Faith and Reason: from Vatican I to John Paul I1

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Faith and Reason: from Vatican I to John Paul I1 FAITH AND REASON: FROM VATICAN I TO JOHN PAUL I1 AVERY CARDlNAL DULLES, S.), John Paul 11's encyclical of September 14, 1998, on "Faith and Reason" takes up a theme that has been a staple of Western theology since at least the time of Augustine in the*fourth century. St. Anselm in the twelfth century and St. Thomas iquinas, in the thirteenth, argued brilliantly for the harmony between faith and reason. The medieval synthesis, already wounded by the inroads of fourteenth- century Nominalism, was sharply contested fiom two sides in the sev- enteenth and eighteenth centuries. At one extreme were self-assured rationalists, who belittled the role of faith, and at the other, skeptical fideists, who distrusted the powers of reason. Since some Catholic thinkers of the early nineteenth century were tainted by these two errors, the Roman Magisterium issued condemnations of both ration- alism and fideism. The official Catholic position was most authorita- tively summarized in 1870 by the First Vatican Council in its Dog- matic Constitution on Catholic Faith, which contained a chapter dedicated to the theme of faith and reason. e Without actually mentioning Thomas Aquinas, Vatican I endorsed 4. 194 AVERY CARDINAL DULLES, S.J. Fronl Vatican I to John Paul I1 195 his position. A decade later, in 1879, Pope Leo XI11 published his might have been expected simply to enlarge upon the positions of encyclical Aetmi Pdtris, proposing St. Thomas as the thinker whose Vatican I, very much as Leo XI11 had done in his encyclical on synthesis of faith and reason should be accepted as a solid founda- Thomistic philosophy in 1879. But instead, he. ___,.addressed__- thegr&lem--- J tion from which to grapple with more recent questions in philosophy in~98gikin&.b~e~Ww%&. and science. The present pope does not, of course, contradict Vatican I. Tn fact, In the first half of the twentieth century the popes issued a num- he quotes or refers to its Constitution on Catholic Faith in favorable ber of further condemnations and admonitions relevant to our ques- terms at least ten times at various points spanning the entire encycli- tion. Early in the century Pius X repudiated the agnostic and histon- cal.' He takes over from Vatican I the familiar ideas that reason has 1; 1; cist theses of Modernism. After World War I, Pius XI censured the power to establish the existence of God and thc preambles of Marxist Communism for its materialist determinism. Pius XI1 in 1950 Christian faith (5553, 67), that faith confirms truths that reason can 1 cautioned against the nouvellr the'ologre of the day, in which he detect- cannot grasp except with great difficulty (943), that faith also I!a. ed a tendency toward historicism and dogmatic relativism. embraces mysteries that lie entirely beyond the range of unaided rea- ,E f At the Second Vatican Council, in 1962-1965, the problem no son (558, g), and that reason can render even these revealed mysteries 1 longer seemed acute. The Council, displaying a measure of historical to some degree intelligible ($83). In line with Vatican I, the pope consciousness, acknowledged the need to understand the Gospel teaches that the Magisterium has the righ't and duty to condemn phi- with all the tools of contemporary scholarship and to proclaim it in losophical tenets that are opposed to truths of faith (955, fn. 72), and ways adapted to existing cultural situations (GS 44, 62). But at the that there can be no conflict between faith and-reason, sirice both are same time it declared that there were unchanging realities and perma- gifts of the same God, who could ncver contra;(ict himself (998,53). ncnt truths (GS 10; DH 3). In the course of its treatment of the Also in the footsteps of Vatican I, John Paul TI opposes both a ration- autonomy of science and culture, it reaffirmed the teaching of Vati- alism that dismisses the input of faith and a fideism that distrusts the can I on the distinction between the "two orders" of faith and reason guidance of reason ($552, 53). He repeats the teaching of Vatican I (GS 59). Elsewhere Vatican I1 praised Thomas Aquinas for having that faith and reason "mutually support each other" ($100). given glorious witness to the harmony of faith and reason (GE 10). Notwithstanding these important continuities, there are striking But these were only passing and disconnected remarks. Vatican I1 differences between the approaches of Vatican I and John Paul U. gave no sustained attention to our theme; it was remarkably silent They are speaking to radically diverse situations. At the time of Vati- about the role of reason in preparing for the assent of faith-a point can I, the issues within