On Russell's "Brief but Notorious Flirtation with Phenomenalism" in His Recent Book Entitled Russell, A.J

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

On Russell's On Russell's "brief but notorious flirtation with phenomenalism" In his recent book entitled Russell, A.J. Ayer claims that Russell in 1914 abandoned the causal theory of perception for a version of phenomenalism. l Ayer says that Russell made no attempt to develop this theory after 1914, and that he tacitly reverted to the causal theory in his later works. It is true that Russell significantly revised his views on perception in 1914, but I hope to show that Russell's revisions did not involve rejection of a causal theory. Russell, by his own admission, changed his views many times during his rich and lengthy philosophical career. Many commentators have made capital of these changes in accusing Russell of incoherence, whereas attentive reading of the works from The Problems of Philosophy (19l2} to H"wnan Knowledge (1948) discloses a unity in the questions handled, along with growth and development in the answers provided. Since Russell did change his theory of perception radically in 1914, one might ask whether my dis~greement with Ayer is merely a verbal dispute about what one calls a causal theory. I do not believe this is the case. In the first place, although the causal theory accepted in 1914 is different from his earl ier theory, it is a genuine causal theory in the sense that, like the earlier one, it locates perceptions at the end of causal chains which begin with physical objects. Russell con­ tinually emphasized this as a crucial feature of any correct theory of perception. Secondly, there is Ayer's claim that Russell lapses to the earlier theory in his later works. This, I believe, is a mistake. The mistake arises, quite naturally, from the difficulty in understanding how an event (in the early works, a sense-datum or sensibile; and in the later works, sensations or percepts} can be caused by a physical object, when at the same time that event is one of the events out of which the physical object is constructed. When Russell's solution to this problem is grasped it is no longer feasible to attribute a reversion to the pre­ 1914 theory to him. Accordingly, one of the aims of this paper is to adumbrate Russell's solution. lA.J. Ayer, Russell (London: Fontana, 19721, pp. 72~I02. 13 Russell's 1914 works, notably "The Relation between Physics and to solve problems which arose from the apparent incompatibility between Sense-Data" and Our Knowledge of the External World,2 conta in suggestions the .knowledge we have of physical objects from our perceptions and the which greatly influenced later versions of phenomenalism such as Carnap's knowledge we have of the same objects through a study of modern physics. Aufbau. Russell himself admits that in "The Relation between Physics Common-sense views of perception tell us that these objects have certain and Sense-Da ta" he was strongly attracted by the possibil tty of inter­ features which they cannot possibly possess if physics is correct. For preting physical objects as structures composed of elements actually example, common sense tells us that the surfaces of these objects possess experienced. However, in the same paper, he says that he became convinced continuity with regard to color and tangibility, whereas physics tells. us that this was an impossible programme, and so "gave up the attempt to that the surfaces are outer layers of gappy systems of colorless particles. construct 'matter' out of experienced data alone, and contented [himself] While trying to present a coherent picture of the world from the with a picture of the world which fitted physics and perception into a viewpoints of both physics and perception, Russell made a remarkable single whole."3 Grover Maxwell refers to this passage when he speaks of discovery: Russell's "brief but notorious fl irtation with phenomenal ism in 1914."4 There were several novelties in the theory as to our knowledge of the external world which burst upon me on New Year's Day 1914. The most However, as Russell well knew, a flirtation does not constitute an important of these was the theory that space has six dimensions and espousal. The 1914 works have been the chief source of those who attri­ not only three. s bute phenomenalism to Russell in that period. The works are well known, What we ordinarily think of as three-dimensional physical space is made but the passages in which Russell explicitly accepts a causal theory of up of points. Each of these points, however, may be considered as a perception have been surprisingly overlooked. perspective, or point of view, of a perceiver. At each perspective, then, there is a three-dimensional perceptual space which is private to the Prior to 1914 Russell accepted a version of the causal theory in observer. This three-dimensional space at each point in a three-dimensional which sense-data