of Metaphors and Slurs

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Phrasal Implicature Theory of Metaphors and Slurs THE PHRASAL IMPLICATURE THEORY OF METAPHORS AND SLURS Alper Yavuz A Thesis Submitted for the Degree of PhD at the University of St Andrews 2018 Full metadata for this thesis is available in St Andrews Research Repository at: http://research-repository.st-andrews.ac.uk/ Please use this identifier to cite or link to this thesis: http://hdl.handle.net/10023/13189 This item is protected by original copyright This item is licensed under a Creative Commons Licence The Phrasal Implicature Theory of Metaphors and Slurs Alper Yavuz This thesis is submitted in partial fulfilment for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (PhD) at the University of St Andrews March 2018 Abstract This thesis develops a pragmatic theory of metaphors and slurs. In the pragmatic literature, theorists mostly hold the view that the framework developed by Grice is only applicable to the sentence-level pragmatic phenomena, whereas the subsenten- tial pragmatic phenomena require a different approach. In this thesis, I argue against this view and claim that the Gricean framework, after some plausible revisions, can explain subsentential pragmatic phenomena, such as metaphors and slurs. In the first chapter, I introduce three basic theses I will defend and give an outline of the argument I will develop. The second chapter discusses three claims on metaphor that are widely discussed in the literature. There I state my aim to present a theory of metaphor which can accommodate these three claims. Chapter3 introduces the notion of \phrasal implicature", which will be used to explain phrase- level pragmatic phenomena with a Gricean approach. In Chapter4, I present my theory of metaphor, which I call \phrasal implicature theory of metaphor" and discuss certain aspects of the theory. The notion of phrasal implicature enables a new conception of what-is-said and a different approach to the semantics-pragmatics distinction. Chapter5 looks into these issues. In Chapter6, I compare my theory of metaphor with three other theories. Finally, in Chapter7, I develop a phrasal implicature theory of slurs, which I argue outperforms its rivals in explaining various uses of slurs. 1 Acknowledgements First of all, I would like to thank Cengiz G¨undo˘gdu. My interest in philosophy started in his seminars at \Insancıl_ At¨olyesi" in Istanbul._ I realised the significance of philosophy for the first time in these open-to-public seminars on history of philosophy and the place of philosophy in life. Next, I would like to thank Omer¨ Naci Soykan, who encouraged me to become a philosopher while I was a Computer Science student. I have felt his support since then. His dedication to philosophy will be a guiding light for the rest of my career. Many thanks to Ilhan_ Inan,_ who was my Master's thesis supervisor at Bo˘gazici University in Istanbul._ I am indebted to him for his profound impact in my initiation to philosophy of language. He has been a mentor, friend and role model for me. I would like to thank Mimar Sinan Fine Arts University, where I began working as a research assistant in 2008, for sponsoring my doctoral education. I am grateful to the chairs of the Philosophy Department Hakan Poyraz and Hasan B¨ulent G¨ozk^an for permitting me to apply to the doctoral funding program of Turkish Council of Higher Education and the subsequent extensions. My research assistant friends Eylem Hacımurato˘glu,Egemen Ku¸scu,Barı¸sAydo˘ganand Ekin Dedeo˘gluhad to undertake extra responsibilities when I was away. My special thanks go to them. I spent three and a half wonderful years in St