Logics for Conditionals

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Logics for Conditionals LOGICS FOR CONDITIONALS LOGICS FOR CONDITIONALS ACADEMISCH PROEFSCHRIFT ter verkrijging van de graad van doctor in de Wijsbegeerte aan de Universiteit van Amsterdam, op gezag van de Rector Magnificus dr. D.W.Bresters, hoogleraar in de Faculteit der Wiskunde en Natuurwetenschappen, in het openbaar te verdedigen in de Aula van de Universiteit (tijdelijk Roetersstraat 15), op vrijdag 4 oktober 1985 te 14.30 uur door FRANCISCUS JACOBUS MARIA MARTINUS VELTMAN geboren te Eindhoven Pnomoioneb: prof.dr. J.F.A.K. van Benthem,Rijksuniversiteit, Groningen prof.dr. J.A.W. Kamp,University of Texas, Austin ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I do not know to whomI am most indebted, to Johan van Benthem or to Hans Kamp. What I do know is that this would have been an altogether different thesis if I had not had the privilege of having mHfi.ofthem as supervisors. With his gift for anticipation Hansis the ideal person to air ones views to - even long before they deserve it. Muchof what is new in the following was inspired by discussions with him. But where Hans was the one who most encouraged me to follow up my own ideas, Johan saw to it that I did not get too wild about them. He has always urged me to put things in a broader perspective and his commentsand questions determined the final shape of this book. I amgrateful also to myteachers at the University of Utrecht, my former colleagues at the Erasmus University in Rotterdam, and mypresent colleagues at the University of Amsterdam.In this connection I want to mention in particular Jeroen van Rijen, Dick de Jongh, Roel de Vrijer, Jeroen Groenendijk, Martin Stokhof and Fred Landman: Jeroen van Rijen's ideas on the philosophy of logic greatly influenced mine; the proofs in this book have benefited much from Dick de Jongh's mathematical taste; Roel de Vrijer carefully read the manuscript and suggested several important improvements on the presentation; Jeroen Groenendijk's and Martin Stokhof's preoccupation with the role of background information in matters of semantics and pragmatics has been of great importance for the development of my own views; and Fred Landmangets the prize for asking the nastiest questions. As will become clear from the notes many other people have by their suggestions and criticism contributed to the contents of this book. I cannot here mention each of them by name, but I amgrateful to all of them. As for editional matters, I amgreatly indebted to Michael Morreau who tried his utmost to turn my double Dutch into readable English. Marjorie Pigge typed this book and I want to thank her for the great care with which she did so. This book has been nearing completion for quite some time. Nowthat it is finally finished, I wouldlike to dedicate it to all those whoare relieved that it is. Amsterdam Frank Veltman August, 1985 CONTENTS Acknowledgements PART I: THE PROBLEM OF CONDITIONALS 1 I.1. METHODOLOGICAL REMARKS 1 I.1.1. The case of the marbles 2 I.1.2. Logic as a descriptive science 5 I.1.2.1. Therationalist tradition 7 1.1.2.2. The empirical approach 9 I.1.3. -Amore pragmatic View 14 I.2. EXPLANATORYSTRATEGIES 22 1.2.1. Logical validity 23 I.2.1.1. The standard explanation 23 I.2.1.2. Truth and evidence 29 1.2.1.3. Probability semantics 32 I.2.1.4. Relevance Logici 38 I.2.2. Pragmatic correctness 40 I.2.3. Logical form 44 49 Notes to Part I PART II: POSSIBLE WORLDS SEMANTICS 52 (mainly on counterfactual conditionals) II.1. PRELIMINARIES §? II.1.1. Worlds and propositions 52 II.1.2. Logical notions 61 II.2. DELINEATIONS Bé II.2.1. Constraints on consequents 58 II.2.2. Constraints on antecedents 78 II.3. ALTERNATIVES gb II.3.1. Ramsey's suggestion and Stalnaker‘s theory 90 II.3.2. Comparative similarity according to Lewis 99 II.3.3. Premise semantics 103“ II.3.4. Comparative similarity induced 113 II.4. MODELTHEORETIC RESULTS 118 II.4.1. Comparingordering functions and selection 119 functions II.4.2. The completeness of 9 126 II.4.3. Extensions of P 132 Notes to Part II 143 PARTIII: DATA SEMANTICS &48 (mainly on indicative conditionals) III.1. SEMANTIC STABILITY AND INSTABILITY 149 III.1.1. Information models 149 III.1.2. Betweenassertability and truth 155 III.1.3. Data logic. Preliminaries 170 180 III .2. PRAGMATIC CORRECTNESS AND INCORRECTNESS III.2.1. Gricean constraints 181 III.2.2. Oddconditionals 183 III.2.3; A test for pragmatic correctness 188 III.3. DATA LOGIC 192 III.3.1. Deduction principles 192 