with which we are acquainted provide the basis for space yields a space with six dimensions. inferences to physical objects. The physical objects, such as tables The importance of this discovery, which to many must seem eccentric, and chairs, are things which we can know only indirectly, but they are baroque, or even unintelligible, cannot be overemphasized. Russell had the causes of sense-data. Ayer calls this inference to things a type always regarded sense-data as physical entities in as much as they were different from the type of things directly known a "vertical inference", suitable objects of study for physics. They were, however, private to and he characterizes causal theories by their appeal to vertical inference. each perceiver, and their physical location was held to be in the region Only two years after the publication of The FToblems of Philosophy of the brain of a perceiver. With the recognition of the six-dimensional Russell realized something which called for a drastic revision in his character of space, the greatest difficulty in considering sense-data as theory of perception. At this time Russell was inspired by Whitehead's parts of external physical objects was overcome, and the way was made theory of matter, and was bolstered by the success they had had together in replacing 'inferred entities by logical constructions in FTimipia clear for constructing physical objects from sense-data, rather than in­ Mathematica. Russell regarded the use of this technique: "Whenever ferring the existence of those objects which we could never experience. possible replace inferred entities by logical constructions", as the Prior to Russell's realization that a sense-datum could be located in two places, that is, in the private space of an observer, and in the supreme maxim of scientific philosophizing. He sought to use this method public perspective space, it seemed a mystery that data which are essen­ tially private could provide any reliable information about the world of 20ur Knowledge of the External World as a Field for Scientific Method in Philosophy (London: Allen and Unwin, 1926). ThIs was first puollshed physics. in 1914. My references are to the 1926 edition. "The Relation oetween From this point on Russell was aware of, and repeatedly pointed out Physics and Sense-Data" was first publ ished in 1914, and was reprinted in Mysticism and Logic (London: Longmans, Green, 1918; New York: Norton, in his later works, the two requirements of a satisfactory theory of 1929). All page numbers refer to the latter edition. perception: (1) Ontologically, perceptions are events. Perception is 3My Philosophical Development (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1959), p. 105. 4Bertrand Russell, ed. D.F. Pears (New York: Anchor, 1972), p. 110. SMy Philosophical Development, p. 105. 14 15 what happens when one becomes aware of something through his senses. 6 whenever it is possible to do without them, Russell found that the only In order to locate these events in space-time and to explain their entities whose existence he must assume in order to connect the world of causal connections with other events, a physical theory is required. physics with the world of sense-perception, are entities which are meta­ (2) From the viewpoint of epistemology, perception is the process of physically similar to sense-data, except that they exist unperceived. getting to know certain kinds of facts without inference. These facts Both actual sense-data and those which would be data if observed are are the basis of all other empirical knowledge. As Russell says, called "sensibilia". Unsensed sensibilia differ from Mill's permanent In considering the reasons for believing in any empirical statement, possibilities of sensation, because, whereas unsensed sensibilia are we cannot escape from perception. '" individual percepts are the only possible data, they have real, not merely possible, existence. basis of all our knowledge, and no method exists by which we can be­ gin with data which are public to many observers.? Russell used a principle of analogy to infer that sensibilia exist at perspectives where no perceiver is present. Ayer classifies this in­ But the epistemological and ontological aspects of perception are not ference to unsensed sensibil ia as a "horizontal inference", i.e. an in­ unrelated. Russell ultimately accepts a causal theory of perception ference which invokes only entities which are of the same type as the because he believes that, even if the account of the world given by entities available to experience. physics were ontologically correct, "Epistemologically, physics might Ayer distinguishes Russell's two theories of perception on the be expected to collapse if perceptions have no external causes."8 The basis of the distinction between horizontal and vertical inferences to great virtue of Russell's theory is its abllity to provide a unified the existence of the external world.
