Gustav Bergmann: Bibliography

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Gustav Bergmann: Bibliography M. S. Gram E. D. Klemke THE ONTOLOGICAL TURN: Srudies in the Philosophy of GUSTAV BERGMANN xowA crTy $ uNlvERSrTy oF rowA PRESS Bibliography WORKS BY GUSTAV BERGMANN Abbreaiations MLP: Th9 Metaphysics of LogicalPositiahm. New York: Longmans, Green & Co., 1954. 'ME: Meaning and Existence. Madison: Universiry of Wisconsin Press, 1959. LR: Logic and Reality, Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 196,$. FB: H. Feigl and M. Brodbeck, eds. Readi.ngs in tbe Philosopby of Science. New York: Appleton-Century Crofa, 1953. M: M. H. Marx, ed. Psychological Tbeory: Contemporary Readings.New York: Macmillan, 1951. 1928 "Zur Axiomatik der Elementargeometrie." Wiener Akdilernie der Wissen- schaften 26 (1928): l-3. 1929 "Zur Axiomatik der Elemenargeometrie." Monatshefte fih Matbematik and P by sik 36 (1929) :269-84. "IJeber eine mit der Hypertorsen verwandte Flaechenklasse." Monatshefte filr Mathematik und Physik 36 (t929)15948. 302 Bibliography 1930 " E benen und B ewe gungs gruppen in Rientanns c hen Raeurnen." J ahre s b eric ht der Deutschen Mathematiker Vereinigung 39 (1930), Part II:54-5 (wirh E. Lukacs). "Ebenen und Beuegangsgruppen in Riemannscben Rteumen." Monatshefte fiir Mathematik und Physik 37 (1930):303-24 (with E. Lukacs). 193 1 "Zwei Bemerkungen zur abstrakten und kombinatorischen Topologie." Mo- natsbefte fiir Mathemutik und Physik 38 (1911):245-56. 1932 "Zur algebraisch-axiomatischen Begruendung der Topologie." Mathematische Zeitschrif t 35 ( 1932) : 502-ll. 193t "Zut anrlytischen Theorie literarischer trVertmasstaebe." lmago 2I (1935): 498-504. "On Physicalistic l\{odels of Nonphysical Terms." Philosophy of Science 7 (1940):l5l-58. "On Some Methodological Problems of Psychology." Philosophy of Science 7 (1940):205-19. Reprinted in FB. "The Subject Matter of Psychology," Pbilosophy of Science 7 (1940):415-33. 1941 "The Logic of Probability," Anaerican lournal of Physics 9 (1941):263-72. "Operationism and Theory in Psychology." Psychological Reaieu 48 (1941): 1-14 (with K. W. Spence). Reprinted in M. Reprinted in an essay collection of Spence. 1942 "An Empiricist Schema of the Psychophysical Problem." Pbilosoph;y of Sci- ence 9 (1942):72-9L ' Bibliography ,01 "syntactical Analysis of the Class Calculus." Philosophy of Science 9 (1942): 227-32. 'lRenrarks Concerning the Epistemology of Scientific Empiricism." Pbilosophy of Sci,ence 9 (1942):283-93. "The Indexical and Presentative Function of Signs." Philosopby of Science 9 (1942):372-74. Discussion of a paper by Willis Moore. 1943 "Note on Identity." Philosophy of Science 10 ( 1943): L6346, (Psychoanalysis and Experimental Psychology;' Mind 52 (1943);122-40. Re- printed in M. 'lOutline of an Empiricist'.Philosophy of Physics." Arnerican loumal of Physics ll (L943):248-58 and 33542. Reprinted in FB. 1944 'lThe Logic of P-sfchophysical Measuremenr." Psychological Revi,ew 5l (1944):1-24 (with K. W. Spence). Reprinted in FB and M. Reprinted in an essay collection of Spence. "The Formalism in Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law." Ethics 55 (1944):l1G-30 (with L. Zerby). "An Empiricist's System of the Sciences." Scientific Monthly 59 (1944): r4H8. "Holism, Historism, and Emergence," Philosophy of Science ll (1944):2A9-21. l'Pure Semantics, Sentences, and Propositions." Mind 5l (L944):218-57. "Notes on Identity." Pbilosophy of Science 11 (1944): 123-24, Discussion. "A Positivistic Metaphysics of Consciousness." Mind 45 (1945):193-226. "Frequencies, Probabilities, and Positivisrn." Pbilosophy and Pbenomenological Research 6 (1945) :26-44. "Review of Ebenstein's 'The P.ure Theory of Law."' Ethics 56 (1945):71-72, "Review of Ortega y Gasset's 'The Mission of the University.'" Mississippi Valley Historical Re,tsiew 32 (1945):266a7, 304 Bibliography 1946 ,,Remarks on Realism." Pbilosophy of Science L3 (1946)t261-73. Reprinted in MLP (153-75). ,,Some Comments on Carnap's Logic of Induction." Phi.losophy of Science 13 (1946)t7r-78. "Review of Cohen's 'Faith of a Liberal."' Ioana Lau Reaiew 32 (1946):178-81. 