the Church were rather clearly drawn. At one that had been of acute concern to the Fathers at Vatican I and to Pius end of the spectrum were rationalists and semi-rationalists who pro- XII. fessed exorbitant confidence in the powers of unaided reason to fath- Since the acrimonious debates of earlier centuries had evidently subsided, Pope John Paul I1 could easily have left the problem in a I. Ten references are fisted by Kenneth I.. Schmitz in his "Faith and Reason: Then and Now," Communio 26 (1999): 595-608, at 598, note 9. He seems to have overlooked the state of benign neglect. If he did wish to speak on the subject, he quotation from Dri Fihin Fides et rdbo g. * From Vatican I to John Paul I1 197 om the depths of reality and who regarded faith as unreliable and claims of pure reason. Unlike Vatican I he refrains from lamentations unnecessary for educated persons. At the other end were fideists and and angry condemnations. In the spirit of Vatican 11, he prefers to traditionalists who denied the capacity of the intellect to attain truths use what Pope John XXIII called "th=d!-m_e~y."~ He sees of a moral or metaphysical nature and who entrusted themselves to himself as a friend and ally, called to help philosophy to extricate faith as a blind movement of emotion or volition or a passive con- itself from its present state of impoverishment. He exhorts it to I formity to tradition. Rationalism was more at home in Germany; recover its original vocation of being a quest for wisdom, as is fideism, in France. implied in the very name philo-sophia, which means love of wisdom Vatican I, recognizing elements of truth and falsehood in both (553, 6). This positive stance harmonizes with the tendency of the rationalism and fideism, adopted a mediating position. Against the Second Vatican Council to depict the Church as a partner in the fideists it affirmed that reason, by its natural powers, could establish struggles of humanity at large, including its search for truth (52; cf. the foundations of faith and the credibility of the Christian revela- GS 16). tion (DS 3019,3033). And against the rationalists Vatican I attributed Whereas Vatican I spoke in authoritative and judgmental tones, the full assurance of the act of faith to the power of divine grace John Paul 11, s&g, huq~m~kground&!*qe enlightening the intellect and inspiring the will (DS 3010). The act m~r~~3i~~~k~~&eJ~e,,2?S,~~Ee'-e&gruu.The philo- was therefore reasonable without being a deliverance of pure reason. sophical quest, as he sees it, begins from below, where experience By the end of the twentieth century, the proud boasts of auto- gives rise to questions. All philosophy, he remarks, begins in wonder nomous reason, setting itself up against the claims of faith, had been (54). The mind ineluctably asks about the mcaningsw of life in the face severely muted. The prevailing mood was one of metaphysical ag- of suffering and inevitable death (526). In language reminiscent of nosticism. Some intellectuals, clinging to a remnant of rationalism, Augustine the pope detects in the human heart "a desire to know the professed a scientism that restricted genuine knowledge to the sphere truth," (Preface), which he later calls "a seed of desire and nostalgia of measurable physical reali.ties. Logical positivists dismissed all for God (524). Giving scope to this impulse, he interprets the search statements not verifiable by experience as "noncognitive" deliverances for wisdom as a pilgrimage or journey of discovery, much along the of emotion, convention, or simple caprice. lines of Bonaventure in his Itineraty ofthe Mind to God (5533, 105). In summary, therefore, the rationalist mentality hardly survives The pope's rhetoric is strikingly different from that of the Magis- today except in the spheres of mathematics, logic, and empirical sci- terium in the nineteenth century. Vatican I had called for a submis- ence. Philosophy, for its part, has practically abandoned the pursuit sion to the authority of God who reveals; it stressed the obligation of of transcendent or metaphysical truth. It has narrowed its horizons the individual to believe whatever is contained in the word of God to the spheres of shifting phenomena, linguistic study, the interpreta- and certified by the Magisterium. John Paul 11, by contrast, adopts tion of texts, and pragmatic strategies for coping with radical plural- the posture of a physician helping a patient on the road to recovery. ism. In this situation John Paul I1 sees no need to restrain the excessive 2. John XXIII, "Gaudet Mater Ecclesia," in The Donmnentr of Kfti~dnII, ed. Walter M. Abbott and Joseph Gallagher (New York: America Press, 1966), 716. From Vatican I to John Paul 11 199 He portrays the truth of revelation as a fulfillment of the universal cles and prophecies.
