Causal V. Positivist Theories of Scientific Explanation : a Defense of the Causal Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Causal V. Positivist Theories of Scientific Explanation : a Defense of the Causal Theory University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1996 Causal v. positivist theories of scientific explanation : a defense of the causal theory. Douglas H. Rice University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Rice, Douglas H., "Causal v. positivist theories of scientific explanation : a defense of the causal theory." (1996). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2291. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2291 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CAUSAL V. POSITIVIST THEORIES OF SCIENTIFIC EXPLANATION: A DEFENSE OF THE CAUSAL THEORY A Dissertation Presented by DOUGLAS H. RICE Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY September 1996 DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY © Copyright by Douglas Hans Rice 1996 All Rights Reserved. CAUSAL V. POSITIVIST THEORIES OF SCIENTIFIC EXPLANATION: A DEFENSE OF THE CAUSAL THEORY A Dissertation Presented by DOUGLAS H. RICE Approved as to style and content by: /u_ y Robert J. Ackermann, Chair ruce Aune, Member 0 If) * 1 Gareth Matthews, Member Stan Rachootin, Member John Robison, Department Head Philosophy Department ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This dissertation could not have been written without the support of many people and institutions. Above all, I am thankful for the love of my family and friends—especially Geraldine, Wiley, Phil, Steve, Cindy, Sioux, Regine, George, and Dan —who encouraged me when they could, and tolerated me when my dissertational struggles were seemingly endless and insufferable. I would also like to express my gratitude to Professors Martha Nussbaum, Cynthia Freeland, Bruce Aune, Vere Chappell, Leonard Ehrlich, Gareth Matthews, Fred Feldman, Bob Wolff, and Bob Ackermann. I learned much from these excellent teachers, and each of them provided me, in different ways and at different times in my career as a philosophy student, with inspiration and encouragement that I appreciate greatly. The Philosophy Department at the University of Massachusetts Amherst supported me generously with teaching assistantships during my tenure as a doctoral candidate. In addition, the Freiburg/Baden-Wuerttemberg Exchange Program at the University of Massachusetts and the German Academic Exchange Service (DAAD) granted me two years of study in Germany unencumbered by teaching duties or financial obligations. It is safe to opportunity, this dissertation would not be finished. say that if I had not been granted this Beyond that, living in Germany was a wonderful experience, and I am grateful to these to institutions for facilitating the journey. Finally, Professor Guenther Patzig was generous hospitality. me during my year at the University of Goettingen, and I thank him for his IV n ABSTRACT CAUSAL V. POSITIVIST THEORIES OF SCIENTIFIC EXPLANATION: A DEFENSE OF THE CAUSAL THEORY SEPTEMBER 1996 DOUGLAS H. RICE, A.B., HARVARD UNIVERSITY M.A., UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS AMHERST Ph.D., UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS AMHERST Directed by: Professor Robert J. Ackerman Three fundamental claims are defended in this dissertation. First, the influence of Hume's epistemological program and his skepticism with respect to causal knowledge have hindered the development of an adequate theory of scientific explanation. Second, Hume's conception of causal knowledge is outdated, and knowledge of causation should be relieved of the special epistemological burden placed on it by Hume's followers. Finally, once relieved of this Humean epistemological burden, the causal theory of scientific explanation is superior to alternatives lying in the tradition of Humean positivism. Humean positivism places severe constraints on theories of scientific explanation, and its influence on extant theories is reviewed. Recent positivist theories of scientific explanation are discussed critically, and are shown to suffer serious difficulties. Particular to attention is paid to recent pragmatic theories (van Fraassen's and Sintonen's) and Kitcher's unificationist theory. examination of The causal theory of scientific explanation is developed through an theories, theories of causation. Traditional views (e.g., the regularity view), recent statistical that and Salmon's (1984) theory of causation are rejected in favor of Cartwright's thesis essential features of scientific causal laws are best understood as capacity ascriptions. The causal capacities and explanations are then outlined: most prominent are the ascription of v the description of causal interactions. The philosophical benefits of the causal theory are also summarized. Common objections to causal theories of explanation are treated. Of central importance is Hume's