1947 "The Logic of Quanta." Americdn lournal of Physics 15 (L947):397-408, and 497-508. Reprinted in FB. "Russell on Particulars." Philosophicdl Reaieu 56 (1947)t59-72. Reprinted in MLP (187-214). ,,Undefined Descriptive Predicates." Philosophy and Pbenomenological Re- search 8 (1947)t55-82. "Sense Data, Linguistic Conventions, and Existence'" Pbilosophy of Science t4 (t947)i52-63. Reprinted in l\{LP (r7G96). "Philosophical and Psychological Pragmatics." Philosophy of Science 14 ( 1947 ) :27 L-7 3. Discussion. "Review of Kelsen's 'General Theory of Law end State."' Etbics 57 (1947): 213-15. 1948 "Concerning Carnap's Definition of 'Extensional' and 'Intensional."' Mind 57 (1948):494-95. "Conditions for an Extensional Elementaristic Language." Analysi's 8 (1948): 44-47. Reprinted in MLP (232-37). "Contextual Definitions in Nonextensional Languages," Joarnal of Symbolic Logic 11 (1948):140. "Descriptions in Nonextensional Contexts." Philosophy of Science 15 (1948): 351-55. "Review of Koehler's'Gestalt Psychology."'Psychological Bulletin 45 (19a8): 3 51-5t. Bibliography 30t 1949 "The Finite Represenations of S5." Methodos I (1949):217-19. "On Nonperceptual Intuition," Philosophy dt Phenomenological Researcb L0 (1949):261-64. Reprinted in MLP (228-31). "Professor Ayer's Analysis of Knowing." Analysis 9 (1949):98-106. Reprinted in MLP (215-27). "A Syntactical Characterization of S5." lournal of Syrnbolic Logic L4 (19+9)t 173-74. "Two Criteria for an Ideal Language," Pbilosopby of Sci'ence L6 (L949):71- 74. Reprinted in Richard Rorry, ed. The Lingai.stic Turn. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1967. See pp. 132-34. "Review of Russell's 'Human Knowledge."' Pbysics Today 2 (1949):27-28. 19t0 "Logical Positivism." In V. Ferm, ed. A History of Philosophicdl Systems. New York: Philosophical Library, 1950. See pp. 47L-82, Reprinted in MLP. "Semantics." In V. Ferm, ed. A Hbtory of Philosophical Systems, pp. 483-92. Reprinted in MLP (1719). "Comments on Storer's Definition of 'Soluble."' Analysis 12 (195L):44r48, "Review of 'Albert Einstein, Philosopher-Scientist!"' (ed. Schilp), Philosophi- cal Reaieu 60 (1951)2268-74. "Review of Kraft's 'Der Wiener Kreis' and Juhos' 'Die Erkenntnis und ihre Leistung."' P hilosopby b P henomenolo gical Researcb 12 ( 195 1 ) : 11943. "Review of Lasswell and Kaplan's 'Power and Society."' Ethics 62 (1951): 6H5. "Two Types of Linguistic Philosophy." Reuieu of Metaphysi.cs 5 (1952)t417- 38. Reprinted in MLP (106-31). 19t2 "The Problem of Relations in Classical Psychology." Philosophical Quarterly 2 (1952):14G-52. Reprinted in MLP (277-99). 306 BibliograPhy "A Criterion of Necessity." Reztie'ut of Metaphysics 6 (L952)t128-79- Discus- sion. "Multiplicative Closures." P ornt gali ae M athematic s ll (19 52) : 169-72. "Review of Brunswick's 'The Conceptual Framework of Psychology!" Psy- chological Bulletin 49 (1952). 19t' "Theoretical Psychology." Io Annual Reaie'ur of Psychology 4 (1953):435-58. ,,The Identity of Indiscernibles and the Formalist Definition of ldentity." Mind 62 (t9h);75-79. Reprinted in MLP (268-76). "Two Comerstones of Empiricism." Synthese 8 (1953):435-52. Reprinted in MLP (78-105). "Logical Positivism, Language, and the Reconsuuction of Metaphysics." Riu. Criti di Storia della filoifiis (1953):453-81. Reprinted in MLP (30-79). Re- printed in part in Richard Rorty. The Lingui.sti.c Turn. