Ralkowski, Mark A. 2009. Heidegger's Platonism. New York and London

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Ralkowski, Mark A. 2009. Heidegger's Platonism. New York and London 128 Critical Notices / The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 6 (2012) 128-138 Ralkowski, Mark A. 2009. Heidegger’s Platonism. New York and London: Contin- uum Publishing, 212 + xx pp., hardbound, $130, 978-1441184894. Plato exerts a signifijicant, albeit not always obvious, influence on Heidegger’s thought. Indeed, Heidegger’s central work Being and Time begins with a quota- tion from Plato’s Sophist: “For manifestly you have long been aware of what you mean when you use the expression ‘being.’ We, however, who used to think we understood it, have now become perplexed.”1 Although Heidegger throughout claimed that Brentano’s dissertation Von der mannigfachen Bedeutung des Seien- den nach Aristoteles2 had been the main influence on his philosophy,3 one does not have to look far for traces of Plato’s influence on his thought. In Being and Time, following the preface, Heidegger speaks of the challenge of a “rekindled γιγαντοµαχία περὶ τῆς οὐσίας,”4 And while he acknowledges the necessity of such a struggle (and even welcomes the opportunity to “reawaken” an understanding of the meaning of the question of Being), he also makes it clear that in under- standing the problem of Being “our fijirst philosophical step” must lie in “not µῦθόν τινα διηγεῖσθαι, in not ‘telling a story’.”5 Both the quotation regarding the gigan- tomachy and that regarding the necessity and desirability of not telling a myth are from Plato’s Sophist (246a and 242c).6 The shadow of Plato thus looms large 1) Macquarrie/Robinson trans.; the passage is from Plato’s Sophist 244a. 2) Franz Brentano, Von der mannigfachen Bedeutung des Seienden nach Aristoteles. Freiburg: Herder, 1862. 3) See, for example, the autobiographical account in “Mein Weg in die Phänomenologie” (1963; since reprinted in volume 14 of the Heidegger Gesamtasugabe, Zur Sache des Denkens (Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann, 2007)). The account has been challenged by many scholars as an idealized self-representation. 4) Note the “demythologization” at stake here, an idea that is given full prominence later in Bultmann’s demythologizing project. Bultmann, of course, was among the theologians most deeply influenced by Heidegger. 5) Heidegger does not indicate the ellipsis here (the passage actually reads µῦθόν τινα ἕκαστος φαίνεταί µοι διηγεῖσθαι), but in his Plato’s Sophist lecture course from 1923 he quotes the full passage. His paraphrasing restatement is characteristic of his strategy of identifying the ontological diffference, i.e., the distinction between Being and beings, as what has never been thought as such in the history of Western philosophy: “This says,” he clarifijies, “that the ancients, insofar as they dealt with Being, told stories about beings, said what happens to beings. Hence the ancients did not at all arrive at a position from which they could deter- mine something about the Being of beings.” Martin Heidegger, Plato’s Sophist, trans. Richard Rojcewicz & André Schuwer (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1997), 305; empha- sis in original. 6) Both passages are cited in Heidegger’s 1923 lecture course on Plato’s Sophist (see n. 5 above). Once again, Heidegger interprets the gigantomachy in characteristically idiosyncratic © Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2012 DOI: 10.1163/187254712X621004 Critical Notices / The International Journal of the Platonic Tradition 6 (2012) 128-138 129 over Heidegger’s masterpiece. And when Heidegger ends his book with a discus- sion of Hegel, we can discern the faint but unmistakable echo of Plato yet again.7 Yet, surprisingly, the question of Heidegger’s ‘Platonism’ has attracted little attention from scholars. Besides Gadamer, who develops his reading of Plato in explicit dialogue with Heidegger,8 few scholars have taken up the question. Apart from a few scholars who have dedicated essays to the topic,9 most Heidegger scholars skirt this issue.10 Among scholars of ancient philosophy, the silence is even more pronounced. With the exception of Stanley Rosen,11 most scholars of ancient philosophy appear to consider a dialogue with Heidegger to be not worth fashion. Asking