Axiomatic Systems

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Axiomatic Systems Math 161 - Notes Neil Donaldson Spring 2021 1 Geometry and the Axiomatic Method 1.1 The Early Origins of Geometry: Thales and Pythagoras We begin with a condensed overview of geometric history. The word geometry itself comes from the ancient Greek terms geo (Earth), and metros (measure): indeed the ancient Greeks are the culture most associated with the development of geometry. Ancient times (pre-500 BC) Egypt, Babylonia, China, India: basic rules for measuring lengths, areas and volumes of simple shapes. Applications: surveying, tax collection, construction, religious practice, astronomy, navigation. Worked examples without general formulæ/abstraction. Ancient Greece (from c.600 BC) Philosophers such as Thales and Pythagoras began the process of ab- straction. General statements (theorems) formulated and proofs attempted, mving mathematics beyond the practical. Concurrent development of early scientific reasoning. Euclid of Alexandria (c.300 BC) Collected and developed earlier work, especially of the Pythagoreans in the Elements; one of the most important books in Western history and remaining a standard school textbook until the early 1900’s. Began the axiomatic method on which modern mathe- matics is based. Later Greek Geometry Archimedes’ (c.270–212 BC) work on area and volume included techniques sim- ilar to those of modern calculus. Ptolemy (c. AD 100–170) writes the Almagest, a treatise on astronomy which begins the study of trigonometry. Post-Greek Geometry During the European Dark Ages, geometric understanding was developed and enhanced by Indian and Islamic mathematicians who particularly developed trigonometry and algebra. Analytic Geometry The melding of algebra with geometry was completed by Descartes in mid-1600’s France, with the advent of co-ordinate systems. Modern Development Non-Euclidean geometries (e.g. hyperbolic geometry) help provide the mathe- matical foundation for Einstein’s relativity and the study of curvature. Following Klein (1872), modern geometry is highly dependent on group theory. Thales of Miletus (c.624–546 BC) Thales was an olive trader from Miletus, a city-state on the west coast of modern Turkey. Through his trades and travels he absorbed mathematical ideas from nearby cultures including Egypt and Babylon. Thales holds pride of place in mathematics as one of the first philosophers to state theorems. Here are five theorems, at least partly attributed to Thales; the last indeed is still known as Thales’ Theorem. 1. A circle is bisected by a diameter. 2. The base angles of an isosceles triangle are equal. 3. The pairs of angles formed by two intersecting lines are equal. 4. Two triangles are congruent if they have two angles and the included side equal. 5. An angle inscribed in a semicircle is a right angle. Thales’ proofs were not what we’d understand by the term, with his reasoning being partly example- based. The important developement was that his statements were abstract and general: e.g. any circle will be bisected by any of its diameters. α β α β The pictures show Thales’ Theorems 1, 2 and 5. ‘Arguments’ for Theorems 1 and 2 could be as simple as ‘fold.’ Theorem 5 follows from the observation that the radius of the circle splits the large triangle into two isosceles triangles: Theorem 2 says that these have equal base angles (labelled), now check that a + b is half the angles in a triangle, namely a right-angle. The ancient Greek word q#wr#w (theoreo) has several meanings: ‘to look at,’ ‘speculate,’ or ‘consider.’ These early theorems were essentially general principles which were supposed to be fairly clear by looking at the picture the right way! Pythagoras of Samos (570—495 BC) Pythagoras grew up on Samos, an island not far from Miletus in the Aegean sea. He also travelled widely, eventually settling in Croton, southern Italy, around 530 BC where he founded a philosophical school devoted to the study of number, music and ge- ometry. Amongst other mathematical contributions, it has been claimed that the Pythaogreans first classified the regular (Platonic) solids and developed the nusical relationship between the length of a vibrating string and its pitch. While it is difficult to verify such assertions, their obsession with number and the ‘music of the universe’ certainly inspired later mathematicians and philosophers— in particular Euclid, Plato and Aristotle—who believed they were refining and clarifying this earlier work. Indeed Book I of Euclid’s Elements seems to have been structured precisely to provide a rig- orous proof of what we now know of as Pythagoras’ Theorem, perhaps the most famous result in mathematics. 