Introduction

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Introduction Introduction How it all Started The earliest discussion of the phenomenon of presuppositions in relation to a formal language probably traces back to the nineteenth century philosopher Gottlob Frege1. Frege’s most significant contribution to modern logic was his ground breaking development of axiomatic predicate logic. Predicate logic uses quantified variables, which makes it far more expressive than Aristotelian syllo- gistic and Stoic propositional logic. Predicate logic could be used to represent inferences involving arbitrarily complex mathematical statements, and success- fully deals with problems which traditional logic is unable to solve, such as the problem of multiple generality2. Amongst his many contributions, Frege is often credited with the principle of the compositionality of meaning, which is the principle that the meaning of a complex expression is determined by the meanings of its constituent expressions and its structure. This principle remains predominant in the field of mathematics, semantics, and natural language pro- cessing, playing a key role when logical representations are constructed from the syntactic structures of a given expression or formula. The details are spelled out formally subsequently, by people such as Tarski (1933; 1944), Montague (1970), ○ Westerstahl (1998), and Janssen (1997; 2001). Presuppositions were not Frege’s central concern. However, according to him, an ideal language should have a truth value for every one of its well- formed sentences. Presuppositions then, make natural language an unfortunate exception to this ideal, because presuppositions must be met in order for the ex- pression containing them to have a truth value. But sometimes presuppositions fail. For example, definite NPs come with a presupposition that they denote properly. Consider the following century old example (Russell 1905): 1Frege, in his article “On Sense and Reference” (1892), in a footnote to a discussion about adverbial clauses, talks about the referential presupposition in the sentence: “after the sepa- ration of Schleswig-Holstein from Denmark, Prussia and Austria quarreled”. Frege points out that the presupposition (Voraussetzung) in which Schleswig-Holstein must be thought of as part of Denmark, is a necessary condition for “the separation” to have a reference. 2The problem of multiple generality is the inability of traditional logic to determine valid inferences of statements involving more than one quantifier. For example: (i) Every number has a successor. (ii) There is a successor preceded by every number. The syntax of traditional logic permits exactly four sentence types: “All A’s are B’s”, “No A’s are B’s”, “Some A’s are B’s” and “Some A’s are not B’s”. Each type is a quantified sentence containing exactly one quantifier. However, (i) and (ii) each involve two quantifiers. The only way for traditional logic to deal with this is to reduce the second quantified expression to a term: ′ (i) Every number is (a-number-which-has-a-successor). (ii)′ Some successor is (a-successor-preceded-by-every-number). But even after this treatment, we cannot determine whether (i) entails (ii). 1 (1) The King of France is bald. The presuppositions in (1) are triggered by the definite NP ‘the King of France’. Frege observed that a singular definite description like this has two constraints associated to its referential function: There is at least one King of France- a presupposition that ‘the King’ must denote an entity in the Model of interpretation; and there is at most one King of France- a presupposition that ‘the King’ is unique in the context. Neither of these are asserted, in other words they are not stated explicitly in (1), and for this reason they are called ‘presuppositions’. These two presuppositions must be satisfied in order that the description can refer. If there is no King, or if there is more than one King of France, (1) will fail to have a proper truth value. Frege saw this as a shortcoming of natural languages when definite descriptions fail to denote some unique entity. The way in which he gets around this deficiency is to include a special nil entity, and whenever a definite description fails to satisfy the aforementioned presuppositions, to assign it assigned to the nil entity. To put this formally, we first designate the iota operator, (an upside down Greek iota), for descriptions (Gamut 1991). Descriptions are an addition to Frege’s predicate logic vocabulary. They are complex terms like the universal quantifier ∀ and the existential quantifier ∃ in that they always come with a variable and are followed by a propositional function which is their scope. Let be a formula and x a variable, in order to interpret descriptions we add the following to the semantics of predicate logic: (2) ⟦ x⟧M,g is the unique individual d ∈ D s.t. VM,g[x~d]() = 1 If there is no such