A Correspondence Theory of Truth

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Correspondence Theory of Truth A Correspondence Theory of Truth by Jay Newhard B.A., University of California, Santa Barbara, 1994 A.M., Brown University, 1997 A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy at Brown University Providence, Rhode Island May 2002 © Copyright 2002 by Jay Newhard This dissertation by Jay Michael Newhard is accepted in its present form by the Department of Philosophy as satisfying the dissertation requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Date__________ _________________________________ James Van Cleve, Director Recommended to the Graduate Council Date__________ _________________________________ Ernest Sosa, Reader Date__________ _________________________________ Nathan Salmon, Reader Approved by the Graduate Council Date__________ _________________________________ Peder J. Estrup Dean of the Graduate School and Research VITA Jay Newhard was born on 01 October 1967 in Allentown, Pennsylvania. He received a Bachelor of Science degree in Chemical Engineering in 1989, and a Master of Science degree in Chemical Engineering in 1991, both from the Pennsylvania State University. In 1994, he received a Bachelor of Arts degree in Philosophy from the University of California, Santa Barbara. In 1997, he received a Master of Arts degree from Brown University. He has taught at the University of Rhode Island, Augustana College, and Texas Tech University. PREFACE A number of philosophical theories of truth have been developed upon common pre- philosophical intuitions: a correspondence theory claims that true propositions correspond to reality; a coherence theory claims that true propositions cohere with other true propositions; and a pragmatic theory claims that true propositions are those (belief in) which are pragmatically useful. Each of these theories characterizes truth as a substantive property, but faces serious objections which render it apparently untenable. Dissatisfaction with these theories has led to theories developed upon more sophisticated philosophical considerations, foremost among them those that challenge whether truth is a substantive property. According to the simple theory of truth, truth is a property, but is simple, unanalyzable, and unsubstantive. The redundancy theory of truth claims that truth is not a property, and that the truth predicate is at best a grammatical expedient, and otherwise redundant. The disquotational, minimal, and prosentential theories are alike in holding that truth is not a substantive property, if a property at all. Other sophisticated attempts are the revision theory, which claims that truth is inherently circular, and the vagueness theory, which claims that the truth predicate is a vague predicate. The aim of this dissertation is to offer and defend a correspondence theory of truth. I must, therefore, not only show that all of these theories of truth, with the exception of the correspondence theory, are defective; I must also extricate the correspondence theory from the criticisms, now standard, which have been taken as decisive against it. In chapter 1, I examine the coherence, pragmatic, simple, redundancy, disquotational, minimal, and prosentential theories of truth, and argue of each that it is unsatisfactory. Special attention is paid to several versions of disquotationalism, whose plausibility has led to its fairly constant support since the pioneering work of Alfred Tarski, through that by W. V. Quine, and recently in the work of Paul Horwich. The discussion of the correspondence theory in chapter 1 is limited to a presentation of traditional versions of the theory and objections to them. A special problem facing a theory of truth is the Liar Paradox. In chapter 2, I discuss the Liar Paradox and the responses made to it by the above theories. The devastating effects of the Liar Paradox on these theories has led to the development of formal theories of truth, such as the revision theory, Kripke’s theory, and the vagueness theory, also examined in chapter 2. In chapter 3, I present and argue for the indexical correspondence theory of truth (the IC theory), a novel version of the correspondence theory according to which truth is a correspondence property sensitive to semantic context. This context-sensitivity explains why an ungrounded sentence does not express a proposition. Consequently, the IC theory accounts for the similarity between the Liar and Truth-Teller sentences, and provides a philosophically motivated immunity to the Liar Paradox, including empirical versions. Customized versions of the Liar Paradox besetting the IC theory are handled by its context-sensitivity, and by enforcing the distinction between truth and truth value. This same pair of considerations also yields solutions to Löb’s Paradox and to Grelling’s Paradox. Arguments similar to those given to defend the IC theory show that with one minor alteration, Kripke’s formal theory may be used to model the IC notion of truth. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I wish to thank my committee members James Van Cleve, Ernest Sosa, and Nathan Salmon for their help with this dissertation, and for their ferocious sense of justice in doing philosophy. Special and abounding thanks are due to Gary Gates and Matthew McGrath for their extremely generous and supportive discussions of the topics in this dissertation. Finally, I wish to thank a few friends whose devoted encouragement, sometimes with kind and sincere words, sometimes just from being their tremendous selves, was most certainly essential to completing this project: David R. Lachterman, John Peterson, André Ariew, George S. Newhard, Jason Kawall, Maria Elena Garcia, Max Deutsch, Alisa Hartz, and most lovingly of all, Rebecca Wee. CONTENTS Chapter 1: Theories of Truth 1 Section 1: Intuitions about the Nature of Truth 1 Section 2: Truth-Bearers 5 Section 3: Correspondence Theories of Truth 9 Section 3.1: Three Weak Correspondence Theories of Truth 10 Section 3.2: Three Strong Correspondence Theories of Truth 12 Section 3.3: Conclusions about Correspondence Theories of Truth 19 Section 4: Coherence Theories of Truth 20 Section 5: Pragmatic Theories of Truth 27 Section 6: Epistemic Theories of Truth 33 Section 7: The Simple Theory of Truth 36 Section 8: The Redundancy Theory of Truth 39 Section 9: Frege’s Theory of Truth 46 Section 10: Tarski’s Theory of Truth 51 Section 11: The Disquotational Theory of Truth 62 Section 12: The Minimalist Theory of Truth 85 Section 12.1: Horwich’s Minimalist Theory of Truth 89 Section 12.2: Sosa’s Finite Minimal Theory of Truth 92 Section 12.3: Horwich’s Minimalist Theory of Truth (slight return) 101 Section 13: The Prosentential Theory of Truth 104 Section 14: Deflationism 109 Section 15: Conclusions about Theories of Truth 113 Chapter 2: Truth Paradox 120 Section 16: The Liar Paradox & Truth Paradox 120 Section 17: Responses to Truth Paradox: Substantive Theories 129 Section 17.1: The Correspondence Theory’s Response 129 Section 17.2: The Coherence Theory’s Response 131 Section 17.3: The Pragmatic Theory’s Response 132 Section 17.4: The Epistemic Theory’s Response 133 Section 18: Responses to Truth Paradox: Deflationary Theories 134 Section 18.1: The Simple Theory’s Response 134 Section 18.2: The Redundancy Theory’s Response 135 Section 18.3: The Disquotational Theory’s Response 136 Section 18.4: The Minimalist Theory’s Response 137 Section 18.5: The Finite Minimal Theory’s Response 139 Section 19: Responses to Truth Paradox: Formal Theories 140 Section 19.1: Tarski’s Theory of Truth 140 Section 19.2: Kripke’s Theory of Truth 143 Section 19.3: Vagueness Theories of Truth 151 Section 19.4: The Revision Theory of Truth 157 Section 20: Context Theories of Truth and Their Responses 162 Section 21: Conclusions about Truth Paradox 168 Chapter 3: A Correspondence Theory of Truth 170 Section 22: The Semantics of the Truth Predicate 170 Section 22.1: Simple versus Complex Correspondence Theory of Truth 170 Section 22.2: Propositions, States of Affairs, and Facts 173 Section 22.3: Truth and Falsity 177 Section 22.4: Truth and Indexicality 185 Section 22.5: States of Affairs and Facts (slight return) 188 Section 22.6: Truth, Truth-Value, and Extension Assignments 192 Section 22.7: Löb’s Paradox 198 Section 22.8: Grelling’s Paradox 200 Section 22.9: The Liar Paradox and the Truth-Teller 203 Section 22.10: A Formal Model of the Truth Predicate 211 Section 23: Objections 217 Section 23.1: Admitting States of Affairs and Facts Multiplies Entities Beyond Necessity 217 Section 23.2: Mereological Worries about Facts 219 Section 23.3: A Partially Defined Predicate Does Not Express a Property 221 Section 23.4: Customized Truth Paradoxical Sentences 223 Section 24: Further Challenging Cases 228 Section 24.1: Analyticity 228 Section 24.2: Counterfactuals and Modalities 235 Section 24.3: Logically Complex Propositions 238 Section 24.4: Negative Facts 241 Section 24.5: True Negative Singular Existentials 244 Section 25: Conclusions 250 Bibliography 256 Table 1: Forms of Negation 125 Figure 1: Expression, Denotation, Correspondence, and Advertance 178 CHAPTER 1: THEORIES OF TRUTH Section 1: Intuitions about the Nature of Truth There are several intuitions commonly had about the nature of truth.1 The correspondence intuition is the intuition that true propositions2 accord with, or correspond to, the way that the world is. For example, if the proposition that Raphael is a painter is true, then Raphael is a painter. Further, the correspondence holds both ways: if Raphael is a painter, then the proposition that he is is true. Truth is often a very useful notion. The truth of the proposition that a certain painting I own was painted by Raphael is extremely important in selling it for its proper value, or perhaps refusing to sell it. The truth of the proposition that a certain syringe contains adrenaline and not a coagulant may be critical in saving a life. The intuition that truth is useful is the pragmatic intuition about the nature of truth.