skeptical argument. Once Hume's conception of causal knowledge is modernized, however, his arguments yield no skepticism particular to the knowledge of causation: causal knowledge is as defensible as are more respectable types of empirical knowledge. Other important objections are also reviewed. Finally, historical studies of two well-known explanatory controversies—the Jensen- Lewontin debate concerning the heritability of IQ, and a dispute about the nature of cosmic radiation—are presented. Positivist theories of scientific explanation can account for neither the origin nor the manner of resolution of these controversies. In contrast, the causal theory of explanation is shown to illuminate the controversies successfully. This success offers additional evidence in favor of the causal theory of scientific explanation. * VI TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS iv ABSTRACT CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION ! 1.1 Explanation and Understanding 1 1.2 Some Philosophical Problems of Explanation 2 1 .3 The Forefathers of Modern Theories of Explanation: Aristotle and Hume 4 1 .4 Two Approaches to the Theory of Explanation 5 1.5 Summary of Chapters 10 2. THE HUMEAN POSITIVIST TRADITION 12 2.1 Hume's Influence and the Positivist Tradition 12 2.2 Hume's Critical Philosophy: The Analysis of Causal Knowledge 13 2.3 Humean Positivism and the Philosophy of Scientific Explanation 13 2.4 Logical Positivism 17 2.5 The Impact of Logical Positivism's Demise on the Philosophy of Science 20 3. POSITIVIST APPROACHES TO SCIENTIFIC EXPLANATION 23 3.1 Neo-Positivist Theories of Scientific Explanation 23 3.1.1 The Covering-Law Model of Explanation 23 3.1.2 Kitcher's Unification Theory of Explanation 35 3. 1.2.1 Explanatory Patterns 38 3. 1.2. 2 Unifying Power 42 3. 1.2. 3 Evaluation of Kitcher's Theory 46 3.2 Paleo-Positivist Theories of Scientific Explanation 55 3.2.1 The Pragmatics of Explanation: Scriven's Contributions 55 3.2.2 The Pragmatics of Explanation: Van Fraassen's Theory of Why-Questions 60 Pragmatics of 3.2.2. 1 Bengt Hannson: The Necessity of a Explanation 6"! 63 3. 2. 2. 2 Van Fraassen's Theory of Why-Questions of Why-Questions 65 3. 2. 2. 3 Evaluation of Van Fraassen's Theory vii 3.2.3 Further Developments in the Pragmatics of Explanation: Explanation and Epistemic Context (Gardentors, Sintonen) 69 3.2.3. 1 Gardenfors: The Dynamic Epistemic Context of Explanation 71 3. 2. 3. 2 Sintonen's Theory of Explanatory Commitment 75 3. 2. 3. 3 Evaluation of Sintonen's Account 80 4. THE CAUSAL THEORY OF SCIENTIFIC EXPLANATION 82 4.1 What is a Cause? 83 4.1.1 Traditional Views of Causation 84 4. 1.1.1 Causation As Regularity 84 4. 1.1. 2 Probabilistic Theories of Causation 90 4. 1.1. 3 The Counterfactual View 99 4.1.2 Salmon's Theory of Causation (1 984) 101 4.1.3 Dowe's (1 992) and Salmon's (1 994) Theory of Causation 107 4.2 Causal Knowledge: Causal Capacities and Interactions 110 4.2.1 The Nature of Causal Capacities and Their Ascription 113 4.2.2 Causes As the Operation of Capacities v. Causes As Regularities 117 4.3 The Causal Theory of Explanation 121 4.4 Theory, Explanation, and Causal Knowledge 125 4.5 A Summary of the Benefits of the Causal Theory of Scientific Explanation 127 5. OBJECTIONS TO THE CAUSAL THEORY OF SCIENTIFIC EXPLANATION 131 5.1 The Importance of Causes in Science 132 5.2 Dispositions 134 5.3 Knowledge of Causal Capacities and Interactions 140 5.4 The Grounds of Hume's Skepticism 140 5.5 The Perception of Causation 147 5.6 Michotte's Experiments 13° 5.7 Hume's Argument Again 154 5.8 More Epistemological Worries 156 5.9 Epistemology and Science 157 5.10 Testing (Bootstrapping) Causal Claims 158 I 66 5.11 Non-Causal Explanations 5.11.1 Laws of Coexistence ^7 167 5.11.2 Brody's Essential-Property Explanations 170 5.11.3 Kim's Non-Causal Connections viii 5.11.4 Other Non-Causal Laws 173 5.11.5 Identity Explanations -| 75 6. EXPLANATORY CONTROVERSIES AND THEIR RESOLUTION 177 6.1 Explanatory Controversy in Science 1 77 6.2 First Case Study: Controversies over the Explanation of Differential IQ-Test Performance 181 6.2.1 Jensen's Argument 183 6.2.2 Heritabi I ity 185 6.2.3 Lewontin's Criticism 187 6.2.4 Jensen's Reply 190 6.2.5 Lewontin Again 192 6.3 Second Case Study: Controversies over the Nature of Cosmic Radiation 1 93 6.3.1 Cosmic Radiation: Photons or Particles? 195 6.3.2 Crisis and Resolution of the Explanatory Controversy 199 6.4 A Comparison of the Two Case Studies 203 6.5 The Covering-Law Model and Explanatory Controversy in the History of Science 203 6.6 Pragmatic Theories of Explanation and Explanatory Controversy in the History of Science 207 6.7 Kitcher's Unification Theory and Explanatory Controversy in the History of Science 209 6.8 Explanatory Controversy and the Causal Theory of Explanation 217 NOTES 220 BIBLIOGRAPHY 248 IX CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION 1.1 Explanation and Understanding Science begins with the desire to understand.