unique individual d ∈ D, then x is assigned to d0, where d0 is the nil entity. At this point we simply have to ensure that d0 does not belong to the set of entities satisfying . In the example of (1), if there is no King of France, as long as d0 does not belong to the interpretation of bald, (1) will be false because d0 ∉ bald. This solution however, is ad hoc and merely scratches the surface of the problem of presupposition failure. Consider the negation of (1): (1)′ The King of France is not bald. Applying (2) to (1)′ just as we did for (1), when there is no King of France, the variable representing the King of France is assigned to d0. Since d0 ∉ bald ′ is the same as ¬(d0 ∈ ), (1) must be true. This outcome suggests that the King of France is not bald if there is no King of France, a rather unintuitive reading, since we typically expect both (1) and (1)′ to be false or unknown in circumstances where there is no such King. A possible solution here would require the modification of the negation operator so that its output for those formulae with d0 is either false or undefined. This modification ultimately leads to trivalent (Strawson 1952; Kleene 1952) and multivalent systems (Herzberger 1973; Martin 1977; Bergmann 1981), both of which have consequences on the entire logical framework that are unforseen by Frege. 2 The first notable attempt after Frege to deal with this problem is Russell. In On Denoting (1905), Russell characterizes the notion of nil entity (or in Russell’s own words, the null class3) as something which is used to denote the class of all “unreal individuals”. Russell firmly rejects the notion of unreal individuals, because to commit to the notion of some existing, yet unreal objects, such as ‘the round square’, ‘the King of France’, is “apt to infringe the law of contradiction”. Instead, he proposes an alternative: Let C be a denoting phrase, say ‘the term having the property F’; then the sentence “C has property G” translates to “there is one and only one term that has the property F, and that one has the property G”. Thus (1) according to Russell should really be read follows: (3) There is one and only one entity that is King of France and he is bald. This approach exemplifies the misleading form thesis, according to which the grammatical form of sentences sometimes does not reflect their logical form, and is therefore misleading. The underlying cause for confusion is that definite descriptions and proper names have the same syntactic function, as ‘the King of France’ and ‘Louis XIX’ (who does not exist) are syntactically interchangeable (substitution of one for the other preserves syntactic well-formedness). Russell points out that this grammatical similarity is deceptive. A sentence such as (1) consisting of a singular definite description and a predicate is not logically a subject-predicate sentence at all, despite its grammatical subject. ‘The King of France’ should not be thought of as a normal NP any more than quantified expressions like everyone and no one. Instead, a definite description is a kind of ‘existential proposition’ and the formulae representing it should be re-written to capture the logical form of such proposition4.For every one-place predica- 3Russell relates the null class to Frege in the following passage (Russell 1905): . Another way of taking the same course (so far as our present alternative is concerned) is adopted by Frege, who provides by definition some purely conven- tional denotation for the cases in which otherwise there would be none. Thus ‘the King of France’, is to denote the null-class. But this procedure, though it may not lead to actual logical error, is plainly artificial, and does not give an exact analysis of the matter. Thus if we allow that denoting phrases, in general, have the two sides of meaning and denotation, the cases where there seems to be no denotation cause difficulties both on the assumption that there really is a denotation and on the assumption that there really is none. 4Russell makes the further claim that proper names are in fact, concealed descriptions. Consider the following: (i) Socrates is a man. (ii) All man are mortal. (iii) (Therefore,) Socrates is mortal. Traditional logic is insufficient for the deductive reasoning from (i) to (iii), because it lacks the syntax to represent (ii). Even though (ii) could be represented as Mortal(S) where S=Socrates, Mortal(all man) simply won’t do for us to arrive at (iii). Frege improved the syllogistic logic system by introducing quantifiers which gives (ii): ∀x man(x) → Mortal(x). Russell expanded this further by claiming that proper names too, are quantified expressions: 3 tion containing a description expressed with the iota operator, we can give an equivalent formula expressed using the standard predicate logic quantifiers: (4) G( xFx) = ∃x(Fx ∧ (∀y(Fy → y=x)) ∧ Gx) And this translation can be generalized to arbitrary formulas of predicate logic.