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1968. See pp. 63-71. "Review of Wisdom's 'Other Minds."' Philosophy & Phenomenological Re- searcb L4 (1953): ll2-14. 19t4 "Bodies, Minds, and Acts." frst published in MLP. "Particularity and the New Nominalism." Methodos 6 (1954):131-47. Re- printed in ME (91-10t). "Sense and Nonsense in Operationism." Scientific Monthly 79 (1954):21V14. Reprinted in P. Frank, ed, The Validation of Scientific Theories. Boston: Beacon Press, 1957. For German tranSlation, see 1965. ,,Some Remarks on the Ontology of Occam." Philosophical Reaie:as 63 ( 1954): 560-71. Reprinted in ME (14+-5+). "Review of Goetz' 'Die Entstehung der Ordung.' " Philosophy anil Phtenome- nological Research 15 ( 1954):287-88. The Metapbysics of Logical Positittism. New York: Longmans, Green & Co., 1954. Second ed. by University of Wisconsin Press, 1967, with Preface. Bibliography 30i 19tt "Professor Quine on Analyticity." Mind 64 (1955):254-58. Reprinted in ME (13e43). "Reducrion." ln Current Trend.s in Psychology and the Behaaioural Sciences. Pittsburgh: Universiqy of Pitp-sluqgh Press, f955. See pp. 59-81. "Intentionaliry." In Sernaktica. Archivio di Filoiofa' Rome: Bocca, 1955. See pp. 177-216. Reprinted in ME (3-38). Reprinted in Thomas M. Olshewsky. Problems ;n thi Pbllosophy of Langaage. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1969. See pp. 20G-32. ,,Dispositional Properties and Dispositions." Pbilosophicdl Studies 6 (1955): 77-80. "Review of Frenkel-Brunswik's 'Psychoanalysis and the Unity of Science."' !ournal of Philosophy 52 (1955):692-95. "Review of Nagel's 'sovereign ReaSon.'" Philosopby dv Phenoruenological Research 16 (1955):128-30. 'Wissenschaft, "Review of Stegmueller's 'MetaphysibS, Skepsis."' Philosophical Reaiew 64 (195 5) :665-67. "Dell'ideologia." Ocidente 6 (1955):519-35. Translation of "Ideology" from J\,ILP. 19t6 "The Contribudon of john B. Watson,'r Psychological Reaieus 63 (1956)t?65- 76. Reprinted in Jordan Scher, ed. Theories of the Mind. Glencoe, Ill.: The Free Pless, 1962. For Italian translation, see'1958. 'lRussell's Examination of Leibniz Examined." Philosophy of Science 23 (1956):175-203. Reprinted in ME (1t5-88). '(The RepreSentations of S5." Journal
Recommended publications
  • Analogies in Physics Analysis of an Unplanned Epistemic Strategy
    . Analogies in Physics Analysis of an Unplanned Epistemic Strategy Von der Philosophischen Fakultät der Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Universität Hannover zur Erlangung des Grades Doktors der Philosophie Dr. phil. Genehmigte Dissertation von Ing. grad. MA Gunnar Kreisel Erscheinungs- bzw. Druckjahr 2021 Referent: Prof. Dr. Mathias Frisch Korreferent: Prof. Dr. Torsten Wilholt Tag der Promotion: 26.10.2020 2 To my early died sister Uta 3 Acknowledgements I could quote only very few by name who have contributed to my work on this thesis, for discussing some of the developed ideas with me or comments on parts of my manuscript. These are in the first place my advisor Mathias Frisch and further Torsten Wilholt, who read critically individual chapters. Much more have contributed by some remarks or ideas mentioned in passing which I cannot assign to someone explicitly and therefore must be left unnamed. Also, other people not named here have supported my work in the one or other way. I think they know who were meant if they read this. A lot of thanks are due to Zoe Vercelli from the International Writing centre at Leibniz University Hannover improving my English at nearly the whole manuscript (some parts are leaved to me because of organisational changes at the writing centre). So, where the English is less correct Zoe could not have had a look on it. Of course, all errors and imprecisions remain in solely my responsibility. 4 Abstract This thesis investigates what tools are appropriate for answering the question how it is possible to develop such a complex theory in physics as the standard model of particle physics with only an access via electromagnetic interaction of otherwise unobservable objects and their interactions it was investigated what the tools are to do this.