rhetorically “what genuinely is at stake in this γιγαντοµαχία περὶ τῆς οὐσίας?,” he immediately supplies the following answer: “The issue is the disclosure of beings, the ones that genuinely satisfy the meaning of Being, and consequently the issue is the demon- stration of the meaning of οὐσία itself. The way to demonstrate the meaning of οὐσία is to produce the beings which satisfy the meaning of Being. This latter task is not independent but is entirely included in the fijirst. The question of the meaning of οὐσία is not alive for the Greeks as an ontological theme; instead they always ask only: which beings genuinely satisfy the meaning of Being and which ontological characters result thereby? The meaning of Being itself remains unquestioned.” Heidegger, Plato’s Sophist, 323. 7) Throughout his career, Heidegger insisted that Hegel was the most Greek of German thinkers; for relevant passages, see Being and Time, 22, 22-23; see also the critique of Hegel that runs through his 1919/1920 lecture course Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie (Martin Heidegger, Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie, 2nd ed. (Frankfurt a.M.: Vittorio Klostermann, 2010)). 8) See, for example, his Dialogue and Dialectic: Eight Hermeneutical Studies in Plato, trans. P. Christopher Smith (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1983) or his The Idea of the Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy, trans. P. Christopher Smith (New Haven, CT: Yale Uni- versity Press, 1986). 9) See, for example, Drew Hyland, “Heidegger’s Plato,” in Questioning Platonism: Continen- tal Interpretations of Plato (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 2004); see also Robert J. Dostal’s his- torical survey of Heidegger’s relationship to Plato in “Beyond Being: Heidegger’s Plato,” Journal of the History of Philosophy 23,1 (January 1985): 71-98. More recently, Catalin Partenie and Tom Rockmore have produced the fijirst volume of essays on the Heidegger/Plato rela- tionship. While individually illuminating on various aspects of the relationship, the essays still do not amount to a comprehensive consideration of that relationship; Catalin Partenie and Tom Rockmore, Heidegger and Plato: Towards Dialogue (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 2005). See also the useful overview in Catherine H. Zuckert, Postmodern Platos (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996). 10) Excluding, of course, a slew of ‘Heideggerianizing’ interpretations of Plato, such as those of John Sallis and some of his students. 11) See, for example, his “Heidegger’s Interpretation of Plato,” The Journal of Existentialism 8,28 (1967): 477-504 or the more recent The Question of Being: A Reversal of Heidegger (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1993)..
Recommended publications
  • Book Summer 2006.Qxd
    Memoir by Stanley Rosen Leo Strauss in Chicago Downloaded from http://direct.mit.edu/daed/article-pdf/135/3/104/1829109/daed.2006.135.3.104.pdf by guest on 01 October 2021 I ½rst met Leo Strauss when I was nine- the graduate of a Swiss private lycée teen years old and a student in the Col- accomplished this some years after my lege of the University of Chicago. It was departure. In 1949, though, the record the spring of 1949–this was during the was one year, which was matched by epoch of the presidency of Robert May- eighteen members of my class, including nard Hutchins, when the University was myself and my classmate and friend Seth at the height of its glory. At that time, Benardete. the College was famous for the eccen- Another peculiarity of the College was tricity and precociousness of many of that one could enter it at any age, and its students, and also for its highly un- among my classmates were a number of usual custom of allowing entering stu- virtual children. I still remember a par- dents to take examinations on the basis ty given by some of the older students. of which they were assigned course re- There, I entered into conversation with quirements. The intention of this pro- a man who seemed to be in his mid-thir- gram was to extend the time we spent ties, a guess that his thick glasses and ad- in graduate school, provided that we al- vanced baldness only strengthened. He ready possessed the necessary founda- informed me that he had broken with tion.