Recommended publications
  • A Companion to Analytic Philosophy
    A Companion to Analytic Philosophy Blackwell Companions to Philosophy This outstanding student reference series offers a comprehensive and authoritative survey of philosophy as a whole. Written by today’s leading philosophers, each volume provides lucid and engaging coverage of the key figures, terms, topics, and problems of the field. Taken together, the volumes provide the ideal basis for course use, represent- ing an unparalleled work of reference for students and specialists alike. Already published in the series 15. A Companion to Bioethics Edited by Helga Kuhse and Peter Singer 1. The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy Edited by Nicholas Bunnin and Eric 16. A Companion to the Philosophers Tsui-James Edited by Robert L. Arrington 2. A Companion to Ethics Edited by Peter Singer 17. A Companion to Business Ethics Edited by Robert E. Frederick 3. A Companion to Aesthetics Edited by David Cooper 18. A Companion to the Philosophy of 4. A Companion to Epistemology Science Edited by Jonathan Dancy and Ernest Sosa Edited by W. H. Newton-Smith 5. A Companion to Contemporary Political 19. A Companion to Environmental Philosophy Philosophy Edited by Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit Edited by Dale Jamieson 6. A Companion to Philosophy of Mind 20. A Companion to Analytic Philosophy Edited by Samuel Guttenplan Edited by A. P. Martinich and David Sosa 7. A Companion to Metaphysics Edited by Jaegwon Kim and Ernest Sosa Forthcoming 8. A Companion to Philosophy of Law and A Companion to Genethics Legal Theory Edited by John Harris and Justine Burley Edited by Dennis Patterson 9. A Companion to Philosophy of Religion A Companion to African-American Edited by Philip L.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Theory-Construction and the Self-Image of Philosophy
    Open Journal of Philosophy, 2014, 4, 231-243 Published Online August 2014 in SciRes. http://www.scirp.org/journal/ojpp http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/ojpp.2014.43031 Philosophical Theory-Construction and the Self-Image of Philosophy Niels Skovgaard Olsen Department of Philosophy, University of Konstanz, Konstanz, Germany Email: [email protected] Received 25 May 2014; revised 28 June 2014; accepted 10 July 2014 Copyright © 2014 by author and Scientific Research Publishing Inc. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution International License (CC BY). http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ Abstract This article takes its point of departure in a criticism of the views on meta-philosophy of P.M.S. Hacker for being too dismissive of the possibility of philosophical theory-construction. But its real aim is to put forward an explanatory hypothesis for the lack of a body of established truths and universal research programs in philosophy along with the outline of a positive account of what philosophical theories are and of how to assess them. A corollary of the present account is that it allows us to account for the objective dimension of philosophical discourse without taking re- course to the problematic idea of there being worldly facts that function as truth-makers for phi- losophical claims. Keywords Meta-Philosophy, Hacker, Williamson, Philosophical Theories 1. Introduction The aim of this article is to use a critical discussion of the self-image of philosophy presented by P. M. S. Hacker as a platform for presenting an alternative, which offers an account of how to think about the purpose and cha- racter of philosophical theories.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine on Knowledge
    Augustine on Knowledge Divine Illumination as an Argument Against Scepticism ANITA VAN DER BOS RMA: RELIGION & CULTURE Rijksuniversiteit Groningen Research Master Thesis s2217473, April 2017 FIRST SUPERVISOR: dr. M. Van Dijk SECOND SUPERVISOR: dr. dr. F.L. Roig Lanzillotta 1 2 Content Augustine on Knowledge ........................................................................................................................ 1 Acknowledgements ................................................................................................................................ 4 Preface .................................................................................................................................................... 5 Abstract ................................................................................................................................................... 6 Introduction ............................................................................................................................................ 7 The life of Saint Augustine ................................................................................................................... 9 The influence of the Contra Academicos .......................................................................................... 13 Note on the quotations ........................................................................................................................ 14 1. Scepticism ........................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Would ''Direct Realism'' Resolve the Classical Problem of Induction?