Recommended publications
  • Semantics and Pragmatics
    Semantics and Pragmatics Christopher Gauker Semantics deals with the literal meaning of sentences. Pragmatics deals with what speakers mean by their utterances of sentences over and above what those sentences literally mean. However, it is not always clear where to draw the line. Natural languages contain many expressions that may be thought of both as contributing to literal meaning and as devices by which speakers signal what they mean. After characterizing the aims of semantics and pragmatics, this chapter will set out the issues concerning such devices and will propose a way of dividing the labor between semantics and pragmatics. Disagreements about the purview of semantics and pragmatics often concern expressions of which we may say that their interpretation somehow depends on the context in which they are used. Thus: • The interpretation of a sentence containing a demonstrative, as in “This is nice”, depends on a contextually-determined reference of the demonstrative. • The interpretation of a quantified sentence, such as “Everyone is present”, depends on a contextually-determined domain of discourse. • The interpretation of a sentence containing a gradable adjective, as in “Dumbo is small”, depends on a contextually-determined standard (Kennedy 2007). • The interpretation of a sentence containing an incomplete predicate, as in “Tipper is ready”, may depend on a contextually-determined completion. Semantics and Pragmatics 8/4/10 Page 2 • The interpretation of a sentence containing a discourse particle such as “too”, as in “Dennis is having dinner in London tonight too”, may depend on a contextually determined set of background propositions (Gauker 2008a). • The interpretation of a sentence employing metonymy, such as “The ham sandwich wants his check”, depends on a contextually-determined relation of reference-shifting.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 5: Methods of Proof for Boolean Logic
    Chapter 5: Methods of Proof for Boolean Logic § 5.1 Valid inference steps Conjunction elimination Sometimes called simplification. From a conjunction, infer any of the conjuncts. • From P ∧ Q, infer P (or infer Q). Conjunction introduction Sometimes called conjunction. From a pair of sentences, infer their conjunction. • From P and Q, infer P ∧ Q. § 5.2 Proof by cases This is another valid inference step (it will form the rule of disjunction elimination in our formal deductive system and in Fitch), but it is also a powerful proof strategy. In a proof by cases, one begins with a disjunction (as a premise, or as an intermediate conclusion already proved). One then shows that a certain consequence may be deduced from each of the disjuncts taken separately. One concludes that that same sentence is a consequence of the entire disjunction. • From P ∨ Q, and from the fact that S follows from P and S also follows from Q, infer S. The general proof strategy looks like this: if you have a disjunction, then you know that at least one of the disjuncts is true—you just don’t know which one. So you consider the individual “cases” (i.e., disjuncts), one at a time. You assume the first disjunct, and then derive your conclusion from it. You repeat this process for each disjunct. So it doesn’t matter which disjunct is true—you get the same conclusion in any case. Hence you may infer that it follows from the entire disjunction. In practice, this method of proof requires the use of “subproofs”—we will take these up in the next chapter when we look at formal proofs.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defence of Constructive Empiricism: Metaphysics Versus Science
    To appear in Journal for General Philosophy of Science (2004) In Defence of Constructive Empiricism: Metaphysics versus Science F.A. Muller Institute for the History and Philosophy of Science and Mathematics Utrecht University, P.O. Box 80.000 3508 TA Utrecht, The Netherlands E-mail: [email protected] August 2003 Summary Over the past years, in books and journals (this journal included), N. Maxwell launched a ferocious attack on B.C. van Fraassen's view of science called Con- structive Empiricism (CE). This attack has been totally ignored. Must we con- clude from this silence that no defence is possible against the attack and that a fortiori Maxwell has buried CE once and for all, or is the attack too obviously flawed as not to merit exposure? We believe that neither is the case and hope that a careful dissection of Maxwell's reasoning will make this clear. This dis- section includes an analysis of Maxwell's `aberrance-argument' (omnipresent in his many writings) for the contentious claim that science implicitly and per- manently accepts a substantial, metaphysical thesis about the universe. This claim generally has been ignored too, for more than a quarter of a century. Our con- clusions will be that, first, Maxwell's attacks on CE can be beaten off; secondly, his `aberrance-arguments' do not establish what Maxwell believes they estab- lish; but, thirdly, we can draw a number of valuable lessons from these attacks about the nature of science and of the libertarian nature of CE. Table of Contents on other side −! Contents 1 Exordium: What is Maxwell's Argument? 1 2 Does Science Implicitly Accept Metaphysics? 3 2.1 Aberrant Theories .