2 A simple proof of Pythagoras’ Theorem1 Much has been written about Pythagoras’ Theorem, including many, many proofs.2 It is often claimed that Pythagoras himself first proved the result, but this is generally accepted to be absurd given that the ‘proof’ most often attributed to the Pythagoreans is based on contradictory ideas about numbers. Other cultures’ frequent use of the result suggests that the statement was known several hundred years before Pythagoras; the earliest known reference comes from China where the state- ment is known as the gou gu. Any argument over attribution is somewhat moot, given that we first need to agree on what ‘proof’ means. As far as modern mathematics is concerned, this means that we need to spend some time considering Axiomatic Systems. Exercises. 1.1.1. Label the second picture above so that each triangle has side lengths a, b, c: now use algebra to give a simple proof of Pythagoras’ Theorem. 1.1.2. A theorem of Euclid states: The square on the parts equals the sum of the squares on each part plus twice the rectangle on the parts By referencing the above picture, state Euclid’s result using modern algebra. (Hint: let a and b be the ‘parts’. ) 1The second picture will animate if you click on it while open in a full-feature pdf reader like acrobat. 2Including a proof by former US President James Garfield: would that current presidents were so learned. 3 1.2 The Axiomatic Method It is believed that a primary motivation for Euclid’s writing of the first book of the Elements was to rigorously prove Pythagoras’ Theorem. In so doing, he essentially invented the axiomatic method. Before considering Euclid’s approach, we describe the revolutionary structure Euclid followed, that of a deductive or axiomatic system. Definition 1.1. An axiomatic system comprises four pieces: 1. Undefined terms: concepts accepted without definition/explanation. In the setting of basic ge- ometry these might include line or point. 2. Axioms/Postulates: logical statements regarding the undefined terms which are accepted with- out proof. For example: There exists a line joining any two given points.a 3. Defined terms: concepts defined in terms of 1 and 2. For instance a triangle could be defined in terms of three non-collinear points. 4. Theorems: logical statements deduced from 1–3. aIn Euclid, an axiom is considered to be somewhat more self-evident than a postulate, but the distinction is not impor- tant to us. For instance, one of Euclid’s axioms is, ‘Things which are equal to the same thing are also equal to one another,’ essentially the transitivity of equality. This feels more general than the postulate regarding a line joining two points. In the strictest sense of the word, a proof is an argument demonstrating the truth of a theorem within an axiomatic system. Given that the Pythagoreans did not follow such a system, they cannot really be said to have proved anything! Examples 1.2. We consider two simple examples of a deductive system: the first is a game—many such can be considered deductive systems—while the second is more traditionally mathematical. Chess 1. Undefined terms: Pieces (as black/white objects) and the board. 2. Axioms/Postulates: Rules for how each piece moves. 3. Defined terms: Concepts such as check, stalemate or en-passant. 4. Theorems: For example, Given a particular position, Black can win in 5 moves. Monoid 1. Undefined terms: A set G and a binary operation ∗. 2. Axioms/Postulates: (A1) Closure: 8a, b 2 G, a ∗ b 2 G. (A2) Associativity: 8a, b, c 2 G, a ∗ (b ∗ c) = (a ∗ b) ∗ c. (A3) Identity: 9e 2 G such that 8a 2 G we have a ∗ e = e ∗ a = a. 3. Defined terms: Concepts such as square a2 = a ∗ a, or commutativity a ∗ b = b ∗ a. 4. Theorems: For example, The identity is unique. Given that the concept of a set and that much notation is needed, one could argue that many more axioms are really required! 4 Definition 1.3. A model of an axiomatic system is an interpretation of the undefined terms such that all the axioms/postulates are true. Example 1.4. (G, ∗) = (Z, +) is a model of a monoid, where e = 0. The big idea of models and axiomatic systems is this: Any theorem proved within an axiomatic system is true in any model of that system. Mathematical discoveries often hinge on the realization that two seemingly separate discussions can be described in terms of models of a common axiomatic system. Properties of Axiomatic Systems Definition 1.5. Certain properties are desirable in an axiomatic system: Consistency The system is free of contradictions. Independence An axiom is independent if it is not a theorem of the others. An axiomatic system is independent if all its axioms are. Completeness Every proposition within the theory is decidable; can be proved or disproved. In practice, it is very unlikely that one has a system which satisfies all three desirable properties. We unpack slightly what is required to demonstrate or contradict each. By necessity, our descriptions are vague, since many notions need to be clarified (such as what is meant by a valid proposition within a theory) before these notions can be made rigorous.