    NOU^S 38:2 (2004) 197–232 Would ‘‘Direct Realism’’ Resolve the Classical Problem of Induction? MARC LANGE University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill I Recently, there has been a modest resurgence of interest in the ‘‘Humean’’ problem of induction. For several decades following the recognized failure of Strawsonian ‘‘ordinary-language’’ dissolutions and of Wesley Salmon’s elaboration of Reichenbach’s pragmatic vindication of induction, work on the problem of induction languished. Attention turned instead toward con- firmation theory, as philosophers sensibly tried to understand precisely what it is that a justification of induction should aim to justify. Now, however, in light of Bayesian confirmation theory and other developments in epistemology, several philosophers have begun to reconsider the classical problem of induction. In section 2, I shall review a few of these developments. Though some of them will turn out to be unilluminating, others will profitably suggest that we not meet inductive scepticism by trying to justify some alleged general principle of ampliative reasoning. Accordingly, in section 3, I shall examine how the problem of induction arises in the context of one particular ‘‘inductive leap’’: the confirmation, most famously by Henrietta Leavitt and Harlow Shapley about a century ago, that a period-luminosity relation governs all Cepheid variable stars. This is a good example for the inductive sceptic’s purposes, since it is difficult to see how the sparse background knowledge available at the time could have entitled stellar astronomers to regard their observations as justifying this grand inductive generalization. I shall argue that the observation reports that confirmed the Cepheid period- luminosity law were themselves ‘‘thick’’ with expectations regarding as yet unknown laws of nature.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception Is Truth
    Perception is Truth... WHEN IT COMES TO LEASING AND SHOPPING REPORTS What is the truth? This age old question has some very deep implications that go way beyond the point of this training tip. Yet, the question reminds us that two people can experience the same incident and walk away with completely different perceptions of what actually happened. Sometimes, just like beauty, "truth” is in the eye of the beholder. It is a matter of perception. Shopping report information is a vivid example of the fact that perception is reality. Occasionally, an EPMS shopper remembers a specific leasing presentation somewhat differently than the on-site professional who was shopped and later evaluated in a written format. The shopper reports that the leasing consultant was a bit distracted and indifferent, not very friendly, or “didn’t seem interested in meeting my needs”. Yet, that individual’s supervisor cannot believe that this very friendly and warm staff member could ever come across in any way but delightful, enthusiastic and professional! “Everyone loves her!” the supervisor explains. Sometimes the gap between what the leasing professional believes about her presentation and what the shopper describes comes down to perception. Regardless of what really (or not really!) happened, the perception of the shopper – and that of the typical rental prospect – is the only “truth” that really matters! Leasing is all about perception, isn’t it? Fellow onsite associates may say, “He is the friendliest guy you’ll ever meet! We love him!” But if this “friendliest guy” is perceived as unfriendly, to that prospect he is unfriendly! “You know, Sara is really nice once you get to know her!” This may be “true”; but the reality is the prospect is unlikely to spend enough time “getting to know” Sara to override their initial impression.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Chemistry
    Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Chemistry Jaap van Brakel Abstract: In this paper I assess the relation between philosophy of chemistry and (general) philosophy of science, focusing on those themes in the philoso- phy of chemistry that may bring about major revisions or extensions of cur- rent philosophy of science. Three themes can claim to make a unique contri- bution to philosophy of science: first, the variety of materials in the (natural and artificial) world; second, extending the world by making new stuff; and, third, specific features of the relations between chemistry and physics. Keywords : philosophy of science, philosophy of chemistry, interdiscourse relations, making stuff, variety of substances . 1. Introduction Chemistry is unique and distinguishes itself from all other sciences, with respect to three broad issues: • A (variety of) stuff perspective, requiring conceptual analysis of the notion of stuff or material (Sections 4 and 5). • A making stuff perspective: the transformation of stuff by chemical reaction or phase transition (Section 6). • The pivotal role of the relations between chemistry and physics in connection with the question how everything fits together (Section 7). All themes in the philosophy of chemistry can be classified in one of these three clusters or make contributions to general philosophy of science that, as yet , are not particularly different from similar contributions from other sci- ences (Section 3). I do not exclude the possibility of there being more than three clusters of philosophical issues unique to philosophy of chemistry, but I am not aware of any as yet. Moreover, highlighting the issues discussed in Sections 5-7 does not mean that issues reviewed in Section 3 are less im- portant in revising the philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Theory of Knowledge and Hegel's Criticism