III.3.2. Completeness and decidability 195 III.4. PROBLEMS AND PROSPECTS 202 III.4.1. Data lattices 202 III.4.2. Complexconditionals 207 III.4.3. Counterfactuals 210 Notes to Part III 213 References 218 Samenvatting (summary in Dutch) 223 PART I THE PWROBLEM OF CONDITIONALS I.1. METHODOLOGICAL REMARKS To those whobelieve that there is such a thing as the logic of conditionals this dissertation mayappear to be yet another attempt to unravel its secrets - which it is not. As a logician, you can do no more than devise a logic 501 conditionals and try to persuade your readers to adopt it. Youmay succeed in doing so if you are able to demonstrate that the one you propose is a better logic for conditionals than the ones proposed so far. The phrase ‘better for conditionals‘ should, however, not be misunderstood. In particular, it should not be interpreted as meaning ‘morelike the real one’. The best logic for conditionals one might propose is not that which they actually possess. It cannot be, not because this actual logic would be not good enough, but simply because there is no such thing. Whethera given logic is better than somealternative has little to do with its better fitting the facts; it is more a question of efficacy. This is one of the theses defended in the following introductory pages. It is put forward whenthe question is discussed as to howone should choose between rival logical theories. That is a very natural question to ask in an introduction to the problem of conditionals. If only because so manytheories have been put forward, all purporting to solve the problem, that putting yet another one on the market might seemto only add to the difficulties. I.1.1. The case of the marbles Here is an example which will return regularly in muchof the following. There are three marbles: one red, one blue, and one yellow. They are known to be distributed among two matchboxes, called 1 and-2. The only other thing which you are told is that there is at least one marble in each box. The various possibilities which this leaves open can be summarized as follows: box 1. box 2 I blue yellow, red II yellow ' blue, red III red blue, yellow IV yellow, red blue V red, blue yellow VI blue, yellow red Bearing these possibilities in mind, you will have to agree that (1) The yeflflow manbfie LA in box 1, £5 both 05 the othenb ahe to be fiound in box 2' ' ' Nowsuppose someone no better informed than yourself were to claim that (2) The ye££ow*manb£e.tAtn box 7 t5 the btue manbte to tn box 2 Youwill disagree. Youmay even go as far as to assert (3) It tbiuflibo that t5 the btue manbteto tn box 2, the yettow one to tn box 1 After all, the yellow marble could just as well be in box 2 together with the blue one, as long as the red one might yet be in box 1. Things are different, however, if it is excluded that the red marble is in box 1. i In that case, (2) holds. That is, (4) 15 the ted manbte to tn box 2, then t5 the btue manbte to tn box 2 at wett, the ye££ow'manbte to tn box 1 For those whodo accept the last two statements there is a surprise. in . store. Using . standard logical . notation . 1 ), we see that sentences (3) and (4) are respectively of the form (3') -(b£ue tn 2-» yettow tn 1) (4‘) ned tn 2 a-(btue tn 2-» ye£tqw.tn 1) So we can apply the principle of ModusTollens to (3') and (4') and conclude (5') ~ned tn 2 That is, (5) Ititt not the cate that the ted manbteto tn box 2 But this conclusion will be a lot less acceptable than the premises (3) and (4) might have seemed.2) Is ModusTollens playing up here, or should (3) or (4) be rejected after all? Anywhohave been confused by the above will feel obliged to choose sides. Somemaychoose to stay with their initial intuitions about (3) and (4), regarding the example as evidence that ModusTollens sometimes fails. But what kind of evidence is this? Whyshould intuitions be treated with this kind of respect, especially where others do not share them? Choosing instead to do something about (3) and (4), and thus save the principle of ModusTollens, would seem a lot safer: all3) existing theories of conditionals will support this. Even so, one would not have an easy time working things out. For although everyone is agreed that something must be done, there is no consensus to be found in the literature as to precisely what it should be. Sometheories will advise you to reject (3), other ones to reject (4). Often, however, the response is more sophisticated, amounting to a denial that we are dealing with a proper instantiation of ModusTollens here.