Recommended publications
  • Developments in Neuroscience and Human Freedom: Some Theological and Philosophical Questions
    S & CB (2003), 16, 123–137 0954–4194 ALAN TORRANCE Developments in Neuroscience and Human Freedom: Some Theological and Philosophical Questions Christianity suggests that human beings are free and responsible agents. Developments in neuroscience challenge this when wedded with two ‘fideisms’: ‘naturalism’ and ‘nomological monism’ (causality applies exclusively to basic particles). The wedding of Galen Strawson’s denial that anything can be a cause of itself with a physicalist account of brain states highlights the problem neuroscience poses for human freedom. If physicalism is inherently reductionistic (Kim) and dualism struggles to make sense of developments in neuroscience, Cartwright’s pluralist account of causality may offer a way forward. It integrates with thinking about the person from a Christian epistemic base and facilitates response to Strawson. Key Words: God, person, neuroscience, freedom, naturalism, nomological monism, physicalism, dualism, causality. Five years ago, the Ethics and Public Policy Center in Washington, hosted a conference on ‘Neuroscience and the Human Spirit’. In his opening address, the organiser, Dr Frederick Goodwin, asked whether developments in the field do not pose a challenge to the ‘very foundation upon which our civilization rests’, namely, ‘free will and the capacity to make moral choices?’ The question I am seeking to address here raises the same issue with respect to the grounds of the Christian understanding of its message and, indeed, of what it is to be a person. In the light of recent advances in understanding the physical workings of our neural substrate, the electrochemical nature of cerebral processing and so on, does it still make sense to conceive of our minds as the free cause of our actions and the conscious centre of human life? So much suggests that the workings of our minds require to be construed in radically physical and, apparently, imper- sonal terms – as a complex causal series of synaptic firings and the like.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Doctrine of Religion As Political Philosophy
    Kant's Doctrine of Religion as Political Philosophy Author: Phillip David Wodzinski Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/987 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2009 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Political Science KANT’S DOCTRINE OF RELIGION AS POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY a dissertation by PHILLIP WODZINSKI submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2009 © copyright by PHILLIP DAVID WODZINSKI 2009 ABSTRACT Kant’s Doctrine of Religion as Political Philosophy Phillip Wodzinski Advisor: Susan Shell, Ph.D. Through a close reading of Immanuel Kant’s late book, Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, the dissertation clarifies the political element in Kant’s doctrine of religion and so contributes to a wider conception of his political philosophy. Kant’s political philosophy of religion, in addition to extending and further animating his moral doctrine, interprets religion in such a way as to give the Christian faith a moral grounding that will make possible, and even be an agent of, the improvement of social and political life. The dissertation emphasizes the wholeness and structure of Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason as a book, for the teaching of the book is not exhausted by the articulation of its doctrine but also includes both the fact and the manner of its expression: the reader learns most fully from Kant by giving attention to the structure and tone of the book as well as to its stated content and argumentation.
    [Show full text]
  • David Hume, "The Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion," and Religious Tolerance
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Supervised Undergraduate Student Research Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects and Creative Work 5-2020 David Hume, "The Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion," and Religious Tolerance Jarrett Delozier [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_chanhonoproj Part of the History of Philosophy Commons, History of Religion Commons, Intellectual History Commons, and the Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons Recommended Citation Delozier, Jarrett, "David Hume, "The Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion," and Religious Tolerance" (2020). Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_chanhonoproj/2382 This Dissertation/Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Supervised Undergraduate Student Research and Creative Work at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Chancellor’s Honors Program Projects by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. DeLozier 1 Introduction In the history of philosophy of religion and natural theology, David Hume is an immensely influential contributor. One of his most important works in the field is his Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, which contains his greatest treatment of natural theology, specifically the design argument. However, there’s a big problem which the Dialogues present to understanding Hume. Eleven of the twelve parts of the Dialogues contain Hume’s sharp criticisms and attacks on the Design argument. But in the final part, in what is often called “Philo’s Reversal,” he seems to completely reverse course by renouncing his skepticism and endorsing the Design argument.
    [Show full text]
  • Douglas Hedley, COLERIDGE, PHILOSOPHY and RELIGION: AIDS to REFLECTION and the MIRROR of the SPIRIT
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 18 Issue 3 Article 9 7-1-2001 Douglas Hedley, COLERIDGE, PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION: AIDS TO REFLECTION AND THE MIRROR OF THE SPIRIT Ken Casey Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Casey, Ken (2001) "Douglas Hedley, COLERIDGE, PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION: AIDS TO REFLECTION AND THE MIRROR OF THE SPIRIT," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 18 : Iss. 3 , Article 9. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil200118330 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol18/iss3/9 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. BOOK REVIEWS Coleridge, Philosophy and Religion: Aids to Reflection and the Mirror of the Spirit by Douglas Hedley Cambridge University Press, 2000, 330pp. KEN CASEY, Kentucky Wesleyan College Emerson, in his panegyric on Plato, notes that "every brisk young man who says in succession fine things to each reluctant generation ... is some reader of Plato, translating into the vernacular, wittily, his good things." He lists a series of eminent thinkers, Boethius, Rabelais, Erasmus, among others, and ends with Coleridge. Modern histories of Platonism tend to relegate Coleridge to a minor role, at best a minor com­ mentator; however, if Douglas Hedley is corr<c'Ct, the view of Coleridge as a minor commentator and patchwork thinker is historically inaccurate and philosophically impoverishing.
