View/Open: Bouhafa Georgetown 0076D 13445.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

View/Open: Bouhafa Georgetown 0076D 13445.Pdf NATURAL JUSTICE UNDER THE SCOPE OF RHETORIC : THE WRITTEN AND THE UNWRITTEN LAWS IN IBN RUSHD ’S POLITICAL AND LEGAL PHILOSOPHY A Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Georgetown University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Islamic studies By Feriel Bouhafa, M.A. Washington, D.C. July 8, 2016 Copyright 2016 by Feriel Bouhafa All Right Reserved ii To the memory of M. Chaker Bouhafa iii NATURAL JUSTICE UNDER THE SCOPE OF RHETORIC : THE WRITTEN AND THE UNWRITTEN LAWS IN IBN RUSHD ’S POLITICAL AND LEGAL PHILOSOPHY Feriel Bouhafa, M.A. Thesis Adviser: Emma Gannagé, Ph.D. ABSTRACT This dissertation explores the works of Ibn Rushd and identifies an appropriation of Aristotle’s concept of natural justice, paying attention to the distinction he makes between the written laws ( al-sunan al-maktūba ) and the unwritten laws ( al-sunan ghayr al-maktūba ) in his Middle Commentary on Aristotle’s Rhetoric (Talkhīṣ al-khaṭāba ), and parallel views in his legal works. My study argues that Ibn Rushd’s legal and political philosophy advances a concrete view of Aristotle‘s natural justice, which anchors ethic in the normative framework of sharī‘a . Ibn Rushd’s conception of natural justice, I propose, is best evidenced in his view on the political and epistemological value of rhetoric and its relation to law. I further argue that Ibn Rushd asserts the necessity of rhetoric to ensure justice—which he considers key to political stability. Ibn Rushd, therefore, constructs his conception of natural justice under the epistemological scope of rhetoric, through the prism of the unexamined opinion ( bādi’ al-ra’y al- mushtarak ), a quasi-rational view of instinct opinion shared among people. I locate this discussion within Ibn Rushd’s views of the written laws and the unwritten laws and their relation to natural justice. The thesis proposes that Ibn Rushd identifies two modes for natural justice: in potentiality , based on natural human inclination, accessible to the masses; and in actuality , linked to the elite, and only accessible to qualified jurists, through ijtihād. Ibn iv Rushd successfully bridges this proposed divide between the masses and the elite, through setting public approval as a condition: he grounds the concept of natural justice in the unexamined opinion, thus providing the epistemological criteria for the qualified jurist to frame arguments curated to garner public approval. Finally, I show how Ibn Rushd contextualizes his conception of the Stagirite’s natural justice within sharī‘a, which, he contends, encompasses both the written laws and the unwritten laws: the written, such as the ḥudūd punishment; and the unwritten associated with the Qur’anic ethical concepts and the objectives of the law grounded in the different legal precepts ( al- qawā‘id al-fiqhiyya ). The importance of my contribution lies in challenging the dominant position, which has long held that Ibn Rushd equates sharī‘a with truth, instead I underline how Ibn Rushd presents the practical efficiency of sharī‘a as the sole ground to its evidence. In advancing novel discussions and unfolding unexamined connections, the thesis of my work revisits this correlation to underline the connection between sharī‘a and practical philosophy. v ACKNOWLEDGEMENT Working toward the completion of the present dissertation has been a stimulating journey through which I landed in several places, Washington, D.C., Cambridge MA, Beirut, Doha, Bern, and finally Freiburg im Breisgau. This also meant that all along this journey, I was fortunate to meet many people who have been a major source of support and to whom I owe much appreciation and gratitude. In Washington D.C, I would like to first express the deepest gratitude to my co- advisors Professor Emma Gannagé and Professor Felicitas Opwis. I consider myself immensely privileged to have had such an excellent team, which not only helped me tackle the complex interdisciplinary nature of my research between philosophy and the study of Islamic jurisprudence, but also provided me with inspiration, patience, and steadfast encouragement as I hurdled all the