Nietzsche's Conceptual Personae of Freedom

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Nietzsche's Conceptual Personae of Freedom Nietzsche’s Conceptual Personae of Freedom Faye Brinsmead A thesis submitted to the School of History and Philosophy at the University of New South Wales in fulfilment of the award of Doctor of Philosophy 2009 Acknowledgements My first thanks must go to my supervisor, Ros Diprose. From the beginning, Ros took my ideas seriously, which I thought I had no right to expect. She encouraged me to think more deeply and rigorously while always stressing the value of my own creativity and ways of expressing myself. As the thesis progressed and developed firmer contours, her engagement with its themes and structure was decisively helpful. I will always remember the neat penciled notes in the margins of the draft chapters I kept on giving her. Ros‘ contributions to my thesis went beyond her supervisory duties when she recommended me for a teaching position which allowed me to escape from an office job and focus more exclusively on my writing. My parents were wonderfully supportive for the duration of a seemingly endless project. I lived under their roof for much of my candidature. My mother, Prue, maintained a lively and detailed interest in where I was up to in my thinking, and my dad, Bernie, offered sound advice at crucial moments, advice based on his own PhD candidature. My sisters Gabrielle and Gina were always ready to listen to brainwaves, theories, and the standard postgraduate tales of woe. I need to thank some very loyal friends without whom the process would have been distinctly dreary. Anita Sekely showed her support and interest in every possible way, from reading draft chapters, listening to conference presentations and offering constant affirmation of the thesis and non-thesis aspects of my life. Dan Webster‘s intellectual curiosity was always stimulating and appreciated. Thanks also to Carl Godfrey and i Annette van Gent. Paula Keating, Sandra Field and Daniel McLoughlin were great mates as well as fellow postgrads. My work supervisors and colleagues were also extremely supportive. Sharon Szeto and Alyson Piper were more understanding and flexible than I could have expected, and many other work colleagues were gratifying interested in what I was doing for the duration of the project. ii Contents Acknowledgements i Table of abbreviations iv Introduction 1 I Nietzsche and the textual politics of conceptual personae 7 II Freedom and will: Nietzsche in conversation with his precursors 32 III The free spirit: Truth, lies, and ‗iridescent uncertainties‘ 88 IV The sovereign individual: Kantian or Nietzschean autonomy? 122 V Zarathustra‘s gift: The freedom of creative willing 168 Conclusion 226 Bibliography 231 iii Table of Abbreviations AOM — Assorted Opinions and Maxims, trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1996. BGE — Beyond Good and Evil, trans. W. Kaufmann, New York, Vintage, 1989. BT — The Birth of Tragedy, trans. S Whiteside, London, Penguin, 1993. D — Daybreak, trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1997. EH — Ecce Homo, trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1992. GM — On the Genealogy of Morals, trans. W. Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale, New York, Vintage, 1989. GS — The Gay Science, trans. J. Nauckhoff, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2001. HAH — Human, All Too Human, trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1996. L — Selected Letters, ed. and trans. by Christopher Middleton, Chicago and London, The University of Chicago Press, 1969. PTG — Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks, trans. Marianne Cowan, Washington DC, Regnery Publishing, 1962. TI — Twilight of the Idols, trans. R.J. Hollingdale, London, Penguin, 1990. UM — Untimely Meditations, trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1997. WP — The Will to Power, trans. W. Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale, New York, Vintage, 1968. WS — Wanderer and his Shadow, trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1996. Z — Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans. G. Parkes, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2005. Note 1: Prefaces will be referred to by the acronyms given above followed by the letter P. For example, the 1886 preface to Human, All too Human will be noted as: HAH P. Note 2: References to Nietzsche‘s works in German are from the Kritische Studienausgabe edited by Giorgio Colli and Mazzino Montinari. Munich: De Gruyter, 1999. iv INTRODUCTION It is the guiding conviction of this thesis that Nietzsche‘s conception of freedom is no less distinctive than are his acknowledged signature concepts such as will to power, nihilism, and genealogy; and that his thought of freedom enters into and illuminates his more celebrated conceptual creations in intriguing ways.1 I explore Nietzschean freedom by deploying Deleuze and Guattari‘s notion of the conceptual persona to identify and closely study three figures which are particularly associated with freedom in Nietzsche‘s writings. These are the free spirit, the sovereign individual, and Zarathustra. I