    [Show full text]
  • Mystical Experience, Religious Doctrine and Philosophical Analysis
    2 [3 181- MYSTICAL EXPERIENCE, RELIGIOUS DOCTRINE ,AND PHILOSOPHICAL ANALYSIS P. C. Almond, M. A. (Lancast.er), B.D. (Hons) (London), Th. L. A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Phi tosophy The Department of Philosophy The University of Adelaide De cember, 1978. ''i,\"6-¡'(,,r-í.¡r',,' ii t ti/'i I;t . i rt ¡t(¡ ' { TABLE OF CONTENTS P age III ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS.. ..... Vi INTRODUCTION: THE PROBLEM OF UNITY AND DIVER- SITY IN RELIGIONS I CHAPTER ONE : R. C. ZAEHNER: THE VARIITIES OF MYSTICAL EXPERIENCE 30 CHAPTER TWO : N. SMART: THE MYSTICAL, THE NUMINOUS AND RELIGIOUS TRADI- TIONS... 64 CHAPTER THREE: W. T. STACE: EXTROVERTIVE AND INTROVERTIVE MYSTICISM tlt CHAPTER FOUR: R. OTTO: THE MYSTICAL, THE NUMINOUS AND METAPHYS I CS 156 CHAPTER FIVE: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS 204 CHAPTER SIX : MYSTICAL EXPERIENCE AND ITS IN- TERPRETATION: AN ANALYSIS OF POSSIBLE MODELS. 213 CHAPTER SEVEN: THE VARIETIES OF MYSTICAL EX- PERIENCE: A PHILOSOPHICAL PROLEGOMENON 254 STLECT BIBLI OGRAPHY 295 SUMMA R Y The spiritual vacuum generated by the decline of t.he Christian world-view in the West has creaLed for Western man the opportunity of taking up any one of a variety of modes of spirituality. Religious diversity has become a fact in Western religious Iife. This increasj-ng pluralism has led to a real-isation of the philosophical problem in- herent in it, a probl-em crystallised in the so-called 'con- flicting truth cl-aimsr problem:- The different religions appear to make different and incompatible cl-aims about the nature of ultimate re afity, of divinity, ofl human nature , and cosmi c destiny .
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine's Three Discoveries: Faith, Will and History
    Augustine’s Three Discoveries: Faith, Will and History Augustine and the City of God Augustine (354-430) is usually treated, and quite justifiably so, as the first medieval philosopher in European intellectual history. However, we all know that he was neither medieval, nor a philosopher, nor, for that matter, a European. He was born and raised a Roman citizen in North Africa, where he was educated to be a public speaker, to become a professor of rhetoric first in Carthage and then in Rome, who, after a brief stint in the imperial court in Milan, having converted to Christianity, returned to Africa, where he became the bishop of Hippo and spent the rest of his life there, tending to his flock, writing theological treatises, while getting involved in sometimes rather bitter theological debates. But this brief summary of apparently conflicting, yet equally justified characterizations merely emphasizes Augustine’s significance as a transitional figure in intellectual history, straddling fundamentally different periods, indeed leading humanity from one into another within the time-span of a single human life. Looking at Augustine from this perspective, as one should especially in the context of a large-scale survey of intellectual history, approaching his monumental City of God, I believe we should focus precisely on those aspects of this work that point in the direction of the “new era”. Therefore, aside from the practical consideration of the impossibility of covering every aspect of this huge and enormously rich work in one sitting, I suggest we focus on those three main aspects of it that express what proved to be the “lasting novelties” of Augustine’s thought: his discoveries of faith, will and history as appropriate subjects of philosophical reflection.