obstacles in the completion this research work. I would also like to thank the family in the Arabic Islamic Studies Department at Georgetown for being such a great support through the years, with a special thank to Meriem Tikue. I would also take the opportunity to thank Professor Ahmad Dallal for his inspiration. I remain indebted to two members we have lost, Professor Barbara Stowasser, a great scholar and mentor, and Nancy Farley, a true friend. I would like to extend my gratitude to Prince Alwaleed bin Talal Center for Muslim Christian understanding for their financial support to this project. In Cambridge, I would like to thank the Center for Middle Eastern Studies at Harvard for hosting me as a visiting fellow in 2012-2013. I specially would like to thank Professor Baber Johansen for being part of my advisory committee, and for offering me valuable insight and guidance. I would like to extend my thanks to members of the Harvard community, especially Professor Noah Feldman and Professor Khaled El- Rouayheb for their support and engagement. From my stay in Beirut, I would like to thank the Orient Institut Beirut for hosting me and providing me with both accommodation and financial support during the summer of 2013. I would like to thank Professor Stefan Leder for his encouragement and his fruitful engagement with my research. My time in Beirut was also valuable, as I was fortunate to have the opportunity to meet with Professor Maroun Aouad, whose expertise and work on Ibn Rushd have been crucial for my own dissertation and to whom I owe my deepest thank. From my time in Qatar, I would like to take the chance to thank the School of Foreign Service in Qatar for all the support and encouragement. A special thank goes to my friend and colleague Abdul Rahman Chameseddine. As to Bern, I would like to thank the Institut für Islamwissenschaft und Neuere Orientalische Philologie and specially Professor Reinhard Schulze and Professor Anke von Kügelgen for their help and support mainly in providing me with working space and access to Library during my several visits, and also Almuth Lahmann for her fruitful exchanges and friendly support . I would like to thank the Open Society whose grant helped me travel to Florence and Istanbul to consult Averroes’ manuscripts. vii Lastly, in Freiburg, my new home, I would like to express my deepest gratitude to Professor Nadja Germann, for her support and for being part of my advisory committee as well her constant encouragement during the last phase of writing my dissertation. A special thank also to my friend and colleague Professor Zied Bou Akl for his valuable support and his generosity sharing his works and ideas. Also I would like to thank the whole Research Lidiac team at Freiburg University, especially my friends and colleagues Noel Rivera and Mostafa Najafi for all the support during my relocation to Freiburg. My deepest appreciation goes to my many friends scattered around the globe: Enass Khanssa who have been a great source of inspiration, support and friendship. Salam for being a great friend in good and dire times. Delphine, Edouard, Stanislas, Samarcande and Solenn for letting me be part of their family through my years in Washington. A special thank to my friend Adrien for his patient and compassion. Emre Cicek, Teymour Morel, Jawdath Jabbour, Dina K. Hussein, Pegah Zohouri, Anas Abdennadher and Till Grallert, to all of you goes my gratitude. Finally, I hope to extend my thank to my family for their love, my beloved deceased father Chacker to whom I dedicate this dissertation, my mother Fatma, and to Kadem, Olfa, Rym, Khelil, Emna and my uncle Okba. And to my new family Susanne, Wolfgang, and Jakob, thank you. My utmost gratitude and love goes to my friend and partner Johannes. viii TABLE OF CONTENTS Introduction 1 Chapter One: Revisiting the appropriation of Aristotle’s natural justice in Ibn Rushd’s thought 11 Overview of Aristotle’s ethical views 13 Aristotle’s ethical views in Rhetoric , Nichomachean Ethics , and Politics 14 Natural right or natural justice? 