Andrews. I cannot imagine a better place to do a philosophy PhD, and I am not exaggerrating. The staff in the Philosophy Department were always helpful and friendly. Thanks to them and to all philosophy postgraduate community for creating such an inclusive work environ- ment. I was lucky enough to be a member of Arch´e. In its inspiring atmosphere doing philosophy was great fun. I would like to thank all my Arch´efriends, but particularly to my office mates Ryo Ito, Fenner Tanswell, Caroline Touborg, Dan Healey and Alex Yates (almost an office mate). My deepest thanks go to my supervisor Derek Ball, who was always extremely helpful and understanding all through the PhD period. He carefully read everything I wrote over and over again and gave me invaluable feedback. I am also indebted to my second supervisor Josh Dever. Every meeting with him was full of intellectual 2 3 pleasure, and his contributions to this thesis were always crucial. I had the chance to discuss several aspects of my thesis with Emma Borg, Elisabeth Camp, Herman Cappelen, Robyn Carston, Aaron Cotnoir, Andy Egan, Berys Gaut, Simon Hope, Colin Johnston, Paula Rubio-Fern´andez,Josef Stern, and Michael Wheeler. I am grateful for their input. I am sincerely thankful to Elisabeth Camp and Patrick Greenough, who kindly accepted to act as my PhD examiners. Their detailed comments on my thesis are of great importance for my future work. I would like to express my immense gratitude to my friends Caroline Touborg, Wolfgang Sattler, Matt Cameron, Ravi Thakral, Poppy Mankowitz and Matt McK- eever, who read parts of my thesis in its final phase and gave me extremely helpful feedback on its content and form. Finally, I wish to thank my partner Ipek_ Mine Sonakın, my parents Veysel and T¨ulinYavuz, and my sister Ozg¨ulYavuz¨ for their love and support. I dedicate this thesis to my beloved partner Ipek_ Mine Sonakın and to my dear teacher Omer¨ Naci Soykan, who passed away on December 3rd, 2017. Contents 1 Introduction 10 1.1 There are Phrasal Implicatures . 11 1.2 Metaphorical Meaning is a Form of Phrasal Implicature . 18 1.3 Slurring Generates Phrasal Implicatures . 19 2 Common Claims about Metaphor 21 2.1 Grice on Metaphor . 21 2.1.1 The Features of Conversational Implicatures . 25 2.1.2 Flouting the Maxims: Metaphor and Irony . 27 2.2 Metaphor-Implicature Contrast Claim . 31 2.3 One-step Process Claim . 37 2.4 The Claim that Metaphorical Meaning is Implicated . 46 3 Phrasal Implicature 53 3.1 Examples of Phrasal Implicatures . 54 3.2 Theoretical Discussion . 58 3.2.1 Previous Discussions concerning Subsentential Implicatures . 59 3.2.1.1 Chierchia on Embedded Implicatures . 61 3.2.1.2 Simons on Embedded Implications . 63 3.2.2 My Proposal . 67 3.2.2.1 Bart Geurts and Karen S. Lewis on the Gricean Rea- soning at the Subsentential Level . 68 3.2.2.2 A Gricean Approach to Subsententials . 71 3.2.2.3 Maxims at the Subsentential Level . 73 4 The Phrasal Implicature Theory of Metaphor 81 4.1 The Theory of Metaphor in General . 81 4.1.1 Triggering of Phrasal Implicatures . 82 4.1.2 The Basic Picture . 87 4.1.3 Salience . 88 4 5 Contents 4.1.4 Question Under Discussion (QUD) . 89 4.1.5 Emergent Property Problem . 91 4.1.6 Systematic Interpretation? . 94 4.1.7 Why not Semanticism? . 95 4.2 Association Sequences . 98 4.2.1 Common Ground . 98 4.2.2 The Epistemological Character of Association Sequences . 100 4.2.3 Wider Contexts . 102 4.2.4 Associating with Phrases or Contents? . 103 4.3 Claims about Metaphor Again . 106 4.3.1 Metaphor-Implicature Contrast Claim . 107 4.3.2 One-step Process Claim . 109 4.3.3 The Claim that Metaphorical Meaning is Implicated . 110 4.4 Implicature Tests . 111 4.4.1 Cancellability . 