    [Show full text]
  • INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS
    INTENTIONALITY Past and Future VIBS Volume 173 Robert Ginsberg Founding Editor Peter A. Redpath Executive Editor Associate Editors G. John M. Abbarno Matti Häyry Mary-Rose Barral Steven V. Hicks Gerhold K. Becker Richard T. Hull Raymond Angelo Belliotti Mark Letteri Kenneth A. Bryson Vincent L. Luizzi C. Stephen Byrum Alan Milchman H. G. Callaway George David Miller Robert A. Delfino Alan Rosenberg Rem B. Edwards Arleen L. F. Salles Andrew Fitz-Gibbon John R. Shook Francesc Forn i Argimon Eddy Souffrant William Gay Tuija Takala Dane R. Gordon Anne Waters J. Everet Green John R. Welch Heta Aleksandra Gylling Thomas F. Woods a volume in Cognitive Science CS Francesc Forn i Argimon, Editor INTENTIONALITY Past and Future Edited by Gábor Forrai and George Kampis Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Cover Design: Studio Pollmann The paper on which this book is printed meets the requirements of “ISO 9706:1994, Information and documentation - Paper for documents - Requirements for permanence”. ISBN: 90-420-1817-8 ©Editions Rodopi B.V., Amsterdam - New York, NY 2005 Printed in the Netherlands CONTENTS Preface vii List of Abbreviations ix ONE The Necessity and Nature of Mental Content 1 LAIRD ADDIS TWO Reading Brentano on the Intentionality of the Mental 15 PHILIP J. BARTOK THREE Emotions, Moods, and Intentionality 25 WILLIAM FISH FOUR Lockean Ideas as Intentional Contents 37 GÁBOR FORRAI FIVE Normativity and Mental Content 51 JUSSI HAUKIOJA SIX The Ontological and Intentional Status of Fregean Senses: An Early Account of External Content 63 GREG JESSON
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Time: a Slightly Opinionated Introduction
    Philosophy of time: A slightly opinionated introduction Florian Fischer There are several intertwined debates in the area of contemporary philos- ophy of time. One field of inquiry is the nature of time itself. Presentists think that only the present moment exists whereas eternalists believe that all of (space-)time exists on a par. The second main field of inquiry is the question of how objects persist through time. The endurantist claims that objects are three-dimensional wholes, which persist by being wholly1 present, whereas the perdurantist thinks that objects are four- dimensional and that their temporal parts are the bearers of properties. The third debate in the field of contemporary philosophy of time is about tense- versus tenseless theory. Tensers are at odds with detensers about the status of the linguistic reference to the present moment. These are only very crude characterizations and it is even disputed by some ad- vocates of the corresponding positions that they are accurate. However this very sketchy picture already reveals a fundamental difference: The eternalism/presentism and endurance/perdurance discussions belong to the field of metaphysics, whereas tense is in the first instance a linguistic phenomenon. Among the many fields of philosophy, there are two that are more intimately interconnected than most but whose practi- tioners have too long pursued relatively independent paths. On the one hand, there are philosophers of language, who have devoted much attention to indexicals (`now', etc.), tem- poral operators (`it has been the case that', etc.), and tensed sentences. On the other hand, there are the philosophers of tensed and tenseless time (also called A-time or B-time, dynamic time or static time, etc.).