23 Ibn Rushd ‘s appropriation of Aristotelian ethical views 27 Earlier approaches to Ibn Rushd’s ethical views in his political philosophy 34 The Straussian Platonic view on sharī‘a in Ibn Rushd’s political views 35 Claims on Ibn Rushd’s “Platonization” of Aristotle’s Rhetoric 40 On Plato’s and Aristotle’s view on Rhetoric 41 The ground for Ibn Rushd’s “Platonization” of Aristotle’s Rhetoric and its ramification for his view of ethics 44 My approach 51 Chapter Two: Rhetoric as a meta-discourse on law, opinion, and Islamic modes of argumentation 57 Overview of rhetoric in the Arabic context 58 The reception of Aristotle’s Rhetoric under the Organon 59 Khaṭāba and Arabic sciences 63 A synopsis of Ibn Rushd’s Short Commentary to Rhetoric and Middle Commentary to Rhetoric 66 The politico-legal role of rhetoric 69 Ibn Rushd’s definition of rhetoric 69 The political utility of rhetoric 73 The necessity of rhetoric for the purpose of justice 83 The logical aim of rhetoric and its expansive scope 90 The logical aim of rhetoric and its expansion 91 Ibn Rushd’s conception of assent 92 The expansion of the scope of assent 97 The social epistemological criteria of the rhetorical material 107 Defining the unexamined opinion (bādi’al-ra’y al-mushtarak ) 108 The acceptance of maḥmūdāt under rhetoric 112 Topics: Arguing for contraries 116 Relation to logical arts 120 Concluding remarks: Rhetoric as a meta-discourse on opinion, islamic modes of argumentation, politics, and justice 125 Chapter Three: Natural justice under rhetoric 127 The challenge to justice 128 x The fallibility of human reasoning 128 The lawgiver’s undue generalization 132 The contingency of matter 135 Ibn Rushd’s conception of natural justice 140 The written and the unwritten laws 140 Justice under the written and the unwritten laws 146 Ibn Rushd’s construal of Aristotle’s natural justice 151 Natural justice: Masses vs.
Recommended publications
  • The Black Platonism of David Lindsay
    Volume 19 Number 2 Article 3 Spring 3-15-1993 Encounter Darkness: The Black Platonism of David Lindsay Adelheid Kegler Follow this and additional works at: https://dc.swosu.edu/mythlore Part of the Children's and Young Adult Literature Commons Recommended Citation Kegler, Adelheid (1993) "Encounter Darkness: The Black Platonism of David Lindsay," Mythlore: A Journal of J.R.R. Tolkien, C.S. Lewis, Charles Williams, and Mythopoeic Literature: Vol. 19 : No. 2 , Article 3. Available at: https://dc.swosu.edu/mythlore/vol19/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Mythopoeic Society at SWOSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Mythlore: A Journal of J.R.R. Tolkien, C.S. Lewis, Charles Williams, and Mythopoeic Literature by an authorized editor of SWOSU Digital Commons. An ADA compliant document is available upon request. For more information, please contact [email protected]. To join the Mythopoeic Society go to: http://www.mythsoc.org/join.htm Mythcon 51: A VIRTUAL “HALFLING” MYTHCON July 31 - August 1, 2021 (Saturday and Sunday) http://www.mythsoc.org/mythcon/mythcon-51.htm Mythcon 52: The Mythic, the Fantastic, and the Alien Albuquerque, New Mexico; July 29 - August 1, 2022 http://www.mythsoc.org/mythcon/mythcon-52.htm Abstract Characterizes Lindsay as a “belated symbolist” whose characters are “personifications of ontological values.” Uses Neoplatonic “references to transcendence” but his imagery and technique do not suggest a positive view of transcendence. Additional Keywords Lindsay, David—Neoplatonism; Lindsay, David—Philosophy; Lindsay, David. A Voyage to Arcturus; Neoplatonism in David Lindsay This article is available in Mythlore: A Journal of J.R.R.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine on Knowledge
    Augustine on Knowledge Divine Illumination as an Argument Against Scepticism ANITA VAN DER BOS RMA: RELIGION & CULTURE Rijksuniversiteit Groningen Research Master Thesis s2217473, April 2017 FIRST SUPERVISOR: dr. M. Van Dijk SECOND SUPERVISOR: dr. dr. F.L. Roig Lanzillotta 1 2 Content Augustine on Knowledge ........................................................................................................................ 1 Acknowledgements ................................................................................................................................ 4 Preface .................................................................................................................................................... 