111 4.4.2 Non-detachability . 113 4.4.3 Non-conventionality . 115 4.5 Special Cases . 116 4.5.1 Metaphorical Use of Definite Descriptions . 116 4.5.2 Adjectival Metaphors . 117 4.5.3 The Metaphorical Use of Proper Names . 117 4.5.4 Tautologous Metaphors . 119 4.5.5 Metaphorical Metonymies . 120 4.5.6 F is a Metaphor for G ...................... 124 4.5.7 Poetic Metaphors . 124 5 What-is-said 129 5.1 What-is-said as Exact Wording . 129 5.1.1 What-is-said and Direct Quotation . 134 5.1.2 What-is-said and Demonstratives . 137 5.1.3 Kent Bach on What-is-said . 138 5.1.4 What-is-said and Metaphor . 139 5.1.5 What-is-said and the Literal Proposition . 142 5.2 A New Conception of Semantics-Pragmatics Distinction . 143 5.2.1 Modularity Question . 146 Contents 6 6 Pragmatic Rivals 149 6.1 Relevance Theory . 149 6.1.1 Loose Talk and Metaphor . 150 6.1.2 A Worry Concerning Metaphorical Ad Hoc Concepts . 151 6.1.3 Two Problems with Relevance Theory . 152 6.2 Borg's Defence of the Autonomy of Metaphors . 155 6.3 Camp's Interactionist Theory of Metaphor . 157 6.3.1 Characterizations . 158 6.3.2 An Interactionist Theory of Metaphor . 159 6.3.3 A Problem with Negated Metaphors . 161 6.3.4 Unnecessary Complications . 163 6.3.5 Cognitive Effects of Metaphor . 168 7 On Slurring 173 7.1 What are Slurs? . 174 7.2 The Features of Slurs . 175 7.2.1 Group Expressions . 175 7.2.2 Different Uses . 176 7.2.2.1 Literal Negative Use . 176 7.2.2.2 Literal Neutral Use . 176 7.2.2.3 Literal Positive Use . 177 7.2.2.4 Figurative (Non-literal) Negative Use . 177 7.2.3 Projection and Embeddability . 178 7.2.4 Descriptivity . 179 7.3 Competing Views . 180 7.3.1 Prohibitionism . 180 7.3.2 Expressivism . 183 7.3.3 Combinatorial Externalism . 186 7.3.4 Conventional Implicature Accounts .
Recommended publications
  • Models and Metaphors: Art and Science Álvaro Balsas; Yolanda Espiña (Eds.)
    Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia ISSN 0870-5283; 2183-461X Provided for non-commercial research and education use. Not for reproduction, distribution or commercial use. Metaphor in Analytic Philosophy and Cognitive Science Mácha, Jakub Pages 2247-2286 ARTICLE DOI https://doi.org/10.17990/RPF/2019_75_4_2247 Modelos e Metáforas: Arte e Ciência Models and Metaphors: Art and Science Álvaro Balsas; Yolanda Espiña (Eds.) 75, Issue 4, 2019 ISSUE DOI 10.17990/RPF/2019_75_4_0000 Your article is protected by copyright © and all rights are held exclusively by Aletheia – Associação Científica e Cultural. This e-offprint is furnished for personal use only (for non-commercial research and education use) and shall not be self-archived in electronic repositories. Other uses, including reproduction and distribution, or selling or licensing copies, or posting to personal, institutional or third party websites are prohibited. If you wish to self-archive your article, contact us to require the written permission of the RPF's editor. For the use of any article or a part of it, the norms stipulated by the copyright law in vigour are applicable. Authors requiring further information regarding Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia archiving and manuscript policies are encouraged to visit: http://www.rpf.pt © 2019 by Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia | © 2019 by Aletheia – Associação Científica e Cultural Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia, Faculdade de Filosofia e Ciências Sociais de Braga, Praça da Faculdade, N.º 1, 4710-297 Braga (Portugal). Phone +351 253 208 080. www.rpf.pt | [email protected] Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia, 2019, Vol. 75 (4): 2247-2286. © 2019 by Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia.