Recommended publications
  • Logic in Action: Wittgenstein's Logical Pragmatism and the Impotence of Scepticism
    This is the final, pre-publication draft. Please cite only from published paper in Philosophical Investigations 26:2 (April 2003), 125-48. LOGIC IN ACTION: WITTGENSTEIN'S LOGICAL PRAGMATISM AND THE IMPOTENCE OF SCEPTICISM DANIÈLE MOYAL-SHARROCK UNIVERSITY OF GENEVA 1. The Many Faces of Certainty: Wittgenstein's Logical Pragmatism So I am trying to say something that sounds like pragmatism. (OC 422) In his struggle to uncover the nature of our basic beliefs, Wittgenstein depicts them variously in On Certainty: he thinks of them in propositional terms, in pictorial terms and in terms of acting. As propositions, they would be of a peculiar sort – a hybrid between a logical and an empirical proposition (OC 136, 309). These are the so-called 'hinge propositions' of On Certainty (OC 341). Wittgenstein also thinks of these beliefs as forming a picture, a World-picture – or Weltbild (OC 167). This is a step in the right (nonpropositional) direction, but not the ultimate step. Wittgenstein's ultimate and crucial depiction of our basic beliefs is in terms of a know-how, an attitude, a way of acting (OC 204). Here, he treads on pragmatist ground. But can Wittgenstein be labelled a pragmatist, having himself rejected the affiliation because of its utility implication? But you aren't a pragmatist? No. For I am not saying that a proposition is true if it is useful. (RPP I, 266) Wittgenstein resists affiliation with pragmatism because he does not want his use of use to be confused with the utility use of use. For him, it is not that a proposition is true if it is useful, but that use gives the proposition its sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Comments on “Facts About the Slingshot” by Gregory Landini Valia Allori
    Comments on “Facts about the Slingshot” by Gregory Landini Valia Allori This paper is very technical, so I will start my comments with a reconstruction of the arguments presented. Only at the end of this I will say what I think. I apologize in advance for any misinterpretation that I might have done. If I did, it was, of course, entirely unintentional. There is an argument against the correspondence theory of truth that, because of its combined simplicity and devastation, has been named the slingshot argument. According to the correspondence theory of truth a sentence is true iff there is a fact corresponding to it. In order to make sense, it seems that this theory must be able to differentiate between facts. The slingshot arguments, if sound, establish that every true sentence corresponds to the same fact, and therefore the corresponding theory of truth is doomed to failure. In his paper, Gregory argues that the slingshot argument is unsound. Let me just recapitulate what the argument says and my understanding of Gregory's argument against it. I will talk only about Davidson’s first version, for simplicity. The comments I will make will nonetheless apply to both versions. Let [p] be a shortcut for the locution “the fact that p”. Then it seems reasonable to assume that: 1) if to sentences p and q are identical, then [p]=[q] 2) if p and q describe the same thing (are co-denoting), then [p]=[q] for example: given S= “Cicero wrote Philippicae Oratione” and R=“Tully wrote Philippicae Oratione”, then [Cicero wrote Philippicae Oratione]=[Tully wrote Philippicae Oratione] 3) if p ad q are logically equivalent sentences, then [p]=[q] for example: S'= “ Plato=x: (x=Plato & S)” is logically equivalent to S, so [S]=[S'] Assumption number 2) is what Gregory calls the assumption of “constitution”: it amounts to say that the facts containing an object do not depend on the description provided.