    [Show full text]
  • SMITH-DELEUZE 9780748643332 PRINT.Indd I 16/04/2012 16:37 SMITH-DELEUZE 9780748643332 PRINT.Indd Ii 16/04/2012 16:37 Essays on Deleuze
    ‘For the last fifteen years, all of us have read one or two of Daniel Smith’s remarkable essays on Deleuze. But now, we have all of them. Finally and thankfully, we have Essays on Deleuze, a book that will become immediately essential reading for anyone interested in twentieth-century continental philosophy.’ Leonard Lawlor, Sparks Professor of Philosophy, Penn State University ‘For many years now Daniel Smith’s work has led us through Deleuze’s philosophy with an unmatched clarity. It is thanks to him that the many historical connections of that philosophy have been grasped in their full rigour and depth. No researcher on Deleuze’s philosophy can pass this work by. No reader can fail to benefit from an engagement with Smith’s groundbreaking interpretation.’ James Williams, Professor of European Philosophy, University of Dundee Essays on Deleuze gathers twenty of Smith’s new and classic essays into one volume for the first time. Gilles Deleuze (1925-1995) was one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth-century, and Daniel W. Smith is widely recognized to be one of his most penetrating interpreters, as well as an important philosophical voice in his own right. Combining his most important pieces over the last fifteen years along with two new essays, this book is Smith’s definitive treatise on Deleuze. The essays are divided into four sections, which cover Deleuze’s use of the history of philosophy, an overview of his philosophical system, an analysis of several Deleuzian concepts, as well as an assessment of his position within contemporary philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • (I) the Dismal Discourse of Postmodernism's Grand Narratives
    The Enlightenment Gone Mad (I) The Dismal Discourse Of Postmodernism’s Grand Narratives RAINER FRIEDRICH “Postmodernism is the enlightenment gone mad” —Stanley Rosen Postmodernism is a diffuse phenomenon that has proved unpropitious to definers. Hardly a wonder, when one of its theorists can come up with twelve different post- modernisms.1 Compounding this difficulty, as Umberto Eco has observed in the postscript to The Name of the Rose, is the tendency of “postmodern” to become “increasingly retroac- tive”; in the end, Eco quips, “the postmodern category will in- clude Homer.” No longer a quip, it has already happened. On the strength of Helen’s depicting, on a robe she is weaving, “the many struggles the Achaeans and Trojans endured for her sake at the hands of the war-god” (Iliad 3), the late Paul de Man claimed the Homeric epic as a self-referential post- modern text! Such retroactive designation, combined with the widespread indiscriminate use of the postmodern category, threatens to render it altogether vacuous. Or nonsensical à la Lyotard: “A work can become modern only if it is first post- modern. Postmodernism thus understood is not modernism at its end but in the nascent state, and this state is constant.”2 the dismal discourse yet for all the diffusion, there is a discernible commonal- ity among the various branches of postmodernism. They have in common a penchant for passing death sentences and issuing death certificates, promulgating, with either insou- arion 19.3 winter 2012 32 the enlightenment gone mad ciant glee or ponderous gloom, the death of reason; the death of the enlightenment; the death of universalism; the death of normativity and law; the death of meaning and truth—in short, the death of almost everything that the Western intellectual tradition stands for in general and that modernity has claimed in particular.
    [Show full text]
  • The Modern World of Leo Strauss Author(S): Robert B
    The Modern World of Leo Strauss Author(s): Robert B. Pippin Source: Political Theory, Vol. 20, No. 3 (Aug., 1992), pp. 448-472 Published by: Sage Publications, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/192187 . Accessed: 03/08/2011 22:19 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at . http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=sage. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Sage Publications, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Political Theory. http://www.jstor.org THE MODERN WORLD OF LEO STRAUSS ROBERTB. PIPPIN Universityof California,San
    [Show full text]
  • Plato and the Question of Beauty (Studies in Continental Thought)
    PHILOSOPHY | CLASSICS & ANTIQUITY HYLAND Reveals the intimate connection between beauty and the philosophical life Plato “A well-written and forcefully argued exposition PLATO of one of the most important themes in Plato’s philosophy.” and and the —Walter Brogan, Villanova University the Drew A. Hyland, one of Continental philosophy’s keenest interpreters of Plato, Question takes up the question of beauty in three Platonic dialogues, the Hippias Major, Symposium, and Phaedrus. What Plato meant by beauty is not easily character- Question ized, and Hyland’s close readings show that Plato ultimately gives up on the pos- of sibility of a defi nition. Plato’s failure, however, tells us something important about beauty—that it cannot be reduced to logos. Exploring questions surround- ing love, memory, and ideal form, Hyland draws out the connections between Beauty beauty, the possibility of philosophy, and philosophical living. This new reading of Plato provides a serious investigation into the meaning of beauty and places it of at the very heart of philosophy. Beauty DREW A. HYLAND is Charles A. Dana Professor of Philosophy at Trinity College. He is editor (with John Panteleimon Manoussakis) of Heidegger and the Greeks (Indiana University Press, 2006). Studies in Continental Thought, John Sallis, editor Cover illustration: © Copyright the Trustees of The British Museum INDIANA INDIANA University Press Bloomington & Indianapolis http://iupress.indiana.edu 1-800-842-6796 DREW A. HYLAND PLATO and the Question of Beauty Studies in Continental Thought John Sallis, editor Consulting Editors Robert Bernasconi William L. McBride Rudolph Bernet J. N. Mohanty John D. Caputo Mary Rawlinson David Carr Tom Rockmore Edward S.