Recommended publications
  • Paradoxes Situations That Seems to Defy Intuition
    Paradoxes Situations that seems to defy intuition PDF generated using the open source mwlib toolkit. See http://code.pediapress.com/ for more information. PDF generated at: Tue, 08 Jul 2014 07:26:17 UTC Contents Articles Introduction 1 Paradox 1 List of paradoxes 4 Paradoxical laughter 16 Decision theory 17 Abilene paradox 17 Chainstore paradox 19 Exchange paradox 22 Kavka's toxin puzzle 34 Necktie paradox 36 Economy 38 Allais paradox 38 Arrow's impossibility theorem 41 Bertrand paradox 52 Demographic-economic paradox 53 Dollar auction 56 Downs–Thomson paradox 57 Easterlin paradox 58 Ellsberg paradox 59 Green paradox 62 Icarus paradox 65 Jevons paradox 65 Leontief paradox 70 Lucas paradox 71 Metzler paradox 72 Paradox of thrift 73 Paradox of value 77 Productivity paradox 80 St. Petersburg paradox 85 Logic 92 All horses are the same color 92 Barbershop paradox 93 Carroll's paradox 96 Crocodile Dilemma 97 Drinker paradox 98 Infinite regress 101 Lottery paradox 102 Paradoxes of material implication 104 Raven paradox 107 Unexpected hanging paradox 119 What the Tortoise Said to Achilles 123 Mathematics 127 Accuracy paradox 127 Apportionment paradox 129 Banach–Tarski paradox 131 Berkson's paradox 139 Bertrand's box paradox 141 Bertrand paradox 146 Birthday problem 149 Borel–Kolmogorov paradox 163 Boy or Girl paradox 166 Burali-Forti paradox 172 Cantor's paradox 173 Coastline paradox 174 Cramer's paradox 178 Elevator paradox 179 False positive paradox 181 Gabriel's Horn 184 Galileo's paradox 187 Gambler's fallacy 188 Gödel's incompleteness theorems
    [Show full text]
  • List of Paradoxes 1 List of Paradoxes
    List of paradoxes 1 List of paradoxes This is a list of paradoxes, grouped thematically. The grouping is approximate: Paradoxes may fit into more than one category. Because of varying definitions of the term paradox, some of the following are not considered to be paradoxes by everyone. This list collects only those instances that have been termed paradox by at least one source and which have their own article. Although considered paradoxes, some of these are based on fallacious reasoning, or incomplete/faulty analysis. Logic • Barbershop paradox: The supposition that if one of two simultaneous assumptions leads to a contradiction, the other assumption is also disproved leads to paradoxical consequences. • What the Tortoise Said to Achilles "Whatever Logic is good enough to tell me is worth writing down...," also known as Carroll's paradox, not to be confused with the physical paradox of the same name. • Crocodile Dilemma: If a crocodile steals a child and promises its return if the father can correctly guess what the crocodile will do, how should the crocodile respond in the case that the father guesses that the child will not be returned? • Catch-22 (logic): In need of something which can only be had by not being in need of it. • Drinker paradox: In any pub there is a customer such that, if he or she drinks, everybody in the pub drinks. • Paradox of entailment: Inconsistent premises always make an argument valid. • Horse paradox: All horses are the same color. • Lottery paradox: There is one winning ticket in a large lottery. It is reasonable to believe of a particular lottery ticket that it is not the winning ticket, since the probability that it is the winner is so very small, but it is not reasonable to believe that no lottery ticket will win.