Recommended publications
  • Theory and Reality
    an introduction to the philosophy of science ........................................................... SCIENCE AND ITS CONCEPTUAL FOUNDATIONS A SERIES EDITED BY DAVID L. HULL THEORY AND REALITY ........................................................... Peter Godfrey-Smith is associate professor of philosophy and of his­ tory and philosophy of science at Stanford University. He is the author PETER GODFREY-SMITH of Complexity and the Function ofMind in Nature. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago 60637 The University of Chicago Press, Ltd., London © 2003 by The University of Chicago All rights reserved. Published 2003 Printed in the United States of America 12 II 100908 45 ISBN: 0-226-30062-5 (cloth) ISBN: 0-226-30063-3 (paper) Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Godfrey-Smith, Peter. Theory and reality: an introduction to the philosophy of science I Peter Godfrey-Smith. p. cm. - (Science and its conceptual foundations) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 0-226-30062-5 (alk. paper) - ISBN 0-226-30063-3 (pbk. : alk. The University of Chicago Press / Chicago and London paper) I. Science-Philosophy. I. Title. II. Series. QI75 .G596 2003 501-dc2I 2002155305 @ The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of the American National Standard for Information Sciences-Perma­ nence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI Z39.48-1992. 56 Chapter Three Later (especially in chapter 14) I will return to these problems. But in the next chapter we will look at a philosophy that gets a good part of its motivation from the frustrations discussed in this chapter. Further Reading 4...................................................................................... Once again, Hempel's Aspects ofScientific Explanation (1965) is a key source, con­ Popper: Conjecture and Refutation taining a long (and exhausting) chapter on confirmation.
    [Show full text]
  • Positivism and the 'New Archaeology'
    2 Positivism and the 'new archaeology' 'Recipes for the Good Society used to run, in caricature, something like this - (1) Take about 2,000 hom. sap., dissect each into essence and accidents and discard the accidents. (2) Place essences in a large casserole, add socialising syrup and stew until conflict disappears. (3) Serve with a pinch of salt.' (Hollis 1977, p. 1) 'The wish to establish a natural science of society . probably remains, in the English speaking world at least, the dominant standpoint today . But those who still wait for a Newton are not only waiting for a train that won't arrive, they're in the wrong station altogether.' (Giddens 1976, p. 13) Introduction How should archaeologists come to have knowledge of the past? What does this knowl- edge involve? What constitutes an explanation of what archaeologists find? This chapter considers the answer to these questions accepted by the 'new' archaeology; it considers epistemological issues raised by a study of the past in the archaeological literature post- dating 1960. New archaeology has embraced explicitly and implicitly a positivist model of how to explain the past and we examine the treatment of the social world as an exten- sion of the natural, the reduction of practice lo behaviour, the separation of'reality', the facts, from concepts and theories. We criticize testing, validation and the refutation of theory as a way of connecting theory and the facts, emphasizing all observation as theory-laden. The new archaeology polemically opposed itself to traditional 'normative' archaeology as a social science and we begin the chapter with a consideration of this change and why it took place.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Thoughts About Natural Law
    Some Thoughts About Natural Law Phflip E. Johnsont My first task is to define the subject. When I use the term "natural" law, I am distinguishing the category from other kinds of law such as positive law, divine law, or scientific law. When we discuss positive law, we look to materials like legislation, judicial opinions, and scholarly anal- ysis of these materials. If we speak of divine law, we ask if there are any knowable commands from God. If we look for scientific law, we conduct experiments, or make observations and calculations, in order to come to objectively verifiable knowledge about the material world. Natural law-as I will be using the term in this essay-refers to a method that we employ to judge what the principles of individual moral- ity or positive law ought to be. The natural law philosopher aspires to make these judgments on the basis of reason and human nature without invoking divine revelation or prophetic inspiration. Natural law so defined is a category much broader than any particular theory of natural law. One can believe in the existence of natural law without agreeing with the particular systems of natural law advocates like Aristotle or Aquinas. I am describing a way of thinking, not a particular theory. In the broad sense in which I am using the term, therefore, anyone who attempts to found concepts of justice upon reason and human nature engages in natural law philosophy. Contemporary philosophical systems based on feminism, wealth maximization, neutral conversation, liberal equality, or libertarianism are natural law philosophies.