    U.Ü. FEN-EDEBİYAT FAKÜLTESİ SOSYAL BİLİMLER DERGİSİ Yıl: 2, Sayı: 2, 2000-2001 KANT’S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE AND HEGEL’S CRITICISM A. Kadir ÇÜÇEN* ABSTRACT Kant inquires into the possibility, sources, conditions and limits of knowledge in the tradition of modern philosophy. Before knowing God, being and reality, Kant, who aims to question what knowledge is, explains the content of pure reason. He formalates a theory of knowledge but his theory is neither a rationalist nor an empiricist theory of knowledge. He investigates the structure of knowledge, the possible conditions of experience and a priori concepts and categories of pure reason; so he makes a revolution like that of Copernicus . Hegel, who is one of proponents of the German idealism, criticizes the Kantian theory of knowledge for “wanting to know before one knows”. For Hegel, Kant’s a priori concepts and categories are meaningless and empty. He claims that the unity of subject and object has been explained in that of the “Absolute”. Therefore, the theory of knowledge goes beyond the dogmatism of the “thing-in- itself” and the foundations of mathematics and natural sciences; and reaches the domain of absolute knowledge. Hegel’s criticism of Kantian theory of knowledge opens new possibilities for the theory of knowledge in our age. ÖZET Kant’ın Bilgi Kuramı ve Hegel’in Eleştirisi Modern felsefe geleneği çerçevesinde Kant, bilginin imkânını, kaynağını, kapsamını ve ölçütlerini ele alarak, doğru bilginin sınırlarını irdelemiştir. Tanrı’yı, varlığı ve gerçekliği bilmeden önce, bilginin neliğini sorgulamayı kendine amaç edinen Kant, saf aklın içeriğini incelemiştir. Saf aklın a priori kavram ve kategorilerini, deneyin görüsünü ve bilgi yapısını veren, fakat ne usçu ne de deneyci * Uludag University, Faculty of Sciences and Letters, Dept.
    [Show full text]
  • Life with Augustine
    Life with Augustine ...a course in his spirit and guidance for daily living By Edmond A. Maher ii Life with Augustine © 2002 Augustinian Press Australia Sydney, Australia. Acknowledgements: The author wishes to acknowledge and thank the following people: ► the Augustinian Province of Our Mother of Good Counsel, Australia, for support- ing this project, with special mention of Pat Fahey osa, Kevin Burman osa, Pat Codd osa and Peter Jones osa ► Laurence Mooney osa for assistance in editing ► Michael Morahan osa for formatting this 2nd Edition ► John Coles, Peter Gagan, Dr. Frank McGrath fms (Brisbane CEO), Benet Fonck ofm, Peter Keogh sfo for sharing their vast experience in adult education ► John Rotelle osa, for granting us permission to use his English translation of Tarcisius van Bavel’s work Augustine (full bibliography within) and for his scholarly advice Megan Atkins for her formatting suggestions in the 1st Edition, that have carried over into this the 2nd ► those generous people who have completed the 1st Edition and suggested valuable improvements, especially Kath Neehouse and friends at Villanova College, Brisbane Foreword 1 Dear Participant Saint Augustine of Hippo is a figure in our history who has appealed to the curiosity and imagination of many generations. He is well known for being both sinner and saint, for being a bishop yet also a fellow pilgrim on the journey to God. One of the most popular and attractive persons across many centuries, his influence on the church has continued to our current day. He is also renowned for his influ- ence in philosophy and psychology and even (in an indirect way) art, music and architecture.
    [Show full text]
  • Studies on Collingwood, History and Civilization
    Studies on Collingwood, History and Civilization Jan van der Dussen Studies on Collingwood, History and Civilization Jan van der Dussen Heerlen , The Netherlands ISBN 978-3-319-20671-4 ISBN 978-3-319-20672-1 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-20672-1 Library of Congress Control Number: 2015951386 Springer Cham Heidelberg New York Dordrecht London © Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifi cally the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfi lms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specifi c statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. Printed on acid-free paper Springer International Publishing AG Switzerland is part of Springer Science+Business Media (www. springer.com) Acknowledgements The following four essays are reproduced from their original publication.