    [Show full text]
  • Grice's Theory of Implicature and the Meaning of the Sentential
    Gergely Bottyán The operationality of Grice’s tests for implicature 1. Introduction In less than a decade after its first publication in 1975, Herbert Paul Grice’s paper Logic and conversation becomes one of the classic treatises of the linguistic subdiscipline now standardly referred to as pragmatics. There are at least two reasons for the paper’s success: (i) it can be regarded as the first truly serious attempt to clarify the intuitive difference between what is expressed literally in a sentence and what is merely suggested by an utterance of the same string of words, (ii) the components of the notional and inferential framework that Grice set up to characterize various kinds of utterance content are intuitively appealing (cf. Haberland & Mey 2002). The present paper has two related aims: (i) to give a comprehensive overview of Grice’s theory of implicature, and (ii) to investigate whether it is possible to test the presence of a conversational implicature on the basis of some or all of the properties that Grice attributes to this construct. It will be argued that of the six characteristics listed by Grice, only cancellability is a practical criterion. However, cancellability is not a sufficient condition of the presence of a conversational implicature. Therefore, additional criteria are needed to arrive at an adequate test. 2. Overview of Grice’s theory of implicature Most of the body of Grice 1975=1989a consists in an attempt to clarify the intuitive difference between what is expressed literally in a sentence and what is merely suggested or hinted at by an utterance of the same string of words.
    [Show full text]
  • Conversational Implicatures (And How to Spot Them)
    Conversational Implicatures (and How to Spot Them) Michael Blome-Tillmann McGill University Abstract In everyday conversations we often convey information that goes above and beyond what we strictly speaking say: exaggeration and irony are obvious examples. H.P. Grice intro- duced the technical notion of a conversational implicature in systematizing the phenom- enon of meaning one thing by saying something else. In introducing the notion, Grice drew a line between what is said, which he understood as being closely related to the conventional meaning of the words uttered, and what is conversationally implicated, which can be inferred from the fact that an utterance has been made in context. Since Grice’s seminal work, conversational implicatures have become one of the major re- search areas in pragmatics. This article introduces the notion of a conversational implica- ture, discusses some of the key issues that lie at the heart of the recent debate, and expli- cates tests that allow us to reliably distinguish between semantic entailments and conven- tional implicatures on the one hand and conversational implicatures on the other.1 Conversational Implicatures and their Cancellability In everyday conversations our utterances often convey information that goes above and beyond the contents that we explicitly assert or—as Grice puts it—beyond what is said by our utterances. Consider the following examples:2 (1) A: Can I get petrol somewhere around here? B: There’s a garage around the corner. [A can get petrol at the garage around the corner.] (2) A: Is Karl a good philosopher? B: He’s got a beautiful handwriting.
    [Show full text]
  • Relevance Implicatures
    Relevance Implicatures Robert van Rooy∗ ILLC/University of Amsterdam [email protected] Abstract According to standard pragmatics, we should account for conversational implicatures in terms of Grice’s (1967) maxims of conversation. Neo-Griceans like Atlas & Levinson (1981) and Horn (1984) seek to reduce those maxims to the so-called Q and I-principles. In this paper I want to argue that (i) there are major problems for reducing Gricean pragmatics to these two principles, and (ii) in fact, we can better account for implicatures by means of an exhaustivity operator defined in terms of a relevance-based ordering relation. 1 Introduction In most circumstances we infer from the fact that the (a) sentences of the following examples are uttered that the (b) sentences are true: (1) a. John ate some of the cookies. b. John didn’t eat all of the cookies (2) a. John is coming or Mary is going. b. John is coming or Mary is going, but not both. (3) a. John is walking, if Mary is talking. b. John is walking if and only if Mary is talking. ∗This note reports on work in progress on the use of relevance for the semantic analysis of natural language. Parts of this paper was presented at the second workshop on Optimality Theoretic Semantics at OTS in Utrecht (2000) and at the Formal Pragmatics conference in Berlin (2001). I would like to thank the participants of those events for their comments and suggestions. I would also like to thank the anonymous reviewers, Reinhard Blutner and expecially Katrin Schulz.