    [Show full text]
  • Robert B. Pippin
    CURRICULUM VITAE ROBERT B. PIPPIN Evelyn Stefansson Nef Distinguished Service Professor in the John U. Nef Committee on Social Thought, the Department of Philosophy, and the College The University of Chicago The John U. Nef Committee on Social Thought 1130 East 59th Street Chicago, Illinois 60637 The Department of Philosophy 1115 E. 58th St. Chicago, IL 60637 (773) 702-5453 FAX: (773) 834-1968 email: [email protected] website: http://home.uchicago.edu/~rbp1/ Education B.A. with Honors in English, Trinity College, Hartford, Conn. 1970 M.A. Philosophy (Minor: Greek), Pennsylvania State University 1972 Ph.D. Philosophy, Pennsylvania State University, August 31, 1974 Honors, Awards, Endowed Lectures, Prizes 2019 - Guggenheim Fellowship 2019 - Penn State Alumni Association Lifetime Achievement Award 2018 - Penn State Graduate School Distiunguished Alumnus Award 2018 (winter) – Steiner Lecture, St. John’s College, Santa Fe, New Mexico 2018 (spring) – Kneller Lecture, Philosophy of Education Society, Chicago, Illinois 2019 (winter) – Penn State Alumni Fellow Award 2017 (fall) – Alumni Association of Penn State Lifetime Achievement Award 2017 (fall) – Thomas Scholl Lecture, Purdue University Philosophy Department 2017 (fall) – Friedrich Nietzsche Lecture (Inaugural), University of Basel, Switzerland 2017 (spring) – elected to the German National Academy of Sciences Leopoldina 2016 (fall) – Townsend Visitor (three lectures), University of California, Berkeley 2015 (fall) – Suarez Lecture, Fordham University 2015 (fall) - Larwill Lecture, Kenyon
    [Show full text]
  • Stanley Rosen: the Nemesis of Nihilism
    Digital Commons @ Assumption University Philosophy Department Faculty Works Philosophy Department 2013 Stanley Rosen: The Nemesis of Nihilism Nalin Ranasinghe Assumption College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.assumption.edu/philosophy-faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons, Political Science Commons, and the Social and Philosophical Foundations of Education Commons Recommended Citation Ranasinghe, Nalin. "Stanley Rosen: The Nemesis of Nihilism." Teaching in an Age of Ideology. Edited by John von Heyking and Lee Trepanier. Lexington Books, 2013, pp. 205-215. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy Department at Digital Commons @ Assumption University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Department Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Assumption University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Chapter 10 Stanley Rosen: The Nemesis of Nihilism Nalin Ranasinghe, Assumption College Although his writing style has changed more than once, Rosen has always sought to defend the lifeline between cosmos and logos; he has always insisted that the bond between philosophy and ordinary language is sacred and indis­ soluble. From this vantage his amazing ability to yoke together and drive the unruly black horse of ordinary language and the ideal steed of metaphysics seems godlike. Accordingly, bearing in mind his teacher's famous assertion that the depth of things resides precisely in their surfaces, it is appropriate that my tribute by should begin by describing Stanley Rosen in the place where his un­ surpassed mastery of both philosophy and ordinary language are most evident: the classroom. I first took a class with Stanley Rosen almost twenty years ago, at Penn State, in the fall of 1985.