5 Abstract ................................................................................................................................................... 6 Introduction ............................................................................................................................................ 7 The life of Saint Augustine ................................................................................................................... 9 The influence of the Contra Academicos .......................................................................................... 13 Note on the quotations ........................................................................................................................ 14 1. Scepticism ........................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • 2. Aristotle's Concept of the State
    Page No.13 2. Aristotle's concept of the state Olivera Z. Mijuskovic Full Member International Association of Greek Philosophy University of Athens, Greece ORCID iD: http://orcid.org/0000-0001-5950-7146 URL: http://worldphilosophynetwork.weebly.com E-Mail: [email protected] Abstract: In contrast to a little bit utopian standpoint offered by Plato in his teachings about the state or politeia where rulers aren`t “in love with power but in virtue”, Aristotle's teaching on the same subject seems very realistic and pragmatic. In his most important writing in this field called "Politics", Aristotle classified authority in the form of two main parts: the correct authority and moose authority. In this sense, correct forms of government are 1.basileus, 2.aristocracy and 3.politeia. These forms of government are based on the common good. Bad or moose forms of government are those that are based on the property of an individual or small governmental structures and they are: 1.tiranny, 2.oligarchy and 3.democracy. Also, Aristotle's political thinking is not separate from the ethical principles so he states that the government should be reflected in the true virtue that is "law" or the "golden mean". Keywords: Government; stat; , virtue; democracy; authority; politeia; golden mean. Vol. 4 No. 4 (2016) Issue- December ISSN 2347-6869 (E) & ISSN 2347-2146 (P) Aristotle's concept of the state by Olivera Z. Mijuskovic Page no. 13-20 Page No.14 Aristotle's concept of the state 1.1. Aristotle`s “Politics” Politics in its defined form becomes affirmed by the ancient Greek world.
    [Show full text]
  • INTRODUCTION 1. Medical Humanism and Natural Philosophy
    INTRODUCTION 1. Medical Humanism and Natural Philosophy The Renaissance was one of the most innovative periods in Western civi- lization.1 New waves of expression in fijine arts and literature bloomed in Italy and gradually spread all over Europe. A new approach with a strong philological emphasis, called “humanism” by historians, was also intro- duced to scholarship. The intellectual fecundity of the Renaissance was ensured by the intense activity of the humanists who were engaged in collecting, editing, translating and publishing the ancient literary heri- tage, mostly in Greek and Latin, which had hitherto been scarcely read or entirely unknown to the medieval world. The humanists were active not only in deciphering and interpreting these “newly recovered” texts but also in producing original writings inspired by the ideas and themes they found in the ancient sources. Through these activities, Renaissance humanist culture brought about a remarkable moment in Western intel- lectual history. The effforts and legacy of those humanists, however, have not always been appreciated in their own right by historians of philoso- phy and science.2 In particular, the impact of humanism on the evolution of natural philosophy still awaits thorough research by specialists. 1 By “Renaissance,” I refer to the period expanding roughly from the fijifteenth century to the beginning of the seventeenth century, when the humanist movement begun in Italy was difffused in the transalpine countries. 2 Textbooks on the history of science have often minimized the role of Renaissance humanism. See Pamela H. Smith, “Science on the Move: Recent Trends in the History of Early Modern Science,” Renaissance Quarterly 62 (2009), 345–75, esp.