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Explanation
    Scientific Explanation Michael Strevens For the Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, second edition The three cardinal aims of science are prediction, control, and expla- nation; but the greatest of these is explanation. Also the most inscrutable: prediction aims at truth, and control at happiness, and insofar as we have some independent grasp of these notions, we can evaluate science’s strate- gies of prediction and control from the outside. Explanation, by contrast, aims at scientific understanding, a good intrinsic to science and therefore something that it seems we can only look to science itself to explicate. Philosophers have wondered whether science might be better off aban- doning the pursuit of explanation. Duhem (1954), among others, argued that explanatory knowledge would have to be a kind of knowledge so ex- alted as to be forever beyond the reach of ordinary scientific inquiry: it would have to be knowledge of the essential natures of things, something that neo-Kantians, empiricists, and practical men of science could all agree was neither possible nor perhaps even desirable. Everything changed when Hempel formulated his dn account of ex- planation. In accordance with the observation above, that our only clue to the nature of explanatory knowledge is science’s own explanatory prac- tice, Hempel proposed simply to describe what kind of things scientists ten- dered when they claimed to have an explanation, without asking whether such things were capable of providing “true understanding”. Since Hempel, the philosophy of scientific explanation has proceeded in this humble vein, 1 seeming more like a sociology of scientific practice than an inquiry into a set of transcendent norms.
    [Show full text]
  • Meta-Metaphysics on Metaphysical Equivalence, Primitiveness, and Theory Choice
    J. Benovsky Meta-metaphysics On Metaphysical Equivalence, Primitiveness, and Theory Choice Series: Synthese Library, Vol. 374 ▶ Contains original research in analytic metaphysics and meta- metaphysics ▶ Offers a detailed and innovative discussion of metaphysical equivalence ▶ Explores the role of aesthetic properties of metaphysical theories from an original angle Metaphysical theories are beautiful. At the end of this book, Jiri Benovsky defends the view that metaphysical theories possess aesthetic properties and that these play a crucial role when it comes to theory evaluation and theory choice. Before we get there, the philosophical path the author proposes to follow starts with three discussions 1st ed. 2016, XI, 135 p. 20 illus. of metaphysical equivalence. Benovsky argues that there are cases of metaphysical equivalence, cases of partial metaphysical equivalence, as well as interesting cases of theories that are not equivalent. Thus, claims of metaphysical equivalence can only be Printed book raised locally. The slogan is: the best way to do meta-metaphysics is to do first-level Hardcover metaphysics.To do this work, Benovsky focuses on the nature of primitives and on the ISBN 978-3-319-25332-9 role they play in each of the theories involved. He emphasizes the utmost importance of primitives in the construction of metaphysical theories and in the subsequent evaluation ▶ 89,99 € | £79.99 of them. He then raises the simple but complicated question: how to make a choice ▶ *96,29 € (D) | 98,99 € (A) | CHF 106.50 between competing metaphysical theories? If two theories are equivalent, then perhaps we do not need to make a choice. But what about all the other cases of non-equivalent "equally good" theories? Benovsky uses some of the theories discussed in the first part of the book as examples and examines some traditional meta-theoretical criteria for theory choice (various kinds of simplicity, compatibility with physics, compatibility with intuitions, explanatory power, internal consistency,...) only to show that they do not allow us to make a choice.