    [Show full text]
  • A Bibliography of Works on Reflexivity
    A bibliography of works on reflexivity The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Peter Suber, A bibliography of works on reflexivity, in Self- Reference: Reflections on Reflexivity 259-362 (Peter Suber and Steven J. Bartlett 1987). Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:4725021 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Peter Suber A Bibliography of \ \'orks on Reflexivity "I don't have to quote anybody else to say what I could say for myself." --Anon. Section One: Introduction . ·:Reflexivity" is the generic name for all kinds and species of CJrcu~an.ty. It includes the self-reference of signs, the self-appplication of pnn~J_Ples and predicates. the self-justification and self-refutation of propositiOns and inferences the self-fulfillment and self-falsification of pre?!ctions, the self-creati~n and self-destruction of logical and legal Cntilie~, the self-augmentation and self-limitation of powers, circular reasonmg, circular causation. cvclic and spiral recurrence, feedback ?ste~s, mutu~li.ty, recipr~city: and organic. fonn. .It includes the sallaciOus, the VICious, the tnvial, and the quesuon beggmg, but also the ound, the benign, the useful and the inescapable. It ranges from the Pro. sa1c· to the numinous, from' the paradoxical to the self-evident, from ~Ience to religion.
    [Show full text]
  • UC San Diego Electronic Theses and Dissertations
    UC San Diego UC San Diego Electronic Theses and Dissertations Title Pluralism and Realism Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/2n611357 Author Evpak, Matthew Publication Date 2018 Peer reviewed|Thesis/dissertation eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA SAN DIEGO Pluralism and Realism A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy by Matthew Evpak Committee in charge: Professor Gila Sher, Chair Professor Samuel Buss Professor Andrew Kehler Professor Donald Rutherford Professor Clinton Tolley 2018 The Dissertation of Matthew Evpak is approved, and it is acceptable in quality and form for publication on microfilm and electronically: _____________________________________________________________________________ _____________________________________________________________________________ _____________________________________________________________________________ _____________________________________________________________________________ _____________________________________________________________________________ Chair University of California San Diego 2018 iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Signature Page ............................................................................................................................................................................................................ iii Table of Contents ....................................................................................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Slingshot Argument, Godel's Hesitation and Tarskian Semantics
    Arhat Virdi The slingshot argument, Godel’s hesitation and Tarskian semantics Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Virdi, Arhat (2009) The slingshot argument, Godel's hesitation and Tarskian semantics. Prolegomena, 8 (2). pp. 233-241. ISSN 1333-4395 © 2009 © 2009 Society for the Advancement of Philosophy, Zagreb This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/27063/ Available in LSE Research Online: Feb 2010 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final manuscript accepted version of the journal article, incorporating any revisions agreed during the peer review process. Some differences between this version and the published version may remain. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. The slingshot argument, Gödel’s hesitation and Tarskian semantics ARHAT VIRDI The slingshot argument is a reductio purporting to show that if there are facts at all there is only one to which all true statements correspond. If facts are not non-trivially individuable then this presumably must render the notion of fact and, by implication, theories such as the correspondence theory of truth incoherent.
    [Show full text]
  • Generalized Molecular Formulas in Logical Atomism
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy An Argument for Completely General Facts: Volume 9, Number 7 Generalized Molecular Formulas in Logical Editor in Chief Atomism Audrey Yap, University of Victoria Landon D. C. Elkind Editorial Board Annalisa Coliva, UC Irvine In his 1918 logical atomism lectures, Russell argued that there are Vera Flocke, Indiana University, Bloomington no molecular facts. But he posed a problem for anyone wanting Henry Jackman, York University to avoid molecular facts: we need truth-makers for generaliza- Frederique Janssen-Lauret, University of Manchester tions of molecular formulas, but such truth-makers seem to be Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts both unavoidable and to have an abominably molecular charac- Consuelo Preti, The College of New Jersey ter. Call this the problem of generalized molecular formulas. I clarify Marcus Rossberg, University of Connecticut the problem here by distinguishing two kinds of generalized Anthony Skelton, Western University molecular formula: incompletely generalized molecular formulas Mark Textor, King’s College London and completely generalized molecular formulas. I next argue that, if empty worlds are logically possible, then the model-theoretic Editors for Special Issues and truth-functional considerations that are usually given ad- Sandra Lapointe, McMaster University dress the problem posed by the first kind of formula, but not the Alexander Klein, McMaster University problem posed by the second kind. I then show that Russell’s Review Editors commitments in 1918 provide an answer to the problem of com- Sean Morris, Metropolitan State University of Denver pletely generalized molecular formulas: some truth-makers will Sanford Shieh, Wesleyan University be non-atomic facts that have no constituents.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism, Holism, and the Concept of Law
    Pragmatism, Holism, and the Concept of Law Adam Michał Dyrda* equally, most commonplace) accusations against a cer- Abstract tain legal theory is the ‘methodological objection’ (MO). In its general form, it is as follows: When discussing O. W. Holmes’s answer to the question What constitutes the law? Morton White underlines the (MO) The discussed theory fails because it uses the fact that Holmes’s inquiry didn’t focus on developing the wrong methodology and asks the wrong questions, concept of law. White states: ‘…Holmes said little in The which precludes the theory from reaching the right Path of the Law about the notion of legal authority, perhaps (adequate) conclusions. Without putting our ques- because he was interested not in what he called a “useless tions in the right way, we cannot grasp any substan- quintessence of all legal systems” but in “an accurate anat- tial answers, i.e. such answers that (at least) could omy of one”’. Such ambition (or lack of ambition) is charac- have a claim to adequacy.1 teristic of many pragmatic enterprises in the field of jurispru- dence. However, sometimes the opposition between legal It seems, then, that for researchers who use this argu- pragmatism and other legal theories is built upon a refer- ment against a particular theory T, the theory T fails on ence to the notion of the ‘nature’ or ‘essence’ of law. Many its own grounds because it asks the wrong questions legal philosophers who aim to reveal the very ‘nature of and, thus, receives inadequate answers. However, it is law’ (or ‘the concept of law’ as H.