    [Show full text]
  • A Confucian Defense of Shame: Morality, Self-Cultivation, and the Dangers of Shamelessness
    religions Article Article Article A ConfucianA Confucian Defense Defense of Shame: of Shame: Morality, Morality, Self-Cultivation, Self-Cultivation, A Confucian Defense of Shame: Morality, Self-Cultivation, and theand Dangers the Dangers of Shamelessness of Shamelessness and the Dangers of Shamelessness Mark BerksonMark Berkson Mark Berkson Department of Religion,Department Hamline of Religion, University, Hamline St. Paul, University, MN 55104, St. USA;Paul, [email protected] 55104, USA; [email protected] Department of Religion, Hamline University, St. Paul, MN 55104, USA; [email protected] Abstract: ManyAbstract: philosophers Many and philosophers scholars in and the scholars West have in the a negative West have view a negative of shame. view In muchof shame. In much of Abstract: Many philosophers and scholars in the West have a negative view of shame.of post-classical In much ofpost-classical Western ethical Western thought, ethical shame thought, is compared shame is negativelycompared negatively with guilt, with as shame guilt, isas shame is asso- post-classical Western ethical thought, shame is compared negatively with guilt, asassociated shame is asso- withciated the “outer”, with the how “outer”, one appears how one before appears others before (and othe thusrs is (and merely thus a is matter merely of a “face”), matter of “face”), and ciated with the “outer”, how one appears before others (and thus is merely a matterand of “face”), guilt is and associatedguilt is associated with the “inner”with the realm “inner” of therealm conscience of the conscience and soul. and Anthropologists soul. Anthropologists and and philoso- guilt is associated with the “inner” realm of the conscience and soul.
    [Show full text]
  • Presidential Address
    Empowering Philosophy Christia Mercer COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY Presidential Address delivered at the one hundred sixteenth Eastern Division meeting of the American Philosophical Association in Philadelphia, PA, on January 10, 2020. The main goal of my presidential address in January 2020 was to show that philosophy’s past offers a means to empower its present. I hoped to encourage colleagues to make the philosophy we teach and practice more inclusive (both textually and topically) and to adopt a more public- facing engagement with our discipline. As I add these introductory remarks to my January lecture, it is June 2020 and the need to empower philosophy has never seemed more urgent. We’ve witnessed both the tragic death of George Floyd and the popular uprising of a diverse group of Americans in response to the ongoing violence against Black lives. Many white Americans—and many philosophers—have begun to realize that their inattentiveness to matters of diversity and inclusivity must now be seen as more than mere negligence. Recent demonstrations frequently contain signs that make the point succinctly: “Silence is violence.” A central claim of my January lecture was that philosophy’s status quo is no longer tenable. Even before the pandemic slashed university budgets and staff, our employers were cutting philosophy programs, enrollments were shrinking, and jobs were increasingly hard to find. Despite energetic attempts on the part of many of our colleagues to promote a more inclusive approach to our research and teaching, the depressing truth remains:
    [Show full text]
  • BY PLATO• ARISTOTLE • .AND AQUINAS I
    i / REF1,l!;CTit.>NS ON ECONOMIC PROBLEMS / BY PLATO• ARISTOTLE • .AND AQUINAS ii ~FLECTIONS ON ECONO:MIC PROBLEMS 1 BY PLA'I'O, ARISTOTLE, JJJD AQUINAS, By EUGENE LAIDIBEL ,,SWEARINGEN Bachelor of Science Oklahoma Agricultural and Mechanical Collage Stillwater, Oklahoma 1941 Submitted to the Depertmeut of Economics Oklahoma Agricultural and Mechanical College In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF SCIENCE 1948 iii f.. 'I. I ···· i·: ,\ H.: :. :· ··: ! • • ~ ' , ~ • • !·:.· : i_ ·, 1r 1i1. cr~~rJ3t L l: i{ ,\ I~ Y , '•T •)() 1 0 ,1 8 API-'HOV~D BY: .J ,.· 1.., J l.;"t .. ---- -··- - ·- ______.,.. I 7 -.. JI J ~ L / \ l v·~~ u ' ~) (;_,LA { 7 {- ' r ~ (\.7 __\ _. ...A'_ ..;f_ ../-_" ...._!)_.... ..." ___ ......._ ·;...;;; ··-----/ 1--.,i-----' ~-.._.._ :_..(__,,---- ....... Member of the Report Committee 1..j lj:,;7 (\ - . "'·- -· _ .,. ·--'--C. r, .~-}, .~- Q_ · -~ Q.- 1Head of the Department . · ~ Dean of the Graduate School 502 04 0 .~ -,. iv . r l Preface The purpose and plan of this report are set out in the Introduction. Here, I only wish to express my gratitude to Professor Russell H. Baugh who has helped me greatly in the preparation of this report by discussing the various subjects as they were in the process of being prepared. I am very much indebted to Dr. Harold D. Hantz for his commentaries on the report and for the inspiration which his classes in Philosophy have furnished me as I attempted to correlate some of the material found in these two fields, Ecor!.Omics and Philosophy. I should like also to acknowledge that I owe my first introduction into the relationships of Economics and Philosophy to Dean Raymond Thomas, and his com~ents on this report have been of great value.