    [Show full text]
  • Pavel Florensky's Theory of Religious Antinomies
    Log. Univers. 13 (2019), 515–540 c 2019 The Author(s) 1661-8297/19/040515-26, published online November 13, 2019 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-019-00234-0 Logica Universalis Pavel Florensky’s Theory of Religious Antinomies PawelRojek Abstract. Pavel Florensky (1882–1937), a Russian theologian, philoso- pher, and mathematician, argued that the religious discourse is essentially contradictory and put forward the idea of the logical theory of antino- mies. Recently his views raised interesting discussions among logicians who consider him a forerunner of many non-classical logics. In this pa- per I discuss four interpretations of Florensky’s views: paraconsistent, L-contradictory, non-monotonic and rhetorical. In conclusion I argue for the integral interpretation which unites these four approaches. Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 03A05; Secondary 03B65, 03B42, 03B53. Keywords. Florensky, Logic of religion, Antinomy, Contradiction, Para- consistency, L-inconsistency, Non-monotonic logic, Rhetoric. 1. Introduction Pavel Florensky (1882–1937) was the first man who attempted to combine Or- thodox theology with modern logic.1 In 1914 he published the famous book The Pillar and the Ground of Truth [18], in which he aimed to express the truth of Orthodoxy by various means of his contemporary culture, including 1 This paper is an extended version of my chapter [37]; I give more comprehensive discussion of Florensky’s logic in my forthcoming book [39]. The first draft of this paper was presented at The Second World Congress on Logic and Religion, Warsaw, June 19, 2017. I am grateful to participants of the Congress for the helpful discussion, and to Viacheslav Moiseev, Teresa Obolevitch, Igor’ Priadko, Tat’iana Rezvykh, Christoph Schneider and two anonymous reviewers for their comments.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic Informed by Justin Bledin a Dissertation Submitted in Partial
    Logic Informed By Justin Bledin A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Logic and the Methodology of Science in the Graduate Division of the University of California, Berkeley Committee in charge: Professor John MacFarlane, Chair Professor Niko Kolodny Professor Seth Yalcin Professor Paolo Mancosu Professor Hans Sluga Fall 2013 Abstract Logic Informed by Justin Bledin Doctor of Philosophy in Logic and the Methodology of Science University of California, Berkeley Professor John MacFarlane, Chair I develop an informational conception of logic as a science fundamentally concerned not with truth but with information. Facts about logical validity, on this conception, tell us about the structure of the bodies of information that we generate, encounter, absorb, and exchange as we interact with one another and learn about our world. I also investigate the normative role of logic in our epistemic practices. In particular, I argue against the widespread idea that there are rational requirements to have logically coherent beliefs that are not merely epiphenomenal on evidential norms. 1 Contents 1 Introduction: Rival Conceptions of Logic 1 2 The Truth Preservation View of Logic 6 3 Against Truth Preservation 13 3.1 |=T r Versus Good Argument . 13 3.2 Sophisticated Truth Preservation . 15 3.3 Truth Preservation Versus Good Argument . 19 3.3.1 Trouble With Descriptivism . 20 3.3.2 Expressivism . 22 3.3.3 Modality With Content . 25 4 The Informational View of Logic 29 4.1 Responses . 29 4.2 A Better Option . 32 5 Modus Ponens Defended 35 5.1 Kolodny and MacFarlane .