undertake close readings of the texts which feature these figures in order to study the way each persona affords Nietzsche the possibility of problematizing freedom differently.2 Nietzsche‘s conceptual personae of freedom are particularly rewarding objects of study, I argue, because they upset a number of received ideas about the nature of freedom. They 1 I have benefited from a number of insightful journal articles and book chapters on Nietzsche‘s thought of freedom. Aaron Ridley‘s argument that Nietzsche‘s reconstruction of freedom is ‗one aspect of his attempt to understand life after the model of art‘ (Ridley 2007a: 204) has informed my approach. Ridley (2007a) and Robert C Solomon (2002) offer illuminating accounts of the relation between Nietzschean freedom and fate. Michael Lackey‘s identification of the oppositionality of freedom and faith in Nietzsche‘s thought (Lackey 1999), and Herman Siemen‘s investigation of the differences between Nietzschean and liberal conceptions of freedom (Siemens 2007) have also been helpful. Few monographs on Nietzschean freedom have as yet appeared. Of those which are currently available, Müller-Lauter (1999) is, in my view, noteworthy for its thorough treatment of the complex constellation of themes, perspectives and methods with which Nietzschean freedom is enmeshed. Dudley (2002) also offers some interesting insights into Nietzschean freedom by means of the conversation between Hegel and Nietzsche which he stages. However, Dudley‘s unusual strategy of evaluating competing conceptions of freedom by reference to a notion of comprehensiveness detracts from his account. The view that philosophy evolves by way of successive attempts to come up with a more ‗comprehensive‘ conceptualisation of a given phenomenon is debatable. Regarding conceptions of freedom as a series of picnic baskets packed with progressively more items is not likely to generate valuable conclusions about the comparative merits and demerits of different thinkers‘ ideations. My own view of the evolution of conceptions of freedom is indebted to Deleuze and Guattari‘s account of concept formation, outlined in Chapter I. 2 In the case of the free spirit I privilege the 1886 preface to HAH for reasons given at the outset of Chapter III. 1 represent a rejection of philosophy‘s longstanding habit of viewing freedom as universal and a priori. In ethics, for example, free will is generally viewed as something which all of us have or none of us has. Those thinkers who hold that we do have free will generally believe that it is a basic human endowment, possessed, under ideal conditions, equally by all. One person‘s freedom is no different from another‘s. While, for ethical thinkers from Plato to Kant, freedom is presupposed, postulated at the outset as a fundamental pre- requisite for moral agency, for Nietzsche, freedom must be striven for.3 Rather than a given, then, freedom for Nietzsche becomes a goal. Where the Platonic moral agent aspires to be just, the Aristotelean to be virtuous and the Kantian to do her duty, the exceptional Nietzschean individual strives to be free. As this reference to exceptionality suggests, for Nietzsche even the ability to set one‘s sights on freedom is the preserve of the few. Although Nietzschean freedom is a goal, the process of becoming-free never ends in a terminus: ‗progress‘ towards freedom always discloses further and higher states for which one must strive. Nor is it a predictably linear process. Rather, like all ‗events in the organic world‘, it is a ‗subduing, a becoming master‘ (GM II 12) involving both self- overcoming and resistance. This gives the process of becoming free a veering, zigzagging trajectory rather than the linear path of a ‗progressus‘ (ibid.), and a heterogeneous character which encompasses ‗more or less mutually independent processes of subduing, plus the resistances they encounter, the attempts at transformation for the purpose of defense and reaction, and the results of successful counteractions‘ (ibid.). The textual 3 In the case of Kant, my claim concerns his notion of transcendental freedom rather than his conception of autonomy. Kantian autonomy does resemble Nietzschean freedom in being something which must be striven for. 2 personae associated with freedom embody this processual conception of freedom. The free spirit and Zarathustra trace out a swerving trajectory towards greater freedom, while the sovereign individual is a late stage in a long process of more or less independent impositions of mastery and the resistances these provoke. These multiple personae of freedom also communicate the view that different human types embody freedom differently, and, further, that some types are not capable or worthy of striving for it at all. The figure of the free spirit is counterpoised against the figure of the bound spirit, representative of the unthinking acceptance of consensual evaluations. The sovereign individual, characterized by its masterly practice of promising, is contrasted with weaker types incapable of keeping their word. And Zarathustra‘s emancipatory exhortations fall on many deaf ears. Each persona could be regarded as a perspectival experiment in thinking freedom.