    [Show full text]
  • Perception and Law Enforcement
    Perception and Law Enforcement Lt. Norman Hale White County Sheriff Department School of Law Enforcement Supervision Session XXXII Criminal Justice Institute Introduction Since the beginning, perception has been used by everyone. When man first said I am naked, I need clothing. The perception was I am naked. Without understanding why things are the way they appear man was fearful of the world around him. Superstitions overwhelmed man and his thoughts. It was an effort to explain the unexplainable. This is the perception of man and his surroundings. Early man worshiped nature in an attempt to change what was happening. At one time, it was believed that a man lived in the moon. This was based on the face seen on the moon. More resonantly, many believed there was or had been life on Mars, because of a photo taken as a satellite passed Mars showing a face on the surface (face on mars). This raised a large stir among people and the scientific community. It was not until some time later when a new photo was taken by a passing satellite, that the face on Mars proved to be a mountain and the face was formed by shadows cast across the surface of the mountain (face on mars). The attempt to understand how things are perceived goes back before the Egyptians were building pyramids. Modern man has devoted an extensive amount of time to studying perception and how it affects man. As the understanding of perception increases, the mystery that caused many superstitions is solved and man is no longer fearful.
    [Show full text]
  • The Origins and Legacy of Quine's Naturalism
    The Origins and Legacy of Quine’s Naturalism 17-18 December 2019 ABSTRACTS Jansenn-Lauret and Macbride: W.V. Quine and David Lewis: Structural (Epistemological) Humility. In this paper we argue that W.V. Quine and D.K. Lewis, despite their differences and their different receptions, came to a common intellectual destination: epistemological structuralism. We begin by providing an account of Quine’s epistemological structuralism as it came to its mature development in his final works, Pursuit of Truth (1990) and From Stimulus to Science (1995), and we show how this doctrine developed our of his earlier views on explication and the inscrutability of reference. We then turn to the correspondence between Quine and Lewis which sets the scene for Lewis’s adoption of structuralism vis-a-vis set theory in the Appendix to his Parts of Classes (1990). We conclude, drawing further from Lewis’s correspondence, by arguing that Lewis proceeded from there to embrace in one of his own final papers, ‘Ramseyan Humility’ (2001), an encompassing form of epistemological structuralism, whilst discharging the doctrine of reference magnetism that had hitherto set Lewis apart from Quine. Rogério Severo: A change in Quine’s reasons for holophrastic indeterminacy of translation Up until the early 1970s Quine argued that the underdetermination of theories by observations is a reason for holophrastic indeterminacy of translation. This is still today thought of as Quine’s main reason for the thesis. Yet, his 1975 formulation of underdetermination renders that argument invalid. This paper explains why. It also indicates Quine’s reasons for holophrastic indeterminacy after 1975, and offers an additional reason for it.
    [Show full text]
  • Brsq #142-144
    THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY QUARTERLY Fall 2009 Issue Numbers 142 -144 / May -November 2009 THE ROAD TO CONNECTICUT Published by The Bertrand Russell Society with the support of Lehman College - City University of New York THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SoCIET¥ QUARTERLY is the official organ of the THE BERTRAND RUSSELL SOCIETY Bertrand Russell Society. It publishes Society news and proceedings, and QUARTERLY articles on the history of analytic philosophy, especially those on Russell's life and works, including historical materials and reviews of recent work on Fall 2009 Issue Russell. Scholarly articles appearing in the a"crrfer/,v are peer-reviewed. Numbers 142-144 / May -November 2009 Co-EDITORS: Rosalind Carey and John Ongley ASSOCIATE EDITOR: Ray Perkins Jr. EDITORIAL BOARD Rosalind Carey, Lehman College-CUNY THE ROAD TO CONNECTICUT John Ongley, Bloomsburg University Raymond Perkins, Jr., Plymouth State University Christopher Pincock, Purdue University David Hyder, University of Ottawa CONTENTS Anat Biletzki, Tel Aviv University SuBMISsloNS : All communications to the Ber/ra#cJ Rwssc// Soci.edy gwcrr/er- In This Issue /y, including manuscripts. book reviews, and letters to the editor, should be Society News sent to: Prof. Rosalind Carey, Philosophy Department, Lehman College- ln Memoriam: Theo Meijer CUNY, 250 Bed ford Park Blvd. West, Bronx, NY 10468, USA, or by email to: [email protected]. Feature SuBSCRlpTloNS: The BRS gwc}rfedy is free to members of the Bertrand Rus- sell Society. Society membership is $35 a year for individuals, $40 for cou- Nicholas Griffin Speaks His Mind: An Interview by ples, and $20 for students and limited income individuals.
    [Show full text]