Recommended publications
  • Some First-Order Probability Logics
    Theoretical Computer Science 247 (2000) 191–212 www.elsevier.com/locate/tcs View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Some ÿrst-order probability logics provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Zoran Ognjanovic a;∗, Miodrag RaÄskovic b a MatematickiÄ institut, Kneza Mihaila 35, 11000 Beograd, Yugoslavia b Prirodno-matematickiÄ fakultet, R. Domanovicaà 12, 34000 Kragujevac, Yugoslavia Received June 1998 Communicated by M. Nivat Abstract We present some ÿrst-order probability logics. The logics allow making statements such as P¿s , with the intended meaning “the probability of truthfulness of is greater than or equal to s”. We describe the corresponding probability models. We give a sound and complete inÿnitary axiomatic system for the most general of our logics, while for some restrictions of this logic we provide ÿnitary axiomatic systems. We study the decidability of our logics. We discuss some of the related papers. c 2000 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: First order logic; Probability; Possible worlds; Completeness 1. Introduction In recent years there is a growing interest in uncertainty reasoning. A part of inves- tigation concerns its formal framework – probability logics [1, 2, 5, 6, 9, 13, 15, 17–20]. Probability languages are obtained by adding probability operators of the form (in our notation) P¿s to classical languages. The probability logics allow making formulas such as P¿s , with the intended meaning “the probability of truthfulness of is greater than or equal to s”. Probability models similar to Kripke models are used to give semantics to the probability formulas so that interpreted formulas are either true or false.
    [Show full text]
  • Open-Logic-Enderton Rev: C8c9782 (2021-09-28) by OLP/ CC–BY
    An Open Mathematical Introduction to Logic Example OLP Text `ala Enderton Open Logic Project open-logic-enderton rev: c8c9782 (2021-09-28) by OLP/ CC{BY Contents I Propositional Logic7 1 Syntax and Semantics9 1.0 Introduction............................ 9 1.1 Propositional Wffs......................... 10 1.2 Preliminaries............................ 11 1.3 Valuations and Satisfaction.................... 12 1.4 Semantic Notions ......................... 14 Problems ................................. 14 2 Derivation Systems 17 2.0 Introduction............................ 17 2.1 The Sequent Calculus....................... 18 2.2 Natural Deduction......................... 19 2.3 Tableaux.............................. 20 2.4 Axiomatic Derivations ...................... 22 3 Axiomatic Derivations 25 3.0 Rules and Derivations....................... 25 3.1 Axiom and Rules for the Propositional Connectives . 26 3.2 Examples of Derivations ..................... 27 3.3 Proof-Theoretic Notions ..................... 29 3.4 The Deduction Theorem ..................... 30 1 Contents 3.5 Derivability and Consistency................... 32 3.6 Derivability and the Propositional Connectives......... 32 3.7 Soundness ............................. 33 Problems ................................. 34 4 The Completeness Theorem 35 4.0 Introduction............................ 35 4.1 Outline of the Proof........................ 36 4.2 Complete Consistent Sets of Sentences ............. 37 4.3 Lindenbaum's Lemma....................... 38 4.4 Construction of a Model
    [Show full text]
  • Axiomatic Systems for Geometry∗
    Axiomatic Systems for Geometry∗ George Francisy composed 6jan10, adapted 27jan15 1 Basic Concepts An axiomatic system contains a set of primitives and axioms. The primitives are Adaptation to the object names, but the objects they name are left undefined. This is why the primi- current course is in tives are also called undefined terms. The axioms are sentences that make assertions the margins. about the primitives. Such assertions are not provided with any justification, they are neither true nor false. However, every subsequent assertion about the primitives, called a theorem, must be a rigorously logical consequence of the axioms and previ- ously proved theorems. There are also formal definitions in an axiomatic system, but these serve only to simplify things. They establish new object names for complex combinations of primitives and previously defined terms. This kind of definition does not impart any `meaning', not yet, anyway. See Lesson A6 for an elaboration. If, however, a definite meaning is assigned to the primitives of the axiomatic system, called an interpretation, then the theorems become meaningful assertions which might be true or false. If for a given interpretation all the axioms are true, then everything asserted by the theorems also becomes true. Such an interpretation is called a model for the axiomatic system. In common speech, `model' is often used to mean an example of a class of things. In geometry, a model of an axiomatic system is an interpretation of its primitives for ∗From textitPost-Euclidean Geometry: Class Notes and Workbook, UpClose Printing & Copies, Champaign, IL 1995, 2004 yProf. George K.