Recommended publications
  • Pride and Sexual Friendship: the Battle of the Sexes in Nietzsche's Post-Democratic World
    PRIDE AND SEXUAL FRIENDSHIP: THE BATTLE OF THE SEXES IN NIETZSCHE’S POST-DEMOCRATIC WORLD Lisa Fleck Uhlir Yancy, B.A., M.A. Dissertation Prepared for the Degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF NORTH TEXAS August 2008 APPROVED: Steven Forde, Major Professor Ken Godwin, Committee Member Richard Ruderman, Committee Member Milan Reban, Committee Member James Meernik, Chair of the Department of Political Science Sandra L. Terrell, Dean of the Robert B. Toulouse School of Graduate Studies Yancy, Lisa Fleck Uhlir, Pride and sexual friendship: The battle of the sexes in Nietzsche’s post-democratic world. Doctor of Philosophy (Political Science), August 2008, 191 pp., bibliography of 227 titles. This dissertation addresses an ignored [partly for its controversial nature] aspect of Nietzschean philosophy: that of the role of modern woman in the creation of a future horizon. Details of the effects of the Enlightenment, Christianity and democracy upon society are discussed, as well as effects on the individual, particularly woman. After this forward look at the changes anticipated by Nietzsche, the traditional roles of woman as the eternal feminine, wife and mother are debated. An argument for the necessity of a continuation of the battle of the sexes, and the struggle among men and women in a context of sexual love and friendship is given. This mutual affirmation must occur through the motivation of pride and not vanity. In conclusion, I argue that one possible avenue for change is a Nietzschean call for a modern revaluation of values by noble woman in conjugation with her warrior scholar to bring about the elevation of mankind.
    [Show full text]
  • WSRC3290 ASCP 2018 Conference Program FA.Indd
    AUSTRALASIAN SOCIETY FOR CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY ANNUAL CONFERENCE 2018 AUSTRALASIAN SOCIETY FOR CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY ANNUAL CONFERENCE 2018 ACKNOWLEDGMENT OF COUNTRY THANKS TO Western Sydney University would like to acknowledge the ≥ Professor Peter Hutchings, Dean of the School of Humanities Burramattagal people of the Darug tribe, who are the traditional and Communication Arts custodians of the land on which Western Sydney University at Jacinta Sassine and the student volunteers Parramatta stands. We respectfully acknowledge the Burramattagal ≥ people’s Ancestors and Elders, past and present and acknowledge ≥ Hannah Stark, Timothy Laurie and student volunteers their 60,000 year unceded occupation of these lands. who organized the PG event ≥ Panel organisers: Dr Suzi Adams and Dr Jeremy Smith; Professor WELCOME Thomas M. Besch; Professor Francesco Borghesi; Dr Sean Bowden; Associate Professor Diego Bubbio; Dr Millicent Churcher; Dr Richard The Conference Organising Committee for 2018 extends a warm Colledge; Dr Ingo Farin; Associate Professor Chris Fleming; Dr John welcome to all our international and Australian participants, and all Hadley; Professor Vanessa Lemm; Professor Li Zhi; Associate Professor others associated with the conference. The ASCP conference is this year hosted by Western Sydney University, at our new Parramatta David Macarthur; Associate Professor Sally Macarthur; Dr Jennifer City campus. The event has been planned and developed across Mensch; Professor Nick Mansfield; Dr Talia Morag; Associate Professor this year by members of the Philosophy Research Initiative. Eric S. Nelson; Professor Ping He; Dr Rebecca Hill; Associate Professor Janice Richardson and Dr Jon Rubin; Dr Marilyn Stendera; Dr Omid Tofighian; Professor Miguel Vatter and Dr Nicholas Heron; Dr Allison CONFERENCE ORGANIZING COMMITTEE Weir; Dr Magdalena Zolkos.