    [Show full text]
  • Situation Theory: a Survey
    ABSTRACT SITUATION THEORY: A SURVEY Situation semantics was developed as an alternative to possible-worlds semantics. While possible-worlds semantics defines the informational content of sentences in terms of complete descriptions of the way the world is or might be, situation semantics defines the informational content of sentences in terms of partial worlds called situations. Situation theory is a novel informational ontology developed to give situation semantics a rigorous mathematical foundation. In reviewing the literature, we observed that although there are a few texts introducing situation theory in varying levels of detail and systematicity, there has not yet been published, until now, a general survey of the situation-theory literature that might introduce and guide future scholars. We note that a similar, if perhaps less-pressing need exists for a survey of the situation-semantics literature, but regret that we must leave such a survey for others. Jacob Ian Lee December 2011 SITUATION THEORY: A SURVEY by Jacob Ian lee A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Science in Computer Science in the College of Science and Mathematics California State University, Fresno December 2011 © 2011 Jacob Ian Lee APPROVED For the Department of Computer Science: We, the undersigned, certify that the thesis of the following student meets the required standards of scholarship, format, and style of the university and the student's graduate degree program for the awarding of the master's degree. Jacob Ian Lee Thesis Author Todd Wilson (Chair) Computer Science Shigeko Seki Computer Science Shih-Hsi Liu Computer Science For the University Graduate Committee: Dean, Division of Graduate Studies AUTHORIZATION FOR REPRODUCTION OF MASTER’S THESIS X I grant permission for the reproduction of this thesis in part or in its entirety without further authorization from me, on the condition that the person or agency requesting reproduction absorbs the cost and provides proper acknowledgment of authorship.
    [Show full text]
  • Presupposition As Investigator Certainty in a Police Interrogation: the Case of Lorenzo Montoya’S False Confession
    Presupposition as investigator certainty in a police interrogation: The case of Lorenzo Montoya’s false confession Author: Philip Gaines This is a postprint of an article that originally appeared in Discourse & Society on July 2018. The final version can be found at https://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0957926518754417. Gaines, Philip. "Presupposition as investigator certainty in a police interrogation: The case of Lorenzo Montoya's false confession." Discourse & Society 29, no. 4 (July 2018): 399-419. DOI:10.1177/0957926518754417. Made available through Montana State University’s ScholarWorks scholarworks.montana.edu Presupposition as investigator certainty in a police interrogation: The case of Lorenzo Montoya’s false confession Philip Gaines Montana State University, USA Abstract This article presents an analysis of the use by police investigators of presupposition-bearing questions (PBQs) in interrogation as a process for communicating certainty of guilt. Among the techniques of interrogational maximization employed by police is the communication to the suspect of the interrogators’ certainty of the suspect’s guilt. While social science research notes that such communication of certainty is given directly, for example by statements that they ‘know’ the suspect is guilty or by direct accusations such as ‘you did it’, this analysis shows that certainty of guilt can also be communicated by presuppositions embedded in interrogation questions. Discourse analysis of the complete transcript of the interrogation of a 14-year-old suspect reveals further that through the use of 177 PBQs, interrogators are able to accrue inadvertent admissions to three crucial global ‘facts’ about the suspect’s involvement in the crime – each of which is composed of multiple subsidiary ‘facts’.
    [Show full text]
  • Entailment, Presupposition, and Implicature in the Work of Ernest Hemingway and Tim O'brien
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1994 The tS ylistic Mechanics of Implicitness: Entailment, Presupposition, and Implicature in the Work of Ernest Hemingway and Tim O'Brien. Donna Glee Williams Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Williams, Donna Glee, "The tS ylistic Mechanics of Implicitness: Entailment, Presupposition, and Implicature in the Work of Ernest Hemingway and Tim O'Brien." (1994). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 5768. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/5768 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough,m asubstandard r gins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand comer and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps.