    [Show full text]
  • Types of Implicature in Informal Conversations Used by the English Education Study Program Students
    Rahayu, Types Of Implicature In Informal… TYPES OF IMPLICATURE IN INFORMAL CONVERSATIONS USED BY THE ENGLISH EDUCATION STUDY PROGRAM STUDENTS Endry Sri Rahayu Prof.Safnil M.A,Ph.D. University of Bengkulu W.R. Supratman, Kd. Limun 38371A. Bengkulu, Indonesia Email : [email protected] Email : [email protected] Abstract: Implicature was refers to implied meaning in utterance that can be understood by indirectly expression. In informal conversation was occurred the hidden meaning of what actually said by the speakers. This study was investigated the types of implicature in informal conversations used by the English education study program students. The study was aimed to analyze the types of implicature and how the implicature is carried out in the informal conversations. The method of study was a descriptive qualitative method. The subjects of this study were 25 students of English study program who have informal conversation. The students’ conversation was transcribed and analyzed by using checklist instrument. The results was shown that 1) there were three types of implicature found in the informal conversations; conventional implicature, generalized conversational implicature and particularized conversational implicature, and 2) the implicature is carried out in the informal conversations by the used of generalized conversational implicature and particularized conversational implicature. Moreover, a conclusion is students in the informal conversation have potentially implicature that indicates that their utterance has implied meaning. The suggestions, the study about implicature should be conducted in different area such as movie, drama or others, to give enrichment information in the Pragmatics study. Keywords: Implicature Types, Informal Conversations, English Education Study Program Students. Abstrak: Implikatur mengacu pada makna tersirat pada suatu ujaran yang dapat dipahami dari ekspresi tidak langsung.
    [Show full text]
  • Lecture 7: Semantics and Pragmatics. Entailments, Presuppositions, Conversational and Conventional Implicatures. Grice's
    Formal Semantics, Lecture 7 Formal Semantics, Lecture 7 B. H. Partee, RGGU April 1, 2004 p. 1 B. H. Partee, RGGU April 1, 2004 p. 2 Lecture 7: Semantics and Pragmatics. Entailments, presuppositions, (intentionally or unintentionally) much more than what is literally said by the words of her conversational and conventional implicatures. Grice’s conversational sentence. maxims. An example: (1) A: How is C getting along in his new job at the bank? 1. Grice’s Conversational Implicatures. .................................................................................................................1 B: Oh, quite well, I think; he likes his colleagues, and he hasn’t been to prison yet. 1.1. Motivation. Questions about the meanings of logical words.......................................................................1 1.2. Truth-conditional content (semantics) vs. Conversational Implicatures (pragmatics).................................2 What B implied, suggested, or meant is distinct from what B said. All B said was that C had 1.3. Conversational maxims. (“Gricean maxims”.) ............................................................................................3 not been to prison yet. 1.4. Generating implicatures. General principles. Examples............................................................................4 1.4.1. Characterization of conversational implicature. .............................................................................4 1.4.2. More Examples...............................................................................................................................4
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Conversational Maxims, Implicature and Presupposition in the Creation of Humour: an Analysis of Woody Allen’S Anything Else