    [Show full text]
  • Two Concepts of Law of Nature
    Prolegomena 12 (2) 2013: 413–442 Two Concepts of Law of Nature BRENDAN SHEA Winona State University, 528 Maceman St. #312, Winona, MN, 59987, USA [email protected] ORIGINAL SCIENTIFIC ARTICLE / RECEIVED: 04–12–12 ACCEPTED: 23–06–13 ABSTRACT: I argue that there are at least two concepts of law of nature worthy of philosophical interest: strong law and weak law . Strong laws are the laws in- vestigated by fundamental physics, while weak laws feature prominently in the “special sciences” and in a variety of non-scientific contexts. In the first section, I clarify my methodology, which has to do with arguing about concepts. In the next section, I offer a detailed description of strong laws, which I claim satisfy four criteria: (1) If it is a strong law that L then it also true that L; (2) strong laws would continue to be true, were the world to be different in some physically possible way; (3) strong laws do not depend on context or human interest; (4) strong laws feature in scientific explanations but cannot be scientifically explained. I then spell out some philosophical consequences: (1) is incompatible with Cartwright’s contention that “laws lie” (2) with Lewis’s “best-system” account of laws, and (3) with contextualism about laws. In the final section, I argue that weak laws are distinguished by (approximately) meeting some but not all of these criteria. I provide a preliminary account of the scientific value of weak laws, and argue that they cannot plausibly be understood as ceteris paribus laws. KEY WORDS: Contextualism, counterfactuals, David Lewis, laws of nature, Nancy Cartwright, physical necessity.
    [Show full text]
  • A Difference-Making Account of Causation1
    A difference-making account of causation1 Wolfgang Pietsch2, Munich Center for Technology in Society, Technische Universität München, Arcisstr. 21, 80333 München, Germany A difference-making account of causality is proposed that is based on a counterfactual definition, but differs from traditional counterfactual approaches to causation in a number of crucial respects: (i) it introduces a notion of causal irrelevance; (ii) it evaluates the truth-value of counterfactual statements in terms of difference-making; (iii) it renders causal statements background-dependent. On the basis of the fundamental notions ‘causal relevance’ and ‘causal irrelevance’, further causal concepts are defined including causal factors, alternative causes, and importantly inus-conditions. Problems and advantages of the proposed account are discussed. Finally, it is shown how the account can shed new light on three classic problems in epistemology, the problem of induction, the logic of analogy, and the framing of eliminative induction. 1. Introduction ......................................................................................................................................................... 2 2. The difference-making account ........................................................................................................................... 3 2a. Causal relevance and causal irrelevance ....................................................................................................... 4 2b. A difference-making account of causal counterfactuals
    [Show full text]
  • Ast#: ___Science Knowledge Study Guide Physical
    Name: ______________________________ Pd: ___ Ast#: _____ Science Knowledge Study Guide Physical Science Honors Provide a short response to the following prompts. 1. Describe how scientific knowledge is affected by new evidence (if the new evidence does NOT support the current understanding). Scientific knowledge grows and changes as new evidence is uncovered. 2. What is scientific knowledge built from? (list 3 things) Continuous testing and observation Debate (argumentation) All contribute to the EMPIRICAL EVIDENCE Confirmation (repetition & replication) 3. Why is it important that we use phrases such as “the results suggest…” or “the evidence supports…” rather than using words such as “prove” or “proof”? Using words such as “prove” violate the tentative nature of science. They imply that scientific knowledge is concrete and unchanging. However, scientific knowledge must remain open to change. 4. Under what circumstances will a scientific theory become a law? Explain. A scientific theory will NEVER become a scientific law; it cannot, nor is it supposed to. A scientific theory and a scientific law are two different things with different purposes (an apple will never become an orange). 5. Why are scientific theories rarely discarded (completely abandoned), even when new evidence doesn’t fit within the current theory? Scientific theories are rarely completely discarded because they are heavily-tested and well-supported explanations. It is rare that new evidence completely invalidates a theory; rather, it is more likely that the theory can be “tweaked” or changed slightly to accommodate the new evidence. 6. What represents the BEST explanation that science can offer? Scientific theories represent the best explanations science has to offer.
    [Show full text]
  • Sacred Rhetorical Invention in the String Theory Movement
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Communication Studies Theses, Dissertations, and Student Research Communication Studies, Department of Spring 4-12-2011 Secular Salvation: Sacred Rhetorical Invention in the String Theory Movement Brent Yergensen University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/commstuddiss Part of the Speech and Rhetorical Studies Commons Yergensen, Brent, "Secular Salvation: Sacred Rhetorical Invention in the String Theory Movement" (2011). Communication Studies Theses, Dissertations, and Student Research. 6. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/commstuddiss/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Communication Studies, Department of at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Communication Studies Theses, Dissertations, and Student Research by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. SECULAR SALVATION: SACRED RHETORICAL INVENTION IN THE STRING THEORY MOVEMENT by Brent Yergensen A DISSERTATION Presented to the Faculty of The Graduate College at the University of Nebraska In Partial Fulfillment of Requirements For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Major: Communication Studies Under the Supervision of Dr. Ronald Lee Lincoln, Nebraska April, 2011 ii SECULAR SALVATION: SACRED RHETORICAL INVENTION IN THE STRING THEORY MOVEMENT Brent Yergensen, Ph.D. University of Nebraska, 2011 Advisor: Ronald Lee String theory is argued by its proponents to be the Theory of Everything. It achieves this status in physics because it provides unification for contradictory laws of physics, namely quantum mechanics and general relativity. While based on advanced theoretical mathematics, its public discourse is growing in prevalence and its rhetorical power is leading to a scientific revolution, even among the public.