    [Show full text]
  • Gustav Bergmann on Ideal Languages
    Gustav Bergmann on Ideal Languages Nino B. Cocchiarella October 30, 1992 1 Bergmann and the Logical Positivists Bergmann began his philosophical career as a logical positivist. He was in u- enced in his early career by Rudolf Carnap in the latter's own early career. Carnap was one of my own teachers in his later years. For Bergmann, the logical positivists \were all either metaphysical materi- alists or phenomenalists" (The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism [MLP], ix). He rejected metaphysical materialism and, initially, adopted phenomenalism. Later, he rejected phenomenalism (which, together with materialism, he re- garded as a \one-level world") and came to regard himself as \a realist of the phenomenological variety," which he described as a \two-level world of minds and bodies in which the former are capable of intending the latter as well as themselves and each other (ibid.). Question: What is the di erence, if any, between metaphysical mind-body dualism and Bergmann's \two-level world" of minds and bodies? Question: Does Bergmann mean by a two-level world of mind and body only that the mental world is not reducible to the material and that otherwise there is only one world (with two levels)? The principle goal of logical positivism (as stated in the 1929 \Manifesto" of the Vienna Circle) was uni ed science (Einheitswissenschaft), by which was meant: 1. a framework in which all knowledge of reality accessible to humanity could be represented This lecture was presented at Indiana University at the Gustav Bergmann Memorial Conference, October 30{31, 1992. The other speakers were: Reinhardt Grossmann (Indiana University), Herbert Hochberg (University of Texas at Austin), Erwin Tegtmeir (University of Mannheim), Robert Turnbull (Ohio State University), and Fred Wilson (University of Toronto).
    [Show full text]
  • Gustav Bergmann (1906 – 1987) During the Years 1946 – 1958
    Review of: Bergmann, Gustav, Collected Works Vol. I Daniel von Wachter Homepage of the author: http://von-wachter.de Email: replace “ABC” in [email protected] by “von-wachter” Address: Dr. Dr. Daniel von Wachter, Institut für Philosophie, Universität München, PF 42, D-80539 München, Germany. This is a preprint version of: Wachter, Daniel von. 2006. "Review of: Bergmann, Gustav, Collected Works Vol. I." In Cambridge and Vienna. Frank P. Ramsey and the Vienna Circle (Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook, vol. 12), edited by M. C. Galavotti. Berlin, 219-222. This document is available at http://epub.ub.uni-muenchen.de. (Format A5; print 2 pages per sheet) Logical Positivism, the Linguistic Turn, and the Reconstruction of the Questions of Ontology Bergmann, Gustav, Collected Works Vol. I: Selected Papers I, edited by E. Tegtmeier, Frankfurt/Lancaster: Ontos-Verlag, 2003. ISBN 3-937202-17- X, pp. 350, hardcover € 99,00 (€ 67,00 subscription). 1 This volume makes available 17 papers published by Gustav Bergmann (1906 – 1987) during the years 1946 – 1958. The edition of Bergmann’s works in three volumes by the publisher “Ontos-Verlag” (www.ontos- verlag.de) is now complete. Volume II contains papers from 1960 – 1981, volume III contains Bergmann’s book Realism from 1967. Bergmann was born in Vienna (Austria) in 1906. When he received his doctorate in mathematics from the University of Vienna in 1928, he had already been invited to join the Vienna Circle, where he was especially influenced by Schlick, Waismann, and Carnap. He went to Berlin to work as an assistant to Albert Einstein and then returned to Vienna.