    [Show full text]
  • NIHILISM, NATURE, and the COLLAPSE of the COSMOS David Storey
    Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011 NIHILISM, NATURE, AND THE COLLAPSE OF THE COSMOS David Storey ABSTRACT: Though nihilism is a major theme in late modern philosophy from Hegel onward, it is only relatively recently that it has been treated as the subject of monographs and anthologies. Commentators have offered a number of accounts of the origins and nature of nihilism. Some see it as a purely historical and predominantly modern phenomenon, a consequence of the social, economic, ecological, political, and/or religious upheavals of modernity. Others think it stems from human nature itself, and should be seen as a perennial problem. Still others think that nihilism has ontological significance and issues from the nature of being itself. In this essay, I survey the most important of these narratives of nihilism to show how commonly the advent and spread of nihilism is linked with changing conceptions of (humanity’s relation to) nature. At root, nihilism is a problem about humanity’s relation to nature, about a crisis in human freedom and willing after the collapse of the cosmos, the erosion of a hierarchically ordered nature in which humans have a proper place. Two themes recur in the literature: first, the collapse of what is commonly called the “great chain of being” or the cosmos generally; and second, the increased importance placed on human will and subjectivity and, correlatively, the significance of human history as opposed to nature. KEYWORDS: Nihilism; Nature; Cosmos We typically regard nihilism as a problem about human life.
    [Show full text]
  • Kojève's Paris
    Florence de Lussy (dir.) Hommage à Alexandre Kojève Actes de la « Journée A. Kojève » du 28 janvier 2003 Éditions de la Bibliothèque nationale de France Kojève’s Paris: A Memoir Stanley Rosen DOI: 10.4000/books.editionsbnf.387 Publisher: Éditions de la Bibliothèque nationale de France Place of publication: Paris Year of publication: 2007 Published on OpenEdition Books: 19 March 2014 Serie: Conférences et Études Electronic ISBN: 9782717725957 http://books.openedition.org Electronic reference ROSEN, Stanley. Kojève’s Paris: A Memoir In: Hommage à Alexandre Kojève: Actes de la « Journée A. Kojève » du 28 janvier 2003 [online]. Paris: Éditions de la Bibliothèque nationale de France, 2007 (generated 18 December 2020). Available on the Internet: <http://books.openedition.org/editionsbnf/ 387>. ISBN: 9782717725957. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4000/books.editionsbnf.387. Kojève’s Paris : A Memoir 1 Stanley Rosen This is a radically revised and expanded version of a short essay commissioned by parallax for a special issue on Kojève’s Paris. I want to emphasize that what follows is a memoir, not a scholarly analysis. It is nevertheless my hope that some readers will find it of philosophical interest. I have been thinking about Kojève for almost forty years, both in himself and in relation to another great teacher, Leo Strauss. Strauss used to endorse Nietszche’s remark that the student’s duty to his teacher is to kill him. This advice, which was not understood by many of those who later came to be called Straussians, is intended to free the neophyte for the arduous task of philosophe, and for the task of doing justice to the nature of one’s teacher.