    [Show full text]
  • Frege and the Logic of Sense and Reference
    FREGE AND THE LOGIC OF SENSE AND REFERENCE Kevin C. Klement Routledge New York & London Published in 2002 by Routledge 29 West 35th Street New York, NY 10001 Published in Great Britain by Routledge 11 New Fetter Lane London EC4P 4EE Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper. Copyright © 2002 by Kevin C. Klement All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any infomration storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. 10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Klement, Kevin C., 1974– Frege and the logic of sense and reference / by Kevin Klement. p. cm — (Studies in philosophy) Includes bibliographical references and index ISBN 0-415-93790-6 1. Frege, Gottlob, 1848–1925. 2. Sense (Philosophy) 3. Reference (Philosophy) I. Title II. Studies in philosophy (New York, N. Y.) B3245.F24 K54 2001 12'.68'092—dc21 2001048169 Contents Page Preface ix Abbreviations xiii 1. The Need for a Logical Calculus for the Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 3 Introduction 3 Frege’s Project: Logicism and the Notion of Begriffsschrift 4 The Theory of Sinn and Bedeutung 8 The Limitations of the Begriffsschrift 14 Filling the Gap 21 2. The Logic of the Grundgesetze 25 Logical Language and the Content of Logic 25 Functionality and Predication 28 Quantifiers and Gothic Letters 32 Roman Letters: An Alternative Notation for Generality 38 Value-Ranges and Extensions of Concepts 42 The Syntactic Rules of the Begriffsschrift 44 The Axiomatization of Frege’s System 49 Responses to the Paradox 56 v vi Contents 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Between Meaning and Essence Explaining Necessary Truth
    This electronic thesis or dissertation has been downloaded from the King’s Research Portal at https://kclpure.kcl.ac.uk/portal/ Between meaning and essence explaining necessary truth Schieder-Hestermann, Jakob Awarding institution: King's College London The copyright of this thesis rests with the author and no quotation from it or information derived from it may be published without proper acknowledgement. END USER LICENCE AGREEMENT Unless another licence is stated on the immediately following page this work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International licence. https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ You are free to copy, distribute and transmit the work Under the following conditions: Attribution: You must attribute the work in the manner specified by the author (but not in any way that suggests that they endorse you or your use of the work). Non Commercial: You may not use this work for commercial purposes. No Derivative Works - You may not alter, transform, or build upon this work. Any of these conditions can be waived if you receive permission from the author. Your fair dealings and other rights are in no way affected by the above. Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 27. Sep. 2021 Between Meaning and Essence - Explaining Necessary Truth Dissertation zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades Doctor philosophiae (Dr. phil.) eingereicht an der Philosophischen Fakultät I der Humboldt Universität zu Berlin im Rahmen des Joint PhD Programms mit dem King’s College London Dissertation submitted to Philosophischen Fakultät I of Humboldt University Berlin as part of the Joint-PhD Program between Humboldt University Berlin and King’s College London von/by Jakob Schieder-Hestermann Präsidentin der Humboldt Universität zu Berlin: Prof.