    [Show full text]
  • How Ought We Live?
    How Ought We Live? The Ongoing Deconstruction of Our Values Mark Nielsen This thesis is submitted to the School of History and Philosophy at the University of New South Wales in fulfilment of the requirements of the PhD in Philosophy 2010 ii iii Dedication For Theresa and Charlotte. iv Acknowledgements Firstly, I would like to thank my supervisor, Paul Patton, for his generous support in assisting me in the creation of this thesis. I am particularly grateful for his patience and understanding in relation to the research method I have used. I would also like to thank my co-supervisor, Rosalyn Diprose, for her generous support. Finally, I would like to thank my wife, Theresa, for her unwavering support over the years and for reminding me of what is important in life. v Table of Contents Title Page i Thesis/Dissertation Sheet ii Originality Statement, Copyright Statement and Authenticity Statement iii Dedication iv Acknowledgements v Table of Contents vi Introduction: Horizontal Philosophy and the Construction of an Ethical Rhizome 1 Macro-Sociological Plateaus 1. The Salesman as Values Educator: A Lesson From a Primary School Teacher 25 2. Feeling Unhappy and Overweight: Overconsumption and the Escalation of Desire 38 3. The Politics of Greed: Trivial Domestic Democracy 52 Philosophical Plateaus 4. The Democratic Rise of the Problem of ―How Ought We Live?‖ 67 5. Living in the Land of Moriah: The Problem of ―How Ought We Sacrifice?‖ 80 6. Welcome to the Mobile Emergency Room: A Convergence Between Ethics and Triage 101 7. Diagnostic Trans-Evaluation and the Creation of New Priorities 111 8.
    [Show full text]
  • A Phenomenological Grounding of Feminist Ethics1 Citation
    Penultimate version - A Phenomenological Grounding of Feminist Ethics1 Citation: Please cite the Journal version which has the correct pages etc,. Society of the British Journal for Phenomenology (accepted 11th April 2018, in press) A Phenomenological Grounding for Feminist Ethics, DOI: 10.1080/00071773.2018.1487195 https://doi.org/10.1080/00071773.2018.1487195 Anya Daly Irish Research Council Fellow, School of Philosophy, University College Dublin, Ireland; Honorary Fellow, School of Historical and Philosophical Studies, University of Melbourne, Australia. Abstract: The central hypothesis of this paper is that the phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty offers significant philosophical groundwork for an ethics that honours key feminist commitments – embodiment, situatedness, diversity and the intrinsic sociality of subjectivity. Part 1 evaluates feminist criticisms of Merleau-Ponty. Part 2 defends the claim that Merleau-Ponty’s non-dualist ontology underwrites leading approaches in feminist ethics, notably Care Ethics and the Ethics of Vulnerability. Part 3 examines Merleau-Ponty’s analyses of embodied percipience, arguing that these offer a powerful critique of the view from nowhere, a totalizing God’s-eye-view with pretensions to objectivity. By revealing the normative structure of perceptual gestalts in the intersubjective domain, he establishes the view from everywhere. Normativity is no longer deferred to higher authorities such as duty, utility or the valorised virtue, but through the perceptual gestalt it is returned to the perceiving embodied
    [Show full text]
  • Derridean Deconstruction and Feminism
    DERRIDEAN DECONSTRUCTION AND FEMINISM: Exploring Aporias in Feminist Theory and Practice Pam Papadelos Thesis Submitted for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Discipline of Gender, Work and Social Inquiry Adelaide University December 2006 Contents ABSTRACT..............................................................................................................III DECLARATION .....................................................................................................IV ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ......................................................................................V INTRODUCTION ..................................................................................................... 1 THESIS STRUCTURE AND OVERVIEW......................................................................... 5 CHAPTER 1: LAYING THE FOUNDATIONS – FEMINISM AND DECONSTRUCTION ............................................................................................... 