    [Show full text]
  • How Hochberg Helped Us Take the Ontological Turn
    The University of Manchester Research How Hochberg helped us take the ontological turn Document Version Submitted manuscript Link to publication record in Manchester Research Explorer Citation for published version (APA): Macbride, F. (2014). How Hochberg helped us take the ontological turn. Dialectica, 68, 163-9. Published in: Dialectica Citing this paper Please note that where the full-text provided on Manchester Research Explorer is the Author Accepted Manuscript or Proof version this may differ from the final Published version. If citing, it is advised that you check and use the publisher's definitive version. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the Research Explorer are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Takedown policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please refer to the University of Manchester’s Takedown Procedures [http://man.ac.uk/04Y6Bo] or contact [email protected] providing relevant details, so we can investigate your claim. Download date:26. Sep. 2021 HOW HOCHBERG HELPED US TAKE THE ONTOLOGICAL TURN Fraser MACBRIDE Please do not cite this version. The published version is, ‘How Hochberg helped us take the ontological turn’, Dialectica, 2014, 68, 163-9 Analytic philosophy has taken an ‘ontological turn' and Herbert Hochberg has played a significant part in helping bring us to where we stand now. This special issue on predicables and relations, two of his abiding concerns over the last 50 years, is dedicated to him.
    [Show full text]
  • Frege, Russell and #1A7DA86
    Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein Michael Potter Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein were founders (although not by any means the sole founders) of the analytic tradition in philosophy; but they did not found the philosophy of language, which has roots stretching back much further. Their principal contribution, indeed, could be regarded as being in the opposite direction: it is not so much that they applied philosophical methods to the study of language as that they applied linguistic methods to the study of certain problems in philosophy. In the course of this work they did develop ideas which shed light on language and how it functions. However, even this must be heavily qualified, since their main contributions were much more to the philosophy of logic (the study of the inferential role of sentences) than to the philosophy of language (the study of how language means what it does). In the summary of their contribution that follows we shall focus on the morals that can be drawn from it for modern work in the philosophy of language. Frege It is worth noting straightaway that mathematics played an important role in shaping the philosophical ambitions of all three of the philosophers we shall be considering. Frege was a mathematician for all of his professional life; Russell began as one and much of what he wrote had the philosophy of mathematics as its focus; and Wittgenstein, although he did not train as a mathematician, announced when he arrived at Cambridge in 1911 that it was the philosophy of mathematics that he wanted to study with Russell.