    [Show full text]
  • What Scientific Theories Could Not Be Author(S): Hans Halvorson Reviewed Work(S): Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol
    What Scientific Theories Could Not Be Author(s): Hans Halvorson Reviewed work(s): Source: Philosophy of Science, Vol. 79, No. 2 (April 2012), pp. 183-206 Published by: The University of Chicago Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/664745 . Accessed: 03/12/2012 10:32 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press and Philosophy of Science Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Philosophy of Science. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.52.67 on Mon, 3 Dec 2012 10:32:52 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions What Scientific Theories Could Not Be* Hans Halvorson†‡ According to the semantic view of scientific theories, theories are classes of models. I show that this view—if taken literally—leads to absurdities. In particular, this view equates theories that are distinct, and it distinguishes theories that are equivalent. Furthermore, the semantic view lacks the resources to explicate interesting theoretical relations, such as embeddability of one theory into another.
    [Show full text]
  • A Visual Analytics Approach for Exploratory Causal Analysis: Exploration, Validation, and Applications
    A Visual Analytics Approach for Exploratory Causal Analysis: Exploration, Validation, and Applications Xiao Xie, Fan Du, and Yingcai Wu Fig. 1. The user interface of Causality Explorer demonstrated with a real-world audiology dataset that consists of 200 rows and 24 dimensions [18]. (a) A scalable causal graph layout that can handle high-dimensional data. (b) Histograms of all dimensions for comparative analyses of the distributions. (c) Clicking on a histogram will display the detailed data in the table view. (b) and (c) are coordinated to support what-if analyses. In the causal graph, each node is represented by a pie chart (d) and the causal direction (e) is from the upper node (cause) to the lower node (result). The thickness of a link encodes the uncertainty (f). Nodes without descendants are placed on the left side of each layer to improve readability (g). Users can double-click on a node to show its causality subgraph (h). Abstract—Using causal relations to guide decision making has become an essential analytical task across various domains, from marketing and medicine to education and social science. While powerful statistical models have been developed for inferring causal relations from data, domain practitioners still lack effective visual interface for interpreting the causal relations and applying them in their decision-making process. Through interview studies with domain experts, we characterize their current decision-making workflows, challenges, and needs. Through an iterative design process, we developed a visualization tool that allows analysts to explore, validate, arXiv:2009.02458v1 [cs.HC] 5 Sep 2020 and apply causal relations in real-world decision-making scenarios.
    [Show full text]
  • Causal Inference for Process Understanding in Earth Sciences
    Causal inference for process understanding in Earth sciences Adam Massmann,* Pierre Gentine, Jakob Runge May 4, 2021 Abstract There is growing interest in the study of causal methods in the Earth sciences. However, most applications have focused on causal discovery, i.e. inferring the causal relationships and causal structure from data. This paper instead examines causality through the lens of causal inference and how expert-defined causal graphs, a fundamental from causal theory, can be used to clarify assumptions, identify tractable problems, and aid interpretation of results and their causality in Earth science research. We apply causal theory to generic graphs of the Earth sys- tem to identify where causal inference may be most tractable and useful to address problems in Earth science, and avoid potentially incorrect conclusions. Specifically, causal inference may be useful when: (1) the effect of interest is only causally affected by the observed por- tion of the state space; or: (2) the cause of interest can be assumed to be independent of the evolution of the system’s state; or: (3) the state space of the system is reconstructable from lagged observations of the system. However, we also highlight through examples that causal graphs can be used to explicitly define and communicate assumptions and hypotheses, and help to structure analyses, even if causal inference is ultimately challenging given the data availability, limitations and uncertainties. Note: We will update this manuscript as our understanding of causality’s role in Earth sci- ence research evolves. Comments, feedback, and edits are enthusiastically encouraged, and we arXiv:2105.00912v1 [physics.ao-ph] 3 May 2021 will add acknowledgments and/or coauthors as we receive community contributions.
    [Show full text]