    [Show full text]
  • On Conditionals
    Smith ScholarWorks Philosophy: Faculty Publications Philosophy 6-3-2018 On Conditionals Theresa Helke Smith College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.smith.edu/phi_facpubs Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Helke, Theresa, "On Conditionals" (2018). Philosophy: Faculty Publications, Smith College, Northampton, MA. https://scholarworks.smith.edu/phi_facpubs/32 This Dissertation has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy: Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Smith ScholarWorks. For more information, please contact [email protected] ON CONDITIONALS THERESA SOPHIE CAROLINE HELKE (BA(Hons), Smith College) A THESIS SUBMITTED FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF SINGAPORE & YALE-NUS COLLEGE 2018 Supervisors: Associate Professor Ben Blumson, Main Supervisor Assistant Professor Malcolm Keating, Co-Supervisor, Yale-NUS College Examiners: Assistant Professor Robert Beddor Assistant Professor Michael Erlewine Emeritus Professor Frank Jackson, Australian National University DECLARATION I hereby declare that this thesis is my original work and it has been written by me in its entirety. I have duly acknowledged all the sources of information which have been used in the thesis. This thesis has also not been submitted for any degree in any university previously. __________________________________________ Theresa Sophie Caroline Helke 3 June 2018 ii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I’d like to thank - supervisors Ben Blumson at the National
    [Show full text]
  • NANASHARA FAGUNDES BEHLE Paradoxos
    1 NANASHARA FAGUNDES BEHLE Paradoxos: inferências semânticas e implicaturas pragmáticas Dissertação apresentada como requisito para a obtenção do grau de Mestre pelo programa de Pós-Graduação da Faculdade de Letras da Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio Grande do Sul. Orientador: Profª. Drª. Ana Maria Tramunt Ibaños Porto Alegre 2014 2 3 Dedico esta dissertação a todos que acreditam em mim e com paciência me ajudam a continuar. 4 AGRADECIMENTOS À CAPES pela bolsa concedida, sem ela esses dois anos de estudo não seriam possíveis. À minha orientadora, Profª. Drª. Ana Maria Tramunt Ibaños, por todo apoio, paciência, dedicação e, principalmente, inspiração, não só neste trabalho, mas em toda minha jornada acadêmica até aqui. Aos meus pais, avós, tios, irmã e cunhado pelo amor e carinho, particularmente nos momentos difíceis que passei em 2013, tornando possível, inclusive, a finalização deste trabalho. À professora Beatriz Viégas-Faria pela revisão atenta do trabalho e também pelas traduções das notas de rodapé. Aos meus professores na FALE, tanto na graduação quanto no mestrado, que tanto me ensinam e me inspiram. Principalmente para o Profº. Drº. Jorge Campos da Costa pelas reflexões e ensinamentos propiciados em suas aulas. Aos funcionários da FALE, principalmente a secretária Tatiana Carré, pela ajuda sempre rápida e eficiente. Aos meus amigos que, em todos esses meses, me ouviram resmungar e me incentivaram (seja com palavras de apoio, leituras e dicas) a sempre continuar. Ariane Clos, Camila Souza, Cristina Gross, Felipe Prolo, Gláucia Peripolli, João Borges, Juliana Hagen, Mariana Pires, Mônica Monawar, Si Lang, Stéphane Dias, Sun Yuqi, Tammi Schalm e outros: obrigada pelo carinho, compreensão e, principalmente, pela paciência! 5 RESUMO Este trabalho tem por objetivo investigar como podem ser trabalhados os paradoxos lógicos em uma interface lógico-linguística.
    [Show full text]
  • Barbershop Paradox and Connexive Implication
    RUCH FILOZOFICZNY LXXV 2019 2 Jacek Malinowski Polish Academy of Sciences, Warsaw, Poland ORCID: 0000-0001-8620-5004 e-mail: [email protected] Barbershop Paradox and Connexive Implication DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.12775/RF.2019.023 Barbershop paradox. In A logical paradox Lewis Carroll1 presented a par- adox concerning properties of conditionals. It is based on a story which could be summarized as follows: Allen, Brown and Carr run a barber- shop. Somebody must be in to take care of the customers. Moreover, Allen and Brown are always together. Carrol formulated the issue in the following two hypotheticals: First. If Carr is out, it follows that if Allen is out Brown must be in. Second. Allen always takes Brown with him. Then Lewis Carrol writes: “If Carr is out, these two Hypotheticals are true together. And we know that they cannot be true together. Which is absurd. Therefore Carr cannot be out. There’s a nice Reductio ad Ab- surdum for you!”. This way we proved in a logical way that Carr must be always in. It is obviously paradoxical because one can easily see that Allen and Brown might be in and then Carr might be out. So, if Allen and Brown are in and Carr is out then both hypotheticals are true. Let us take a closer look at this. Let propositions A, B, C denote re- spectively ‘Allen is out’, ‘Brown is out’, ‘Car is out’. This way Carrol’s hypotheticals take the form: (1) C → (A → B); (2) A → B. ∼ 1 Lewis Carroll, “A logical paradox”, Mind 3, no.