    [Show full text]
  • Origin of Russell's Early Theory of Logical Truth As Purely General Truth
    Modern Logic Volume 8, Number 3 & 4 (May 2000-October 2001), pp. 21–30. ORIGIN OF RUSSELL’S EARLY THEORY OF LOGICAL TRUTH AS PURELY GENERAL TRUTH: BOLZANO, PEIRCE, FREGE, VENN, OR MACCOLL? JAN DEJNOZKAˇ Who most likely influenced Russell’s early theory of logical truth as purely general truth: Bolzano, Peirce, Frege, Venn, or MacColl? Russell’s theory of logical truth as invariance, or as truth under any interpretation, anticipates Alfred Tarski (1936), J. C. C. McKin- sey (1945), Rudolf Carnap (1947), Saul Kripke (1980), Joseph Almog (1989), and John Etchemendy (1990), and has antecedents in Bernard Bolzano and John Venn. Russell’s theory resembles Bolzano’s substitu- tional account of logical truth, which Etchemendy compares to Tarski’s satisfactional account of logical truth (Etchemendy [14, pp. 27-33])1. Tarski himself compares his closely related definition of logical con- sequence to Carnap and to Bolzano (Tarski [52, pp. 413-18, 417 n.+] following H. Scholtz). Russell’s theory of what is possible as what is sometimes the case is close to McKinsey [30, p. 83] and Venn [55, p. 40], with roots in Diodorus Cronus and Parmenides. Russell’s fundamental paper on modality, “Necessity and Possibility” (Russell [51]), which Russell read to the Oxford Philosophical Society on October 22, 1905 (Urquhart [54, p. 507]), was not published during his lifetime. It appeared in a volume of the Collected Papers of Bertrand Russell only in 1994 (Russell [34]). Had it been published in 1905 as the companion piece to “On Denoting” I believe it was, the course of modal logic — not to mention the course of Russell studies — might well have been different2.
    [Show full text]
  • Grumbles and Quibbles from Mitteleuropa
    teorema Vol. XXX/1, 2011, pp. 103-113 ISSN: 0210-1602 [BIBLID 0210-1602 (2011) 30:1; pp. 103-113] Grumbles and Quibbles from Mitteleuropa Kevin Mulligan Hanjo Glock’s judicious, lively, reliable and extraordinarily wide- ranging account of analytic philosophy contains many good things. Several of his numerous, interesting and well-argued criticisms of available accounts of the history of analytic philosophy are spot on – for example, his objections to Michael Friedman’s influential Parting of the Ways [Friedman (2000)]. I was also pleased to find that he (henceforth “HG”) endorses a conception of analytic philosophy (henceforth “AP”) which is in part “genetic”.1 In accor- dance with the Editor’s instructions, my quibbles focus on only two frag- ments of HG’s rich analysis. I. AUSTRO-ANGLO ? HG sketches a view of the origins of AP according to which the latter is at bottom “Anglo-Austrian” and Austrian (Austro-Hungarian) philosophy is to be sharply distinguished from German philosophy. Versions of this view have been set forth, as he notes, by Neurath, Haller, Dummett, Barry Smith and Peter Simons. (I, too, have defended a similar view). HG accepts that many of the claims put forward by proponents of the Neurath-Haller thesis are correct and important. But he disagrees with what he calls three of their suggestions: “first, that there is a single, unified and unique current of ‘scien- tific`, proto-analytic philosophy which dominated Austrian philosophy; sec- ondly, that the proto-analytic/analytic movement was entirely alien to Germany; and thirdly, that this movement was universally characterised by realism and hostility to Kant” [p.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography of the Writings of Gustav Bergmann
    Bibliography of the Writings of Gustav Bergmann 1928 Zur Axiomatik der Elementargeometrie. Weiner Akademie Der Wissenschaften, 26, (1928): 1-3. 1929 Über eine mit den Hypertorsen verwandte Flachenklasse. Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, 36, (1929): 259-268. Zur Axiomatik der Elementargeometrie. Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, 36, (1929): 269-284. 1930 Ebenen und Bewegungsgruppen in Riemannschen Räumen. Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker Vereiningung, 39, (1930): 54-55. (with E. Lukács) Ebenen und Bewegungsgruppen in Riemannschen Räumen. Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, 37, (1930): 303-324. (with E. Lukács) 1931 Zwei Bemerkungen zur abstracten und kombinatorischen Topologie. Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, 38, (1931): 245-256. 1932 Zur algebraisch-axiomatischen Begründung der Topologie. Mathematische Zeitschrift, 35, (1932): 502-511. 1935 Zur analytischen Theorie literarischer Wertmasstäbe. Imago, 21, (1935): 498-504. 1940 On Physicalistic Models of Non-Physical Terms. Philosophy of Science, 7, (1940): 151- 158. On Some Methodological Problems of Psychology. Philosophy of Science, 7, (1940): 205-219. The Subject Matter of Psychology. Philosophy of Science, 7, (1940): 415-433. 1941 The Logic of Probability. American Journal of Physics, 9, (1941): 263-272. Operationism and Theory in Psychology. Psychological Review, 48, (1941): 1-14. (with K. Spence) 1942 An Empiricist Schema of the Psychophysical Problem. Philosophy of Science, 9, (1942): 72-91. Syntactical Analysis of the Class Calculus. Philosophy of Science, 9, (1942): 227-232. Remarks Concerning the Epistemology of Scientific Empiricism. Philosophy of Science, 9, (1942): 283-293. The Indexical and Presentative Function of Signs. Philosophy of Science, 9, (1942): 372- 374. 1943 Notes on Identity. Philosophy of Science, 10, (1943): 163-166.