    [Show full text]
  • Deduction (I) Tautologies, Contradictions And
    D (I) T, & L L October , Tautologies, contradictions and contingencies Consider the truth table of the following formula: p (p ∨ p) () If you look at the final column, you will notice that the truth value of the whole formula depends on the way a truth value is assigned to p: the whole formula is true if p is true and false if p is false. Contrast the truth table of (p ∨ p) in () with the truth table of (p ∨ ¬p) below: p ¬p (p ∨ ¬p) () If you look at the final column, you will notice that the truth value of the whole formula does not depend on the way a truth value is assigned to p. The formula is always true because of the meaning of the connectives. Finally, consider the truth table table of (p ∧ ¬p): p ¬p (p ∧ ¬p) () This time the formula is always false no matter what truth value p has. Tautology A statement is called a tautology if the final column in its truth table contains only ’s. Contradiction A statement is called a contradiction if the final column in its truth table contains only ’s. Contingency A statement is called a contingency or contingent if the final column in its truth table contains both ’s and ’s. Let’s consider some examples from the book. Can you figure out which of the following sentences are tautologies, which are contradictions and which contingencies? Hint: the answer is the same for all the formulas with a single row. () a. (p ∨ ¬p), (p → p), (p → (q → p)), ¬(p ∧ ¬p) b.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz's Ontological Proof of the Existence of God and the Problem Of
    Leibniz’s Ontological Proof of the Existence of God and the Problem of »Impossible Objects« Wolfgang Lenzen (Osnabrück) Abstract The core idea of the ontological proof is to show that the concept of existence is somehow contained in the concept of God, and that therefore God’s existence can be logically derived – without any further assumptions about the external world – from the very idea, or definition, of God. Now, G.W. Leibniz has argued repeatedly that the traditional versions of the ontological proof are not fully conclusive, because they rest on the tacit assumption that the concept of God is possible, i.e. free from contradiction. A complete proof will rather have to consist of two parts. First, a proof of premise (1) God is possible. Second, a demonstration of the “remarkable proposition” (2) If God is possible, then God exists. The present contribution investigates an interesting paper in which Leibniz tries to prove proposition (2). It will be argued that the underlying idea of God as a necessary being has to be interpreted with the help of a distinguished predicate letter ‘E’ (denoting the concept of existence) as follows: (3) g =df ιxE(x). Principle (2) which Leibniz considered as “the best fruit of the entire logic” can then be formalized as follows: (4) ◊E(ιxE(x)) → E(ιxE(x)). At first sight, Leibniz’s proof appears to be formally correct; but a closer examination reveals an ambiguity in his use of the modal notions. According to (4), the possibility of the necessary being has to be understood in the sense of something which possibly exists.
    [Show full text]
  • Minimal Pronouns1
    1 Minimal Pronouns1 Fake Indexicals as Windows into the Properties of Bound Variable Pronouns Angelika Kratzer University of Massachusetts at Amherst June 2006 Abstract The paper challenges the widely accepted belief that the relation between a bound variable pronoun and its antecedent is not necessarily submitted to locality constraints. It argues that the locality constraints for bound variable pronouns that are not explicitly marked as such are often hard to detect because of (a) alternative strategies that produce the illusion of true bound variable interpretations and (b) language specific spell-out noise that obscures the presence of agreement chains. To identify and control for those interfering factors, the paper focuses on ‘fake indexicals’, 1st or 2nd person pronouns with bound variable interpretations. Following up on Kratzer (1998), I argue that (non-logophoric) fake indexicals are born with an incomplete set of features and acquire the remaining features via chains of local agreement relations established in the syntax. If fake indexicals are born with an incomplete set of features, we need a principled account of what those features are. The paper derives such an account from a semantic theory of pronominal features that is in line with contemporary typological work on possible pronominal paradigms. Keywords: agreement, bound variable pronouns, fake indexicals, meaning of pronominal features, pronominal ambiguity, typologogy of pronouns. 1 . I received much appreciated feedback from audiences in Paris (CSSP, September 2005), at UC Santa Cruz (November 2005), the University of Saarbrücken (workshop on DPs and QPs, December 2005), the University of Tokyo (SALT XIII, March 2006), and the University of Tromsø (workshop on decomposition, May 2006).
    [Show full text]
  • What Is Presupposition Accommodation?