    [Show full text]
  • Redalyc.Logical Consequence for Nominalists
    THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia ISSN: 0495-4548 [email protected] Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea España ROSSBERG, Marcus; COHNITZ, Daniel Logical Consequence for Nominalists THEORIA. Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia, vol. 24, núm. 2, 2009, pp. 147- 168 Universidad del País Vasco/Euskal Herriko Unibertsitatea Donostia-San Sebastián, España Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=339730809003 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative Logical Consequence for Nominalists Marcus ROSSBERG and Daniel COHNITZ BIBLID [0495-4548 (2009) 24: 65; pp. 147-168] ABSTRACT: It has repeatedly been argued that nominalistic programmes in the philosophy of mathematics fail, since they will at some point or other involve the notion of logical consequence which is unavailable to the nominalist. In this paper we will argue that this is not the case. Using an idea of Nelson Goodman and W.V.Quine's which they developed in Goodman and Quine (1947) and supplementing it with means that should be nominalistically acceptable, we present a way to explicate logical consequence in a nominalistically acceptable way. Keywords: Philosophy of mathematics, nominalism, logical consequence, inferentialism, Nelson Goodman, W.V. Quine. 1. The Argument from Logical Consequence We do not have any strong convictions concerning the question of the existence or non- existence of abstract objects. We do, however, believe that ontological fastidiousness is prima facie a good attitude to adopt.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics and Natural Kinds: Slingshots, Fundamentality, and Causal Structure
    METAPHYSICS AND NATURAL KINDS: SLINGSHOTS, FUNDAMENTALITY, AND CAUSAL STRUCTURE By ANDREW LEE MCFARLAND Submitted to the graduate degree program in the Department of Philosophy and the Graduate Faculty of the University of Kansas in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. ________________________________ Chair: John Symons ________________________________ John Bricke ________________________________ Armin Schulz ________________________________ Clif Pye ________________________________ Philippe Huneman Date Defended: May 16, 2014 The Dissertation Committee for Andrew Lee McFarland certifies that this is the approved version of the following dissertation: METAPHYSICS AND NATURAL KINDS: SLINGSHOTS, FUNDAMENTALITY, AND CAUSAL STRUCTURE ________________________________ JOHN SYMONS Date approved: May 16, 2014 ii DISSERTATION ABSTRACT Metaphysics and Natural Kinds: Slingshots, Fundamentality, and Causal Structure Andrew Lee McFarland My dissertation addresses a question relevant to metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophy of science: What are natural kinds? I explore a view that holds that natural kinds are complex, structural properties that involve causal structure. Causal structure describes the idea that for the many properties associated with natural kinds, these properties are nomically linked – that is causally connected – in such a way that the properties of non-natural kinds are not. After criticizing arguments in favor of a nominalist theory of kinds – one that holds that a natural kind just is to be identified with its class of instances – and after defending the notion of a complex structural property from several prominent objections posed by David Lewis, I apply a causal account of natural kinds to a set of problematic cases, paying special attention to isomeric kinds from chemistry. iii Dedication I dedicate this doctoral thesis to my family and to the tireless support they have given me over the years.
    [Show full text]
  • "Metaphysical" Possibility Revisited
    Justin Clarke-Doane Columbia University “Metaphysical” Possibility Revisited Metaphysical Possibility: That alethic, non-deontic, modality whose necessities are supposed to include the likes of conceptual truths, (pure) mathematical truths, truths of fundamental ontology (such as that there are, or are not, propositions, properties, or possible worlds), mereological truths, identity truths, explanatorily basic normative truths, and grounding truths. o Sider: “We are told that logic…is metaphysically necessary. We are told that laws of nature are not….[I]t is metaphysically necessary that “nothing can be in two places at once”, and so on. This conception falls…short of a full criterion. But a thin conception is not in itself problematic. For when a notion is taken to be fundamental, one often assumes that the facts involving the notion will outrun one's conception [2011, 266].” It is widely agreed that the intelligibility of metaphysical modality has been vindicated. o Quine: “I do not myself make sense…of metaphysical necessity [1990, 224].” o Williamson: “[M]etaphysical modality is only one member of the extended family of objective modalities. Arguments for scepticism about metaphysical modality tend [implausibly] to generalize to other objective modalities [2016, 462].” But even if metaphysical modality is intelligible, it could lack much metaphysical significance. I will argue that this is the case, and will conclude with an alternative conception of possibility. Extant “Deflationist” Critiques Sidelle [1989] & Unger [2014]: “Twin Earth” thought experiments just concern the meaning of a word. We all agree what worlds there are. We just disagree about how to describe them. Problem: This critique is quite limited.
    [Show full text]