8 INTRODUCTION ......................................................................................................... 8 FEMINIST CRITIQUES OF PHILOSOPHY..................................................................... 10 Is Philosophy Inherently Masculine? ................................................................ 11 The Discipline of Philosophy Does Not Acknowledge Feminist Theories......... 13 The Concept of a Feminist Philosopher is Contradictory Given the Basic Premises of Philosophy.....................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Poststructuralism, in a Companion to Philosophy in Australia & New Zealand, Monash University Publishing, Clayton, Vic., Pp.455‐459
    This is the published version: Reynolds, Jack 2010, Poststructuralism, in A companion to philosophy in Australia & New Zealand, Monash University Publishing, Clayton, Vic., pp.455‐459. Available from Deakin Research Online: http://hdl.handle.net/10536/DRO/DU:30061160 Reproduced with the kind permission of the copyright owner. Copyright : 2010, Monash University Publishing A COMPANION TO PHILOSOPHY IN AUSTRALIA & NEW ZEALAND I 455 Poststructuralism Poststructuralism Jack Reynolds While it is difficult to precisely define poststructuralism, we can begin ostensively by noting some of the philosophers who are most consistently and famously associated with the term. This includes Michel Foucault, Gilles Deleuze, Jacques Derrida, and Jean-Franc,:ois Lyotard. As such, poststructuralism refers primarily to those philosophers working in France who contested and problematised the reigning orthodoxy in the humanities and social sciences in the early 1960s, which at that time was structuralism. Before positively considering their work and the way in which their overlapping but not univocal interests came to form what we today refer to as poststructuralism, it is important to consider their immediate predecessor on the French scene, structuralism. Structuralism was both a methodological mode of analysis as well as a more thoroughgoing metaphysical and ontological position, and it was widespread in the 1950s and '60s, whether it be Roland Barthes employing structuralist techniques in literary theory, Claude Levi-Strauss in anthropology, Jacques Lacan in psychoanalysis, or Louis Althusser in relation to Marxism and class analysis. The linguistics of Ferdinand de Saussure was also garnering renewed attention. Structuralism sought to arrive at a stable and secure knowledge of a system or a structure, by charting differences within that structure, and it sought to do so without any references to subjectivity and consciousness.
    [Show full text]
  • Record: 1 HEIDEGGER, JEAN-LUC NANCY, and the QUESTION of DASEIN's EMBODIMENT
    Record: 1 HEIDEGGER, JEAN-LUC NANCY, AND THE QUESTION OF DASEIN'S EMBODIMENT. By: Sorial, Sarah. Philosophy Today, Summer2004, Vol. 48 Issue 2, p216-230, 25p; Abstract Analyzes the criticism made against Martin Heidegger, which maintains that Heidegger is guilty of reproducing the metaphysical subject because of his refusal to address the question of Dasein's embodiment. Role of Jean-Luc Nancy in extrapolating an ethics of embodiment from Heidegger's thinking; Philosophy and the body; Triadic relation between the body, community and meaning.; (AN 14169782) Database: Academic Search Complete Full Text Database: Author: Sorial, Sarah Title: HEIDEGGER, JEAN-LUC NANCY, AND THE QUESTION OF DASEIN'S EMBODIMENT: AN ETHICS OF TOUCH AND SPACING Source: Philos Today; Summer 2004; 48, 2; pg. 216-230 ISSN: 0031-8256 Publisher: DePaul University © 2004 Copyright DePaul University . Provided by ProQuest LLC. All Rights Reserved. How can one get hold of the body? I am already speechless.1 In Being and Time, Heidegger engages in a radical critique of Western metaphysics, and more specifically, of the metaphysical subject in its Cartesian form.2In this "destruction" of the tradition, part of Heidegger's project is to demonstrate that the conception of the subject elaborated by metaphysics not only severs the subject from the world but also constitutes a disavowal of Dasein's relationality and dependence on the other. For Heidegger, Dasein is here [being-there], it is being-in-the-world in terms of fallenness and thrownness; it is characterized by motion and projection, anticipation and ek-staticity; it is ontologically being-with others and endowed with the possibility of care.