    [Show full text]
  • 7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul
    7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul Roger Crisp n the recent revival of interest in Aristotelian ethics, relatively little attention has been paid to the virtue of greatness of soul (megalopsuchia). This is partly Ibecause of the focus on the more structurally central concepts of Aristotle’s theory, in particular happiness (eudaimonia) and virtue (aret¯e). But in fact a study of greatness of soul can reveal important insights into the overall shape of Aristotelian ethics, including the place of external goods and luck in the virtuous life, and the significance of “the noble” (to kalon). Further, Aristotle describes the great-souled person in more detail than any other, and calls greatness of soul a “sort of crown of the virtues” (NE IV.3.1124a1–2). Many have found aspects of the portrait of the great-souled person in the Nicomachean Ethics repellent or absurd, but that is no good reason for the student of Aristotle to shy away from it. In this chapter, I shall elucidate Aristotle’s account of greatness of soul, addressing some puzzles internal to that account and bringing out its place in, and implications for, the ethics of Aristotle and of those modern writers influenced by him. Greatness of Soul as a Virtue To understand greatness of soul as an Aristotelian virtue requires first understand- ing Aristotle’s conception of virtue itself. Aristotle distinguishes virtues into two classes – intellectual virtues and virtues of character – corresponding to distinct aspects of the human soul (NE I.13). Greatness of soul is a virtue of character, though, like all such virtues, it requires its possessor to have the intellectual virtue of practical wisdom (phron¯esis; NE VI.13).
    [Show full text]
  • In Defense of the Development of Augustine's Doctrine of Grace By
    In Defense of the Development of Augustine’s Doctrine of Grace by Laban Omondi Agisa Submitted to the faculty of the School of Theology of the University of the South in Partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Sacred Theology January 2020 Sewanee, Tennessee Approved ____________________________ _______________ Adviser Date ____________________________ _______________ Second Adviser Date 2 DECLARATION I declare that this is my original work and has not been presented in any other institution for consideration of any certification. This work has been complemented by sources duly acknowledged and cited using Chicago Manual Style. Signature Date 3 ACKNOWLEDGEMENT My study of theology was initiated in 2009 by the then Provost of St. Stephens Cathedral, Nairobi, the late Ven. Canon John Ndung’u who was a great encouragement to me. This was further made possible through my bishop the Rt. Rev. Joel Waweru and the Rev. Geoffrey Okapisi who were sources of inspiration. My studies at Carlile College (Church Army Africa) and St. Paul’s University laid a strong theological foundation and I appreciate among others the influence of the Rev. Dr. John Kiboi who introduced me to Philosophy, Systematic Theology, Ethics, and African Christian Theology that eventually became the foundation for my studies at the University of the South. I also appreciate the encouragement of my lecturers Mrs. Tabitha Waweru and Dr. Scholarstica Githinji during my Study of Education at Kenya Technical Trainers College and at Daystar University respectively. My interest in this topic came as a result of many sittings with two professors at the University of the South, Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • The Agent Intellect As" Form for Us" and Averroes's. Critique of Al-Farabi
    Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía ISSN: 0188-6649 [email protected] Universidad Panamericana México Taylor, Richard C. The Agent Intellect as "form for us" and Averroes's. Critique of al-Farabi Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía, núm. 29, 2005, pp. 29-51 Universidad Panamericana Distrito Federal, México Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=323027318003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative The Agent Intellect as "form for us" and Averroes's Critique of al-FarabT Richard C. Taylor Marquette University This article explicates Averroes's understanding of human knowing and abstraction in this three commentaries on Aristotle's De Anima. While Averroes's views on the nature of