    MASTER IN ENGLISH LANGUAGE AND LINGUISTICS MASTER DISSERTATION THE ROLE OF CONVERSATIONAL MAXIMS, IMPLICATURE AND PRESUPPOSITION IN THE CREATION OF HUMOUR: AN ANALYSIS OF WOODY ALLEN’S ANYTHING ELSE Department of English Philology I, UCM STUDENT: Ramiro Nieto Álvaro TUTOR: Dr. Marta Begoña Carretero Lapeyre Septiembre de 2011 1 TABLE OF CONTENTS ABSTRACT........................................................................................................................4 1. Introduction.....................................................................................................................5 1.1 Framework and outline................................................................................................5 1.2. Research hypothesis and aim of the study..................................................................6 1.3. Overview of the method.............................................................................................7 1.4. Description of the data................................................................................................8 1.4.1. Plot and characters........................................................................................9 1.4.2. Film poster analysis.........................................................................................10 1.5. Context and “double level” …......………………………………………………...15 2. Humour in Woody Allen’s Anything Else..............................................................17 2.1 What is humour?........................................................................................................17
    [Show full text]
  • 1 - Arises from the Sense of an Utterance and Not from Its Form
    IMPLICATURE AND SEMANTIC CHANGE Kate Kearns University of Canterbury September 2000 (To appear under the title 'Implicature and language change' in Jef Verschueren, Jan-Ola Östman, Jan Blommaert & Chris Bulcaen eds. Handbook of Pragmatics 2000, John Benjamins.) 1. INTRODUCTION The basic components of semantic change are the two processes represented in (1). (1) a. Fa > Fab Form F with sense a acquires an additional sense b b. Fab > Fb Form F with senses a and b loses sense a Process (b) must operate on a polysemous form. If we assume that polysemy must arise by process (a), process (b) is dependent on process (a), but not vice versa. Accordingly, the process of sense gain (as in (a)) is the sine qua non of semantic change. This paper reviews proposals that in some semantic changes, implicature is the mechanism by which sense b initially comes to be associated with Fa. The establishment of b as a sense of F is attributed to conventionalization of the implicature. The notion of implicature is not precisely defined, and may be compared to a concept with prototypical and peripheral instances. A prototypical implicature is a particularized conversational implicature as first proposed by Grice (1975), in which the implicature is intended by the speaker, dependent on the particular context of utterance, and calculated by identifiable inferential steps, including certain communicative principles as premisses -- in Grice's theory, the Cooperative Principle and its constitutive maxims, most importantly the maxims of Quantity and Relation. (Implicatures calculated under Quantity and Relation are discussed in more detail below.) Implicatures of this kind, though differently classified, remain important in post-Gricean and Neo-Gricean theories of communication.
    [Show full text]
  • Linguistics 103 Language Structure and Verbal Art Entailment And
    Linguistics 103 Language Structure and Verbal Art Entailment and Presupposition vs. Implicature Entailment A sentence S entails a proposition P if P is true whenever S is true. (1) a. Hilda ate apples and bananas. entails Hilda ate apples. because, if Hilda ate apples and bananas, then, necessary, Hilda ate apples = if Hild ate apples and bananas, then it cannot be that Hilda did not eat apples. b. All cows eat grass and Bossie is a cow. entails Bossie eats grass. because, if all cows eat grass and Bossie is a cow, then, necessarily, Bossie eats grass = if all cows eat grass and Bossie is a cow, then it cannot be that Bossie does not eat grass. Presupposition A sentence S presupposes a proposition P if the truth of P is assumed by the speaker in order for S to be appropriate in a discourse. (2) a. Why did you steal the money? presupposes You stole the money. a.′ You did not steal the money. # Why did you steal the money? # means ‘bizarre’ or ‘inappropriate’ b. Hortense burst into tears again. presupposes Hortense burst into tears once before. b.′ Hortense has never burst into tears. # Hortense burst into tears again. c. The King of France is bald presupposes There is a King of France. There is no King of France. # The King of France is bald. d. Stop bothering me! presupposes You are bothering me. You are not bothering me. # Stop bothering me! Presuppositions can exist with all sorts of utterance types (questions, commands, statements, performatives) but entailments exist only with utterances that express propositions.