    [Show full text]
  • Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: the Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy Christopher Bailes Washington University in St
    Washington University in St. Louis Washington University Open Scholarship All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) 5-24-2012 Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy Christopher Bailes Washington University in St. Louis Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd Recommended Citation Bailes, Christopher, "Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The eN ed for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy" (2012). All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs). 681. https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/etd/681 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in All Theses and Dissertations (ETDs) by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WASHINGTON UNIVERSITY IN ST. LOUIS Department of Germanic Languages and Literatures Dissertation Examination Committee: Paul Michael Lützeler, Chair Julia Driver Matt Erlin Erin McGlothlin Gillian Russell Lynne Tatlock Ludwig Wittgenstein and Hermann Broch: The Need for Fiction and Logic in Moral Philosophy By Christopher Wade Bailes A dissertation presented to the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences of Washington University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2012 Saint Louis, Missouri Acknowledgements I would like to thank the Department of Germanic Languages and Literatures and Washington University in Saint Louis for their generous financial support. My dissertation benefited from various guest lecturers, conferences, and graduate seminars supported by the university, and would not have been financially feasible without the tuition waivers and more than adequate living stipends that kept me afloat.
    [Show full text]
  • Austrians Tend to Be Preoccupied with the Idiosyncrasies of Their Own Mentality. the Austrian Soul (Die Österreichische Seele)
    i PREFACE Austrians tend to be preoccupied with the idiosyncrasies of their own mentality. The Austrian soul (die österreichische Seele) and its various crises of identity have been the objects of all kinds of analyses, ranging from Erwin Ringel’s psychological inquiries to Helmut Qualtinger’s satirical caricatures, whose black humour is typical of the entertainment seen in the Austrian cabaret. The reasons for this self- questioning obsession are manifold and partially roorted in the multiculturalism of the Austro-Hungarian Empire. Vienna of the fin de siècle was not only the capital but also the cultural meeting place for intellectuals from all corners of the Empire. This creative atmosphere was characterized by the exchange of ideas among various schools, circles, groups, and individuals, and nourished by Vienna’s thriving coffeehouse culture. The decline and eventual dissolution, in 1918, of the Habsburg Monarchy, reactivated once again the problematic issue of Austrian identity, an identity defined mainly in contrast to Germany, its neighbour to the north. Numerous scholars have tried both to define and to account for the existence of Austrian traditions in various cultural fields. The extensive work of philosophers such as Rudolf Haller and Barry Smith has substantiated the claim, expressed earlier by Otto Neurath in the manifesto of the Vienna Circle, that there are distinct Austrian traditions in philosophy. Literary critics such as Claudio Magris, Ulrich Greiner, and Robert Menasse investigated similar claims about typically Austrian features in literature. We invited leading experts on these topics to participate in an international conference, Writing the Austrian Traditions (May 12-14, 2000 at Woodsworth College, University of Toronto), in order to discuss some of the significant connections between Austrian literary and philosophical traditions.
    [Show full text]