    [Show full text]
  • Embodiment Sensuous Promptings of the Body, and to Mould Or Form Material Circumstances Against Their Claim to Be the Source for Action
    In Corporeal Generosity Rosalyn Diprose pursues a novel approach to one of the central topics in contemporary scholarly and practical ethical debates: how to conceive and promote ethical relations responsive to the differences of others. The ghost behind this problem is the Kantian ALISON ROSS conception of ethics. The noumenal, moral capacity of the Kantian subject is, famously, a the ethics of formal idea of reason. Through it the subject houses a double potential: to act against the embodiment sensuous promptings of the body, and to mould or form material circumstances against their claim to be the source for action. In Diprose’s ROSALYN DIPROSE book, testing the assumptions of this model of Corporeal Generosity: On Giving with ethics takes her directly to broader social and Nietzsche, Merleau-Ponty, and Levinas political problems. The strength of this work is SUNY Press, Albany, New York, 2002 not, I think, just the philosophically sensitive ISBN 0-79145-322-7 way it considers these problems but its am- RRP US$20.95 (pb) bitious redefinition of works by thinkers, such as Nietzsche, Merleau-Ponty and Levinas, who depart from the tradition that contains ‘ethics’ in a model driven by the need to conquer the body and its affects.1 In resetting contemporary treatments of the theme of ethics in the vocabulary of ‘generos- ity’, Diprose asks us to reconsider this term out- side the anthropological model of gift exchange or the contractual model of property, primarily because she conceives of the ethical force of ‘generosity’ as ‘corporeal’. The notion of ‘cor- poreal generosity’ is present in the three sec- tions of the book as an interrogative model for thinking through the operation of institutional practices (such as the place of the body in the clinical encounter, the assumptions regarding the sexed body that drive legal decisions on ALISON ROSS—THE ETHICS OF EMBODIMENT 223 surrogacy rights and the treatment of indi- that the authority we ‘invest in the law … to genous populations in Australia).
    [Show full text]
  • The Art of Dreaming Flesh Expressing a World
    csr 12.1-03 (32-43) 3/8/06 5:38 PM Page 32 Merleau-Ponty and Petyarre on the art of dreaming Flesh Expressing a World ROSALYN DIPROSE I do not understand painting very well, and especially not Australian Indigenous painting, the dot painting of Western and Central Desert artists such as Kathleen Petyarre.1 This is not to feign naivety. The truth is: I have not had enough practice inhabiting this or any painting. I grew up without art on the wall, among gum trees, red dirt, dying wattle, and ‘two thirds (blue) sky’.2 While this might suggest that I inhabit the same landscape as Petyarre, I also grew up without ‘the Dreaming’, the meaning that this dot painting is said to be about. How and why then can this painting have the impact on me that it does? And, given the history of colonisation in Australia, including the colonisation of Indigenous meanings, what is the politics of the impact of that painting? The difficulty in answering these questions begins with the ontological baggage of western philosophy that comes with the label ‘the Dreaming’. As Howard Morphy points out, ‘the Dreaming’ was coined by anthropologists in the late nineteenth century and, while adopted by Aboriginal groups to refer to their varying ideas about the nature of the world, the term erases the differences between different language groups regarding what they might mean by ‘belonging to dreams’.3 Beyond that kind of colonisation, the term entrenches a peculiarly western model of representation and of ‘belonging’ (that is, of the relation between self, world and meaning).