    [Show full text]
  • Conversational Implicatures in English Dialogue: Annotated Dataset
    Conversational implicatures in English dialogue: Annotated dataset Elizabeth Jasmi George*‑ , Radhika Mamidi LTRC, International Institute of Information Technology, Gachibowli, Hyderabad 500 032, Telangana, India Abstract Human dialogue often contains utterances having meanings entirely different from the sentences used and are clearly understood by the interlocutors. But in human-computer interactions, the machine fails to understand the implicated meaning unless it is trained with a dataset containing the implicated meaning of an utterance along with the utterance and the context in which it is uttered. In linguistic terms, conversational implicatures are the meanings of the speaker’s utterance that are not part of what is explicitly said. In this paper, we introduce a dataset of dialogue snippets with three constituents, which are the context, the utterance, and the implicated meanings. These implicated meanings are the conversational implicatures. The utterances are collected by transcribing from listening comprehension sections of English tests like TOEFL (Test of English as a Foreign Language) as well as scraping dialogues from movie scripts available on IMSDb (Internet Movie Script Database). The utterances are manually annotated with implicatures. Keywords: Conversational implicature ; Pragmatics ; Dialogue ; Conversational implicature dataset ; Crowd-sourcing ; 1. Introduction A conversation in the animation movie ‘Anastasia’ goes like this, (1) ANYA: Is this where I get travelling papers? CLERK: It would be if we let you travel, which we don’t so it isn’t. For a simple polar question asked by the character ANYA, the complex response by the CLERK allows a human reader to conclude on many implicatures with a ‘yes’ or a ‘no’ as answers to that polar question while reading that dialogue in the movie script.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatics Implicature Speech Acts Illocutionary Acts Classified
    Pragmatics Pragmatics is the study of the way language is used. It is the study not of sentences, but of utterances: sentences (complete and incomplete) spoken by particular people in particular circumstances. Observations about how language is used: 1. sentences can imply information that is not stated explicitly 2. we don't just say things, we do things by uttering sentences 3. who is participating can determine the effect of what is said 4. a correct answer to a question may not be appropriate 5. speakers don't always mean what they say Implicature "Conversational maxims": Paul Grice Maxim of Quantity Maxim of Quality Maxim of Relation (Maxim of Relevance) Maxim of Manner Speech Acts Locutionary Act Illocutionary Act Perlocutionary Effect Illocutionary Acts Classified Representatives Directives Questions Commissives Expressives Declarations Handout for Psy 598-02, summer 2001 Packer Pragmatics 2 Problems with this classification: There are several problems with this classification 1. Nofsinger 2. The definitions of the speech act families are given in very mentalist terms. "Expressives" are the clearest example of this. Felicity Conditions Preparatory Conditions Sincerity Conditions Essential Condition Propositional Content Condition Explicit and Nonexplicit Speech Acts performative verbs Direct and Indirect Speech Acts Illocutionary Act Syntactic Form Representative Declarative Commissive Declarative Declaration?? Declarative Directive Imperative Yes-No Question Yes-No Interrogative Wh-Question Wh-Interrogative Expressive Exclamatory Expressed and Implied Speech Acts Literal and Nonliteral Speech Acts A speeaker does not always mean what they say. More accurately, a speech act is not always what it seems to be on a literal interpretation of the words.
    [Show full text]
  • Outline of Relevance Theory'
    Links & Letters 1, 1994 85-106 Outline of relevance theory' Deirdre Wilson*, Dan Sperber** *Department of Linguistics University College London **CNRS and CREA Ecole Polytechnique, Paris ABSTRACT In this paper, we outline a relevance-based approach to pragmatics, the theory of utterance interpretation. The main aim of a pragmatic theory is to explain how the hearer recognises the intended interpretation of an utterance. We argue that this interpretation is not decoded but inferred, by a non-demonstrative inference process in which considerations of relevance play a central role. We offer a definition of relevance, and argue that every utterance creates an expectation of relevance in the hearer, with the preferred interpretation being the one that best satisfies that expectation of relevance. The theory is illustrated by applying it to a wide range of examples. 1. Introduction Pragmatics is the study of the general cognitive principles and abilities involved in utterance interpretation, and of their cognitive effects. In construct-ing an explanatory pragmatic theory, a variety of specific problems must be solved. Utterances may be ambiguous or referentiall~ambivalent, as in ( 1 ) : (1) The football team gathered round their coach. Pragmatic theory should explain how the hearer of caracter (1) decides which football tearn the speaker has in mind, and whether 'coach' was intended to mean bus or games teacher. Utterances have not only explicit content but implicit import, as in (2): (2) a. Peter: 1s George a good sailor? b. Mary: ALL the Te English are good sailors. Pragmatic theory should explain how (2b) is understood as implying that George is a good sailor.
    [Show full text]