    [Show full text]
  • Fideism and Presuppositionalism
    Grace Theological JournalS.1 ( 1987) 89- 99 FIDEISM AND PRESUPPOSITIONALISM STEPHEN R. SPENCER The oft-asserted view that a presuppositional apologetic is in­ herently fideistic raises the question of whether Cornelius Van Til was, indeed, afideist. When Van Til's writings are examined in light of fide ism defined as an advocacy of faith as the sole source of reliance in the ascertaining of truth, fide ism is seen as incompatible with Van Til's position. His presuppositional approach manifests a concern for truth, for rationality, and for a faith that has both content andfoundaiion. * * * INTRODUCTION ERTAINLY one of the most frequent characterizations of the pre­ C suppositional apologetic of Cornelius Van Til is that it is "fideistic." Lewis, for example, is concerned that Van Til, despite serving forty-five years as a professor of apologetics, has constructed a system of theology, not a system of apologetics. l In Lewis's estima­ tion, Van Til has not supplied a means of disputing with unbelievers concerning the truthfulness of Christianity. "In the name of defending the faith he has left the faith defenseless. ,,2 Montgomery likewise warns against Van Til's tendency to treat the unbeliever as a believer, working out systematic theology and its implications rather than verifying Christianity by "focusing upon their needs" and using as a "starting point" the "common rationality.,,3 Montgomery fears that Van Til has given the unbeliever "the impres­ sion that our gospel is as aprioristically, fideistically irrational as the presuppositional claims of its competitors.'" 'G. R. Lewis, "Van Til and Carnell-Part I," in Jerusalem and Athens (ed.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume and Pascal Terence Penelhum
    Document generated on 09/24/2021 7:46 p.m. Lumen Selected Proceedings from the Canadian Society for Eighteenth-Century Studies Travaux choisis de la Société canadienne d'étude du dix-huitième siècle Human Nature and Truth: Hume and Pascal Terence Penelhum Volume 12, 1993 URI: https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1012578ar DOI: https://doi.org/10.7202/1012578ar See table of contents Publisher(s) Canadian Society for Eighteenth-Century Studies / Société canadienne d'étude du dix-huitième siècle ISSN 1209-3696 (print) 1927-8284 (digital) Explore this journal Cite this article Penelhum, T. (1993). Human Nature and Truth: Hume and Pascal. Lumen, 12, 45–64. https://doi.org/10.7202/1012578ar Copyright © Canadian Society for Eighteenth-Century Studies / Société This document is protected by copyright law. Use of the services of Érudit canadienne d'étude du dix-huitième siècle, 1993 (including reproduction) is subject to its terms and conditions, which can be viewed online. https://apropos.erudit.org/en/users/policy-on-use/ This article is disseminated and preserved by Érudit. Érudit is a non-profit inter-university consortium of the Université de Montréal, Université Laval, and the Université du Québec à Montréal. Its mission is to promote and disseminate research. https://www.erudit.org/en/ 5. Human Nature and Truth: Hume and Pascal It may seem strange to combine the names of two such radically opposite thinkers as Blaise Pascal and David Hume. But I shall suggest that when we juxtapose some of the fundamental aspects of their thought, the result is instructive in several ways. First, though least in real impor• tance, I think it becomes possible to make some conjectures about direct influence from Pascal in the seventeenth century to Hume in the eight• eenth.
    [Show full text]
  • Theodicy and Reason Logic, Metaphysics
    THEODICY AND REASONTHEODICY Philosophica 2 — Theodicy and Reason Logic, Metaphysics, GERETTO, PERISSINOTTO CAMPOSAMPIERO, FAVARETTI and Theology in Leibniz’s Essais de Théodicée (1710) edited by Matteo Favaretti Camposampiero, Mattia Geretto, and Luigi Perissinotto Edizioni Ca’Foscari Theodicy and Reason Philosophica Collana diretta da Luigi Perissinotto Cecilia Rofena 2 Edizioni Ca’Foscari Philosophica Direttori Luigi Perissinotto (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Cecilia Rofena (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Comitato scientifico Silvana Borutti (Università degli studi di Pavia, Italia) Jean-Pierre Cometti (Université de Provence - Aix-Marseille I, France) Arnold Davidson (University of Chicago, USA) Roberta Dreon (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Giuseppe Goisis (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Daniele Goldoni (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Mauro Nobile (Università degli Studi di Milano-Bicocca, Italia) Gian Luigi Paltrinieri (Università Ca’ Foscari Venezia, Italia) Vicente Sanfélix Vidarte (Universitat de València-Estudi General, España) Direzione e redazione Univerisità Ca’ Foscari Venezia Dipartimento di Filosofia e Beni Culturali Palazzo Malcanton Marcorà Dorsoduro 3484/D, 30123 Venezia http://edizionicafoscari.unive.it/col/dbc/10/Philosophica Theodicy and Reason Logic, Metaphysics, and Theology in Leibniz’s Essais de Théodicée (1710) edited by Matteo Favaretti Camposampiero, Mattia Geretto, and Luigi Perissinotto Venezia Edizioni Ca’ Foscari - Digital Publishing 2016 Theodicy and Reason:
    [Show full text]
  • The Continuity of John Hick's Thought
    EVOLUTIONARY MONISM: THE CONTINUITY OF JOHN HICK'S THOUGHT A THESIS SUBMITTED IN CANDIDACY for THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF PHILOSOPHICAL FOUNDATIONS Stephen Shaw Institute for Christian Studies August 1985 CONTENTS INTRODUCTION................................................... 4 CHAPTER 1 - THE HUMAN KNOWER................................... 9 FAITH AS PROPOSITIONAL BELIEF.................................. 9 FAITH AS MEDIATED AWARENESS................................... 15 SIGNIFICANCE AND INTERPRETATION...........................16 SIGNIFICANCE AND ACTION.................................. 18 INTERPENETRATION AND MEDIATION............................19 THREE ORDERS OF OOGNITION................................ 19 Natural.... .............................. .......... 19 Moral.......... ...................... .............. 20 Religious........................................... 21 THE EVOLUTION OF RELIGIOUS CONSCIOUSNESS..................24 VARIATIONS IN INTERPRETIVE FREEDOM........................26 Natural.... .........................................26 Moral......... ......................................26 Religious............. .............................. 27 CHAPTER 2 - THE HUMAN IN THE MAKING........................... 29 THE TWO THEODICIES............................................ 29 THE FIRST STAGE OF CREATION, MORAL EVIL AND PAIN...............33 MORAL EVIL............................................... 33 PAIN..................................................... 36 THE EVOLUTIONARY PROCESS................................. 39
    [Show full text]
  • Faith and Reason
    Phil 2301 Intro to Philosophy FAITH AND REASON "More consequences for thought and action follow from the affirmation or denial of God than from answering any other basic question. They follow for those who regard the question as answerable only by faith or only by reason, and even for those who insist upon suspending judgment entirely." —Great Books of the Western World, volume 2, p. 543. Introduction: Why do you believe in God? I. The Relationship Between Faith and Reason A. Introductory questions on the relationship between faith and reason • Is religious belief and Christian faith rational? • Is Christian faith an essentially irrational activity? • Is Christian faith an arational activity? • If the claims of religious belief cannot be proven, is it still reasonable to prove these claims? • How many things are there in life that we cannot prove, and yet we believe them any way? • In this sense, could belief in God, and other religious beliefs be properly basic? • Is it sometimes morally permissible purposefully to get one self to believe what the evidence alone does not warrant, and this for pragmatic or existential reasons? • Is faith a separate form of life wherein external judgments are precluded and objective reason plays a very limited role? “For till it be resolved how far we are to be guided by reason, and how far by faith, we shall in vain dispute, and endeavor to convince one another in matters of religion.” —John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. by A. C. Fraser (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1894), II, 415. B. The precise issue What role should reason play in the validation or invalidation of religious belief systems and practices? I.
    [Show full text]
  • 4Freud's Moses
    UC Berkeley Berkeley Forum in the Humanities Title Freud and Monotheism: Moses and the Violent Origins of Relligion Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3xk7594z ISBN 9780823280025 Authors Sharvit, Gilad Feldman, Karen S Publication Date 2018 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California Freud and Monotheism Berkeley Forum in the Humanities Freud and Monotheism Moses and the Violent Origins of Religion Gilad Sharvit and Karen S. Feldman, editors Townsend Center for the Humanities University of California, Berkeley Fordham University Press New York Copyright © 2018 The Regents of the University of California All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means— electronic, mechanical, photocopy, recording, or any other— except for brief quotations in printed reviews, without the prior permission of the publisher. The publishers have no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs for external or third- party Internet websites referred to in this publication and do not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate. The publishers also produce their books in a variety of electronic formats. Some content that appears in print may not be available in electronic books. Library of Congress Cataloging- in- Publication Data available online at http://catalog.loc.gov. Printed in the United States of America 20 19 18 5 4 3 2 1 First edition Contents Introduction Gilad Sharvit and Karen S. Feldman 1 1. “Why [the Jews] Have Attracted This Undying Hatred” Richard J.
    [Show full text]