    [Show full text]
  • Wat De Schildpad Zei Tegen Achilles: Lewis Carrolls Gevolgtrekkingsparadox
    Wat de schildpad zei tegen Achilles: Lewis Carrolls gevolgtrekkingsparadox. Bas Savenije [email protected] Gepubliceerd in Phlizz, Online Magazine van het Lewis Carroll Genootschap, december 2020 (https://lewiscarrollgenootschap.nl/phlizz) Inleiding Dit is het zesde artikel in een reeks over de logica van Lewis Carroll1. Na de eerste twee inleidende artikelen, beschreven de derde en de vierde een tweetal methoden die Carroll had ontwikkeld om de conclusies van syllogismen en sorites te bepalen; beide methoden zijn onderdeel van zijn symbolische logica en hebben een sterk visueel karakter. Het onderwerp van het vijfde en zesde artikel is een tweetal paradoxen2 die Carroll in respectievelijk 1894 en 1895 publiceerde in het tijdschrift Mind: - A Logical Paradox (1894), - What the Tortoise Said to Achilles (1895). Velen beschouwen deze paradoxen als Carrolls meest waardevolle bijdragen aan de logica en ze zijn veelvuldig besproken en bediscussieerd door logici en filosofen. Carroll gebruikte zijn pseudoniem bij deze publicaties en vanwege hun stijl zijn ze ook als literair werk te zien. Maar beide waren wel degelijk bedoeld als een serieuze bijdrage aan de logica. Het thema van de paradoxen betreft hypotheticals, hypothetische of voorwaardelijke uitspraken in de vorm ‘als …. dan ….’. Uit zijn dagboekaantekening wordt duidelijk dat Carroll in de jaren ’90 werkte aan een theorie over voorwaardelijke uitspraken, die vermoedelijk bedoeld was voor een van de latere, niet door hem voltooide delen van Symbolic Logic. In zijn teruggevonden manuscripten is daar echter niets van aangetroffen. Mijn vorige artikel ging over A Logical Paradox, beter bekend als de Barbershop Paradox. Het onderwerp van dit artikel is wat wel Carrolls Paradox of Inference (‘gevolgtrekkingsparadox’) wordt genoemd3.
    [Show full text]
  • Pavel Florensky's Theory of Religious Antinomies
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Jagiellonian Univeristy Repository Log. Univers. 13 (2019), 515–540 c 2019 The Author(s) 1661-8297/19/040515-26, published online November 13, 2019 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11787-019-00234-0 Logica Universalis Pavel Florensky’s Theory of Religious Antinomies PawelRojek Abstract. Pavel Florensky (1882–1937), a Russian theologian, philoso- pher, and mathematician, argued that the religious discourse is essentially contradictory and put forward the idea of the logical theory of antino- mies. Recently his views raised interesting discussions among logicians who consider him a forerunner of many non-classical logics. In this pa- per I discuss four interpretations of Florensky’s views: paraconsistent, L-contradictory, non-monotonic and rhetorical. In conclusion I argue for the integral interpretation which unites these four approaches. Mathematics Subject Classification. Primary 03A05; Secondary 03B65, 03B42, 03B53. Keywords. Florensky, Logic of religion, Antinomy, Contradiction, Para- consistency, L-inconsistency, Non-monotonic logic, Rhetoric. 1. Introduction Pavel Florensky (1882–1937) was the first man who attempted to combine Or- thodox theology with modern logic.1 In 1914 he published the famous book The Pillar and the Ground of Truth [18], in which he aimed to express the truth of Orthodoxy by various means of his contemporary culture, including 1 This paper is an extended version of my chapter [37]; I give more comprehensive discussion of Florensky’s logic in my forthcoming book [39]. The first draft of this paper was presented at The Second World Congress on Logic and Religion, Warsaw, June 19, 2017.