    [Show full text]
  • Math 310 Class Notes 1: Axioms of Set Theory
    MATH 310 CLASS NOTES 1: AXIOMS OF SET THEORY Intuitively, we think of a set as an organization and an element be- longing to a set as a member of the organization. Accordingly, it also seems intuitively clear that (1) when we collect all objects of a certain kind the collection forms an organization, i.e., forms a set, and, moreover, (2) it is natural that when we collect members of a certain kind of an organization, the collection is a sub-organization, i.e., a subset. Item (1) above was challenged by Bertrand Russell in 1901 if we accept the natural item (2), i.e., we must be careful when we use the word \all": (Russell Paradox) The collection of all sets is not a set! Proof. Suppose the collection of all sets is a set S. Consider the subset U of S that consists of all sets x with the property that each x does not belong to x itself. Now since U is a set, U belongs to S. Let us ask whether U belongs to U itself. Since U is the collection of all sets each of which does not belong to itself, thus if U belongs to U, then as an element of the set U we must have that U does not belong to U itself, a contradiction. So, it must be that U does not belong to U. But then U belongs to U itself by the very definition of U, another contradiction. The absurdity results because we assume S is a set.
    [Show full text]
  • Axiomatic Foundations of Mathematics Ryan Melton Dr
    Axiomatic Foundations of Mathematics Ryan Melton Dr. Clint Richardson, Faculty Advisor Stephen F. Austin State University As Bertrand Russell once said, Gödel's Method Pure mathematics is the subject in which we Consider the expression First, Gödel assigned a unique natural number to do not know what we are talking about, or each of the logical symbols and numbers. 2 + 3 = 5 whether what we are saying is true. Russell’s statement begs from us one major This expression is mathematical; it belongs to the field For example: if the symbol '0' corresponds to we call arithmetic and is composed of basic arithmetic question: the natural number 1, '+' to 2, and '=' to 3, then symbols. '0 = 0' '0 + 0 = 0' What is Mathematics founded on? On the other hand, the sentence and '2 + 3 = 5' is an arithmetical formula. 1 3 1 1 2 1 3 1 so each expression corresponds to a sequence. Axioms and Axiom Systems is metamathematical; it is constructed outside of mathematics and labels the expression above as a Then, for this new sequence x1x2x3…xn of formula in arithmetic. An axiom is a belief taken without proof, and positive integers, we associate a Gödel number thus an axiom system is a set of beliefs as follows: x1 x2 x3 xn taken without proof. enc( x1x2x3...xn ) = 2 3 5 ... pn Since Principia Mathematica was such a bold where the encoding is the product of n factors, Consistent? Complete? leap in the right direction--although proving each of which is found by raising the j-th prime nothing about consistency--several attempts at to the xj power.
    [Show full text]
  • The Entscheidungsproblem and Alan Turing
    The Entscheidungsproblem and Alan Turing Author: Laurel Brodkorb Advisor: Dr. Rachel Epstein Georgia College and State University December 18, 2019 1 Abstract Computability Theory is a branch of mathematics that was developed by Alonzo Church, Kurt G¨odel,and Alan Turing during the 1930s. This paper explores their work to formally define what it means for something to be computable. Most importantly, this paper gives an in-depth look at Turing's 1936 paper, \On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem." It further explores Turing's life and impact. 2 Historic Background Before 1930, not much was defined about computability theory because it was an unexplored field (Soare 4). From the late 1930s to the early 1940s, mathematicians worked to develop formal definitions of computable functions and sets, and applying those definitions to solve logic problems, but these problems were not new. It was not until the 1800s that mathematicians began to set an axiomatic system of math. This created problems like how to define computability. In the 1800s, Cantor defined what we call today \naive set theory" which was inconsistent. During the height of his mathematical period, Hilbert defended Cantor but suggested an axiomatic system be established, and characterized the Entscheidungsproblem as the \fundamental problem of mathemat- ical logic" (Soare 227). The Entscheidungsproblem was proposed by David Hilbert and Wilhelm Ackerman in 1928. The Entscheidungsproblem, or Decision Problem, states that given all the axioms of math, there is an algorithm that can tell if a proposition is provable. During the 1930s, Alonzo Church, Stephen Kleene, Kurt G¨odel,and Alan Turing worked to formalize how we compute anything from real numbers to sets of functions to solve the Entscheidungsproblem.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Choice