    Draft version from July 2000 What is Presupposition Accommodation? Kai von Fintel MIT In his paper “What is a Context of Utterance?”, Christopher Gauker (1998) argues that the phenomenon of informative presuppositions is incompatible with the “pragmatic” view of presuppositions as involving requirements on the common ground, the body of shared assumptions of the participants in a conversation. This is a surprising claim since most proponents of this view have in fact dealt with informative presuppositions by appealing to a process called presupposition accommodation. Gauker’s attack shows the need to clarify the nature of this process. Introduction: The Common Ground Theory of Presuppositions Here is a stylized version of the picture of information-gathering discourse developed by Stalnaker.1 The common ground of a conversation at a particular time is the set of propositions that the participants in that conversation at that time mutually assume to be taken for granted and not subject to (further) discussion. The common ground describes a set of worlds, the context set, which are those worlds in which all of the propositions in the common ground are true. The context set is the set of worlds that for all that is currently assumed to be taken for granted, could be the actual world. 1 Stalnaker (1972, 1973, 1974, 1978, 1988, 1998). Other important work in this tradition includes Karttunen (1974), Lewis (1979), Heim (1982, 1983, 1992), and Thomason (1990). When uttered assertively, sentences are meant to update the common ground. If the sentence is accepted by the participants, the proposition it expresses is added to the common ground.
    [Show full text]
  • A Prolegomenon to Situation Semantics
    A PROLEGOMENON TO SITUATION SEMANTICS David J. Israel Bolt Beranek and Newman Inc. Cambridge, MA 02238 Situation Semantics (yet?). ABSTRACT So what is there? Besides a few published An attempt is made to prepare Computational papers, each of them containing at least one Linguistics for Situation Semantics. position since abandoned~ there is a book ~ Attitudes literally on the very I INTRODUCTION verge of publication. This contains the philosophlcal/theoretlcal background of the program The editors of the AI Journal recently hit upon - The Big Picture. It also contains a very brief the nice notion of correspondents' columns. The treatment of a very simple fragment of ALIASS. And basic idea was to solicit experts in various what, the reader may well ask is ALIASS? An fields, both within and outside of Artificial Artificial Language for lliustratlng Aspects of Intelligence, to provide "guidance to important, ~Ituation ~emantlcs, that's what. Moreover there interesting current literature" in their fields. is in the works a ceiiaboratlve effort, to be For Philosophy, they made the happy choice of Dan called Situations andS. m This will contain Dennett; for natural language processing, the a "Fragment of Situation Semantics", a treatment of equally happy choice of Barbara Grosz. Each has so an extended fra~ent of ~. Last, for the far contributed one column, and these early moment, but not least, is a second book by Barwise contributions overlap in one, and as it happens, and Perry, ~ ~, which will include only one, particular; to wit: Situation~manties. a treatment of an even more extended fragment of Witness Dennett: English, together with a self-contalned treatment of the technical, mathematical background.
    [Show full text]
  • An Analysis of Presupposition Triggers in Hilary Clinton's First
    International Journal of English Linguistics; Vol. 6, No. 5; 2016 ISSN 1923-869X E-ISSN 1923-8703 Published by Canadian Center of Science and Education An Analysis of Presupposition Triggers in Hilary Clinton’s First Campaign Speech Ruiqing Liang1 & Yabin Liu1 1 School of Foreign Studies, Jinan University, Guangzhou, China Correspondence: Yabin Liu, School of Foreign Studies, Jinan University, Guangzhou, China. E-mail: [email protected] Received: July 19, 2016 Accepted: August 9, 2016 Online Published: September 23, 2016 doi:10.5539/ijel.v6n5p68 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.5539/ijel.v6n5p68 This paper is supported by “the Fundamental Research Funds for the Central Universities” (grant no.: 15JNYH007) and “the National Social Science Foundation of China” (grant no.:12BYY119). Abstract Presupposition triggers play a vital role in verbal communication. Based on Hilary Clinton’s first campaign speech, this paper intends to analyze the presupposition triggers at both lexical and syntactic levels, for the purpose of figuring out how Hilary succeeds in achieving her political intentions through the use of presupposition triggers, hoping to contribute to the composition and understanding of political speeches. Keywords: presupposition triggers, presupposition, Hilary Clinton, political speech 1. Introduction Presupposition, first put forward by German philosopher Gottlob Frege in 1892, was originally studied in philosophy of language and later introduced to the field of linguistics. As the study of presupposition continues, it has been found that presuppositions are typically generated by the use of lexical items or linguistic constructions. These lexical items and linguistic constructions are called presupposition triggers (Levinson, 1983; Huang, 2007). Presupposition has long been used as a property of language to mold the audience’s ideology.
    [Show full text]