the human material intellect changes through the three commentaries until he reaches is famous view of the unity of the material intellect as one for all human beings, his view of the agent intellect as 'form for us' is sustained throughout these works. In his Long Commentary on the De Anima he reveals his dependence on al-Farabi for this notion and provides a detailed critique of the Farabian notion that the agent intellect is 'form for us' only as agent cause, not as our true formal cause. Although Averroes argues that the agent intellect must somehow be intrinsic to us as our form since humans 2tieper se rational and undertake acts of knowing by will, his view is shown to rest on an equivocal use of the notion of formal cause.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Predication1
    António Pedro Mesquita University of Lisbon Aristotle on Predication1 Abstract: Predication is a complex entity in Aristotelian thought. The aim of the present essay is to account for this complexity, making explicit the diverse forms it assumes. To this end, we turn to a crucial chapter of the Posterior Analytics (1 22), where, in the most com- plete and developed manner within the corpus, Aristotle proceeds to systematize this topic. From the analysis, it will become apparent that predication can assume, generically, five forms: 1) the predication of essence (τὸ αὐτῷ εἶναι κατηγορεῖσθαι), that is of the genus and the specific difference; 2) essential predication (τό ἐν τῷ τί ἐστι κατηγορεῖσθαι), that is either of the genus or of the differences (or their genera); 3) the predication of accidents per se and 4) simple accidents (ὡς συμβεβηκότα κατηγορεῖσθαι); 5) accidental predication (κατὰ συμβεβηκὸς κατηγορεῖσθαι). However, only types 2–4 are forms of strict predication (ἁπλῶς). In effect, the “pre- dication” of essence is not a genuine predication, but a formula for identity, constituting, technically, the statement of the essence of the subject (or its definition). On the other hand, accidental “predication” can only be conceived of as such equivocally, since it results from a linguistic accident through which the ontological subject of the attribution suffers a displacement to the syntactic position of the predicate, which is not, by nature, its own. In neither case does the attribution bring about any legitimate predication. The study concludes with a discussion of Aristotle’s thesis according to which no subs- tance can be a predicate, which is implied by its notion of accidental predication, a thesis which has been – and in our opinion wrongly so – challenged in modern times.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle (384-322 BCE)
    Aristotle (384-322 BCE) The Pythagoreans, Socrates, and Plato attempted to reconcile an element of human freedom with material determinism and causal law. But the first major philosopher to argue convincingly for some indeterminism was probably Aristotle. This is despite the fact that he described a causal chain back to a prime mover or first cause, and he elaborated the four possible causes (material, efficient, formal, and final). In his Physics and Metaphysics Aristotle also said there were "accidents" caused by "chance(τυχή)." In his Physics, he clearly reckoned chance among the causes. Aristotle might have added chance as a fifth cause - an uncaused or self-caused cause - that happens when two causal chains come together by accident (συμβεβεκός). He noted that the early physicists found no place for chance among the causes. Aristotle knew that many decisions were quite predictable based on habit and character, but they were no less free if one's character itself and predictable habits were developed freely in the past and were changeable in the future. This was the view of Eastern philosophies and religions. Our karma has been determined by our past actions (even from past lives), and strongly influences our current actions, but we are free to improve our karma by future good actions. As a principal architect of the concept of causality, and the formulator of the four causes, Aristotle's statements on indefinite causes are perhaps his most significant contribution to freedom, in the world and in human decisions. In his Metaphysics, Aristotle makes the case for chance and uncaused causes (causa sui) and in the Nicomachean Ethics he shows our actions can be voluntary and "up to us" so that we can be morally responsible.
    [Show full text]