    THE AXIOM OF CHOICE THOMAS J. JECH State University of New York at Bufalo and The Institute for Advanced Study Princeton, New Jersey 1973 NORTH-HOLLAND PUBLISHING COMPANY - AMSTERDAM LONDON AMERICAN ELSEVIER PUBLISHING COMPANY, INC. - NEW YORK 0 NORTH-HOLLAND PUBLISHING COMPANY - 1973 AN Rights Reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the Copyright owner. Library of Congress Catalog Card Number 73-15535 North-Holland ISBN for the series 0 7204 2200 0 for this volume 0 1204 2215 2 American Elsevier ISBN 0 444 10484 4 Published by: North-Holland Publishing Company - Amsterdam North-Holland Publishing Company, Ltd. - London Sole distributors for the U.S.A. and Canada: American Elsevier Publishing Company, Inc. 52 Vanderbilt Avenue New York, N.Y. 10017 PRINTED IN THE NETHERLANDS To my parents PREFACE The book was written in the long Buffalo winter of 1971-72. It is an attempt to show the place of the Axiom of Choice in contemporary mathe- matics. Most of the material covered in the book deals with independence and relative strength of various weaker versions and consequences of the Axiom of Choice. Also included are some other results that I found relevant to the subject. The selection of the topics and results is fairly comprehensive, nevertheless it is a selection and as such reflects the personal taste of the author. So does the treatment of the subject. The main tool used throughout the text is Cohen’s method of forcing.
    [Show full text]
  • First-Order Logic in a Nutshell Syntax
    First-Order Logic in a Nutshell 27 numbers is empty, and hence cannot be a member of itself (otherwise, it would not be empty). Now, call a set x good if x is not a member of itself and let C be the col- lection of all sets which are good. Is C, as a set, good or not? If C is good, then C is not a member of itself, but since C contains all sets which are good, C is a member of C, a contradiction. Otherwise, if C is a member of itself, then C must be good, again a contradiction. In order to avoid this paradox we have to exclude the collec- tion C from being a set, but then, we have to give reasons why certain collections are sets and others are not. The axiomatic way to do this is described by Zermelo as follows: Starting with the historically grown Set Theory, one has to search for the principles required for the foundations of this mathematical discipline. In solving the problem we must, on the one hand, restrict these principles sufficiently to ex- clude all contradictions and, on the other hand, take them sufficiently wide to retain all the features of this theory. The principles, which are called axioms, will tell us how to get new sets from already existing ones. In fact, most of the axioms of Set Theory are constructive to some extent, i.e., they tell us how new sets are constructed from already existing ones and what elements they contain. However, before we state the axioms of Set Theory we would like to introduce informally the formal language in which these axioms will be formulated.
    [Show full text]
  • 2 Axiomatic Systems
    Hawraa Abbas Almurieb Geometry 2 Axiomatic Systems 2.1. Introduction to Axiomatic Systems We need undefined terms for any axiomatic system to build the axioms upon them. Which are basic worlds or things for the system. 2.1.1 Definitions of the system are all other technical terms of the system are ultimately defined by means of the undefined terms. 2.1.2. An axiom is a list of statements dealing with undefined terms and definitions that are chosen to remain unproved. 2.1.3. A theorem is any statement that can be proven using logical deduction from the axioms. 2.1.4. An axiomatic System is a list of axioms and theorems that dealing with undefined terms. Example: Committees Undefined terms: committee, member Axiom 1: Each committee is a set of three members. Axiom 2: Each member is on exactly two committees. Axiom 3: No two members may be together on more than one committee. Axiom 4: There is at least one committee. Chapter Two: Axiomatic Systems 1 | P a g e Hawraa Abbas Almurieb Geometry 2.1.5. A model for an axiomatic system is a way to define the undefined terms so that the axioms are true. Sometimes it is easy to find a model for an axiomatic system, and sometimes it is more difficult. Example: Members Ali, Abbas, Ahmed, Huda, Zainab, Sara. Committees {Ali, Abbas, Ahmed} {Ali, Huda, Zainab} {Abbas, Huda, Sara} {Ahmed, Zainab, Sara} 2.1.6.An axiom is called independent if it cannot be proven from the other axioms. Example: Consider Axiom 1 from the Committee system.