    [Show full text]
  • De Barbershop Paradox Van Lewis Carroll Bas Savenije [email protected]
    De Barbershop Paradox van Lewis Carroll Bas Savenije [email protected] Gepubliceerd in Phlizz, Online Magazine van het Lewis Carroll Genootschap, september 2020 (https://lewiscarrollgenootschap.nl/phlizz) Inleiding Dit is het vijfde artikel in een reeks over de logica van Lewis Carroll. Na de eerste twee inleidende artikelen, beschreven de derde en de vierde een tweetal methoden die Carroll had ontwikkeld om de conclusies van syllogismen en sorites te bepalen; beide methodes zijn onderdeel van zijn symbolische logica en hebben een sterk visueel karakter1. Het onderwerp van dit en het volgende artikel is een tweetal paradoxen die Carroll in respectievelijk 1894 en 1895 publiceerde in het tijdschrift Mind. Velen beschouwen deze paradoxen als Carrolls meest waardevolle bijdragen aan de logica2. Bertrand Russell noemde de beide paradoxen in een radio-interview in 1942 als illustratie van Carrolls bijzondere kwaliteit als bedenker van puzzels. Hij voegde daar aan toe dat het een hele klus was om er een oplossing voor te vinden en karakteriseerde ze expliciet als het beste werk dat hij had geleverd3. De betreffende artikelen in Mind zijn: - A Logical Paradox (1894), - What the Tortoise Said to Achilles (1895). Carroll leverde zelf geen oplossing bij deze paradoxen. Ze zijn veelvuldig besproken en bediscussieerd door logici en filosofen doch die discussies leverden geen overeenstemming over wat de moraal van het verhaal is. Carroll gebruikte zijn pseudoniem bij beide artikelen en vanwege hun stijl zijn ze ook als literair werk te zien. Wellicht daardoor zijn diverse commentatoren van oordeel dat Carroll er geen bijzondere interpretatie mee voor ogen had en zich zelfs niet volledig bewust was van hun belang.
    [Show full text]
  • Logic A-Z from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia Chapter 1
    Logic A-Z From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Chapter 1 Antepredicament Antepredicaments, in logic, are certain previous matters requisite to a more easy and clear apprehension of the doctrine of predicaments or categories. Such are definitions of common terms, as equivocals, univocals, etc., with divisions of things, their differences, etc. They are thus called because Aristotle treated them before the predicaments, hoping that the thread of discourse might not afterwards be interrupted. 1.1 References • This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain: Chambers, Ephraim, ed. (1728). "*article name needed". Cyclopædia, or an Universal Dictionary of Arts and Sciences (first ed.). James and John Knapton, et al. 2 Chapter 2 Apophasis Not to be confused with Apophysis (disambiguation), Apoptosis, or Apophis (disambiguation). Apophasis is a rhetorical device wherein the speaker or writer brings up a subject by either denying it, or denying that it should be brought up.*[1] Accordingly, it can be seen as a rhetorical relative of irony. Also called paralipsis (παράλειψις) – also spelled paraleipsis or paralepsis –, or occupatio,*[2]*[3]*[4]*[5] and known also as prae- teritio, preterition, antiphrasis (ἀντίφρασις), or parasiopesis (παρασιώπησις), apophasis is usually employed to make a subversive ad hominem attack, which makes it a frequently used tactic in political speeches to make an attack on one's opponent. Using apophasis in this way is often considered to be bad form. The device is typically used to distance
    [Show full text]