    [Show full text]
  • The Compassion of Zarathustra: Nietzsche on Sympathy and Strength
    The Compassion of Zarathustra: Nietzsche on Sympathy and Strength The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Frazer, Michael. 2006. The compassion of Zarathustra: Nietzsche on sympathy and strength. Review of Politics 68, no. 1: 49-78. Published Version http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0034670506000052 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:3350069 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Page 1 The final, definitive version of this article was published in The Review of Politics 68:1 (February 2006), pp. 49-78 by Cambridge University Press. All rights reserved. © 2006 University of Notre Dame. Available online at http://journals.cambridge.org. The Compassion of Zarathustra: Nietzsche on Sympathy and Strength Michael L. Frazer Contemporary moral and political discourse, across the ideological spectrum, regularly celebrates sentiments of sympathy or compassion.1 Most canonical philosophers would take issue with this current vogue for shared suffering; Friedrich Nietzsche is far from unique in this regard. Indeed, Nietzsche acknowledges that the “overestimation of and predilection for compassion [des Mitleidens] on the part of modern philosophers is something new: hitherto philosophers have been at one as to the worthlessness of compassion. I name only Plato, Spinoza, La Rochefocauld and Kant…” (GM Preface 5, p. 455).2 With many such philosophers, however, compassion is ignored, downplayed, or written-off more than it is actively opposed, often lumped together with all other strong emotions as an irrational “passion” to be subdued by “reason.” Yet Nietzsche was hardly an opponent of the non-rational passions as such,3 and his critique of compassion is singular in both its extent and its vehemence.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae Martin Black 88A Marion St., Apt. 2
    Curriculum Vitae Martin Black 88A Marion St., Apt. 2 Brookline, MA 02446 Phone: (617) 955-3910 Email: [email protected] AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION Ancient Greek Philosophy, Political Philosophy, Ancient Greek Language and Literature AREAS OF COMPETENCE Early Modern Philosophy, Theoretical and Applied Ethics, Existentialism, Nietzsche EDUCATION 2009 PhD in Philosophy, Boston University Dissertation Title: “Plato’s Depiction of the Socratic Turn in the Phaedo, Parmenides, and Symposium” First Reader: Stanley Rosen 2004 MA (Research) in Philosophy, Melbourne University Thesis Title: “On Politics and Philosophy: A Reading of Plato’s Apology of Socrates” 1998 BA (Honours) in Philosophy and Classics, Melbourne University PUBLICATIONS Forthcoming: Rosen, Stanley, Essays in Ancient and Modern Philosophy, 2 Vols., Edited with an Introduction by Martin Black (to be published by St. Augustine’s Press in November 2011) “Plato’s Critique of Poetry in the Symposium,” in Plato’s Music, ed. Eugenio Benitez, A Special Issue of Literature and Aesthetics, vol. 19, no. 1 (Sydney: University of Sydney Printing: June 2009): 51-73. “Is There a Crisis of Modernity?” in Human Ends and the Ends of Politics, Proceedings of the Junior Visiting Fellows Conference, edited with a Preface by Martin Black and Kirsten McKillop, Institute for Human Sciences/Institut für Wissenschaften vom Menschen, Vienna (IHS/IWM: published on the web, http://www.iwm.at in February 2009) “Self-Knowledge,” Traffic: An Interdisciplinary Journal, ed. Monica Dux, Issue 1 (University of Melbourne
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae: Drew A
    Drew A. Hyland CURRICULUM VITAE: DREW A. HYLAND Charles A. Dana Professor of Philosophy Trinity College Hartford, CT 06106 Born: February 9, 1939 Citizenship: U.S.A. Personal: Married, two children Degrees: B.A Princeton University 1961 M.A. The Pennsylvania State University 1963 Ph.D. The Pennsylvania State University 1965 Thesis Topic: "Eros and Philosophy: A Study of Plato's Symposium" Thesis Advisor: Stanley Rosen Academic Honors: B.A. Cum Laude M.A. Cum Laude - excused from thesis Recipient of Graduate School Fellowship. Pennsylvania State University, 1963-64 Renewed from 1964-65 but declined in order to accept teaching position at University of Toronto Fellow of the Institute for Greek Philosophy, Colorado Springs, Colorado, June 1970 Mellon Symposium Fellow, 1976 Charles A. Dana Professor of Philosophy, September 1, 1982 Hewlitt-Mellon Grant for Course Development, $1000, Summer 1983 Supplementary Sabbatical, Trinity College, 1984 National Endowment For the Humanities Grant: Project Director, Summer Seminars for Secondary School Teachers, 1986 National Endowment For the Humanities Grant: Project Director, Summer Seminars for Secondary School Teachers, 1988 Brownell Prize for Excellence in Teaching, 1990 Faculty Research Grant, Fall, 1994 Distinguished Scholar Award, Philosophical Society For the Study of Sport, June, 1998 Faculty Research Grant, Fall, 2001: “Postmodern Readings of Plato.” Trustees’ Award for Faculty Excellence, Trinity College, 2010. Director, Collegium Phaenomenologicum, Citta di Castello, Italy, July, 2013 Visiting
    [Show full text]