    [Show full text]
  • Randomness in Arithmetic and the Decline and Fall of Reductionism in Pure Mathematics
    RANDOMNESS IN ARITHMETIC AND THE DECLINE AND FALL OF REDUCTIONISM IN PURE MATHEMATICS IBM Research Report RC-18532 November 1992 arXiv:chao-dyn/9304002v1 7 Apr 1993 G. J. Chaitin Lecture given Thursday 22 October 1992 at a Mathematics – Computer Science Colloquium at the University of New Mexico. The lecture was videotaped; this is an edited transcript. 1. Hilbert on the axiomatic method Last month I was a speaker at a symposium on reductionism at Cam- bridge University where Turing did his work. I’d like to repeat the talk 1 2 I gave there and explain how my work continues and extends Turing’s. Two previous speakers had said bad things about David Hilbert. So I started by saying that in spite of what you might have heard in some of the previous lectures, Hilbert was not a twit! Hilbert’s idea is the culmination of two thousand years of math- ematical tradition going back to Euclid’s axiomatic treatment of ge- ometry, going back to Leibniz’s dream of a symbolic logic and Russell and Whitehead’s monumental Principia Mathematica. Hilbert’s dream was to once and for all clarify the methods of mathematical reasoning. Hilbert wanted to formulate a formal axiomatic system which would encompass all of mathematics. Formal Axiomatic System −→ −→ −→ Hilbert emphasized a number of key properties that such a formal axiomatic system should have. It’s like a computer programming lan- guage. It’s a precise statement about the methods of reasoning, the postulates and the methods of inference that we accept as mathemati- cians.
    [Show full text]
  • Axiomatic Systems
    Eucliean and Non-Euclidean Geometry – Fall 2007 Dr. Hamblin Axiomatic Systems An axiomatic system is a list of undefined terms together with a list of statements (called “axioms”) that are presupposed to be “true.” A theorem is any statement that can be proven using logical deduction from the axioms. Examples Here are some examples of axiomatic systems. Committees Undefined terms: committee, member Axiom 1: Each committee is a set of three members. Axiom 2: Each member is on exactly two committees. Axiom 3: No two members may be together on more than one committee. Axiom 4: There is at least one committee. Monoid Undefined terms: element, product of two elements Axiom 1: Given two elements x and y, the product of and , denoted , is a uniquely defined element. Axiom 2: Given elements , , and , the equation is always true. Axiom 3: There is an element , called the identity, such that and for all elements . Silliness Undefined terms: silly, dilly. Axiom 1: Each silly is a set of exactly three dillies. Axiom 2: There are exactly four dillies. Axiom 3: Each dilly is contained in a silly. Axiom 4: No dilly is contained in more than one silly. Notice that in the second example, the axioms defined a new term (“identity”). This isn’t an undefined term because the axiom includes a definition. Also, these axioms refer to basic set theory that you learned in Discrete Math. For our purposes, we will assume all of those basic set theory terms are known. It is possible to view set theory itself as another axiomatic system, but that is beyond the scope of this course.
    [Show full text]
  • First-Order Logic in a Nutshell
    Chapter 2 First-Order Logic in a Nutshell Mathematicians devised signs, not separate from matter except in essence, yet distant from it. These were points, lines, planes, solids, numbers, and countless other characters, which are depicted on paper with certain colours, and they used these in place of the things sym- bolised. GIOSEFFO ZARLINO Le Istitutioni Harmoniche, 1558 First-Order Logic is the system of Symbolic Logic concerned not only with rep- resenting the logical relations between sentences or propositions as wholes (like Propositional Logic), but also with their internal structure in terms of subject and predicate. First-Order Logic can be considered as a kind of language which is dis- tinguished from higher-order languages in that it does not allow quantification over subsets of the domain of discourse or other objects of higher type. Nevertheless, First-Order Logic is strong enough to formalise all of Set Theory and thereby vir- tually all of Mathematics. In other words, First-Order Logic is an abstract language that in one particular case might be the language of Group Theory, and in another case might be the language of Set Theory. The goal of this brief introductionto First-Order Logic is to illustrate and summarise some of the basic concepts of this language and to show how it is applied to fields like Group Theory and Peano Arithmetic (two theories which will accompany us for a while). Syntax: The Grammar of Symbols Like any other written language, First-Order Logic is based on an alphabet, which consists of the following symbols: 11 12 2 First-Order Logic in a Nutshell (a) Variables such as v0, v1, x, y, .
    [Show full text]