    [Show full text]
  • Ann V. Murphy
    Ann V. Murphy Fordham University Department of Philosophy Office: 718-817-3321 441 East Fordham Road Fax: 718-817-3300 Bronx, New York 10458 [email protected] APPOINTMENTS • 2012-present. Associate Professor of Philosophy (with tenure). Fordham University • 2006- Present. Assistant Professor of Philosophy. Fordham University. • 2003-2006. New South Global Postdoctoral Fellow. School of Philosophy. University of New South Wales. Sydney, Australia. • 2002-2003. Visiting Assistant Professor. Mount Holyoke College. South Hadley, MA. EDUCATION • Ph.D. Philosophy. University of Memphis. Memphis, TN. 2002. • B.A. Philosophy. Grinnell College. Grinnell, IA. 1996. AREAS OF RESEARCH Areas of Specialization: Feminist Theory, 20th Century Continental Philosophy, Social and Political Philosophy (especially philosophies of violence and non-violence) Areas of Competence: Phenomenology, Ethics, Philosophy of Race PUBLICATIONS Book Violence and the Philosophical Imaginary. SUNY Series in Gender Theory. (2012) Journal Articles & Book Chapters 1. “Corporeal Vulnerability and the New Humanism” in Hypatia: A Journal of Feminist Philosophy. Special Issue on the Ethics of Embodiment. Eds. Debra Bergoffen and Gail Weiss. Volume 26, No.3. 2011. 2. “’Violence is Not an Evil:’ Ambiguity and Violence in Simone de Beauvoir’s Early Philosophical Writings” in philoSOPHIA: a journal of continental feminism. Volume 1, no.1. 2010. 3. “’All Things Considered:’ Sensibility and Ethics in the Later Merleau-Ponty and Derrida” in Continental Philosophy Review. Volume 42. No. 4. 2010. 4. “The Remainder: Between Symbolic and Material Violence” in Philosophy and the Return of Violence: Studies from this Widening Gyre. Eds. Christopher Yates and Nathan Eckstrand. Continuum Press. 2011. 5. “Ambiguity and Precarious Life: Tracing Beauvoir’s Legacy in the Work of Judith Butler” in Simone de Beauvoir Engages The Philosophers: Essays on Beauvoir's Dialogue with Western Thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Introduction RECONSIDERING THE PHENOMENOLOGY OF SOCIAL ENCOUNTERS Luna Dolezal and Danielle Petherbridge The essays collected inBody/Self/Other: The Phenomenology of Social Encounters examine the lived experience of our relations with others as well as the complexity of embodied interaction and forms of sociality. Deploying phe- nomenology along with a variety of other philosophical approaches, including critical theory, social philosophy, feminist theory, and post-structuralism, the contributions in this book describe and critically interrogate existential, material, and normative features of self-other relations in a range of contexts with contemporary significance. The book questions, for example, what it is to perceive or be perceived in terms of race, gender, sexuality, animal- ity, criminality, or medicalized forms of subjectivity. If these are habitual patterns or attitudes built up in everyday experience within our lifeworlds, how do we transform, or even rupture, these perceptions and experiences? Moreover, if we, as social beings, are constituted through intersubjective relations, what are the costs of the absence of this relationality in conditions of isolation or imprisonment, or, why might such relations manifest fear and anxiety in public space or in old age? Moreover, what is the nature of our intercorporeality and what ethical obligations, if any, does the fact of our embodied relationality imply for us? Following the work of philosophers such as Edmund Husserl, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and Jean-Paul Sartre, phenomenology has articulated various aspects of self-other relations making salient the intercorporeal and consti- tutive nature of our encounters with others. This book significantly extends 1 © 2017 State University of New York Press, Albany 2 DOLEZAL AND PETHERBRIDGE these phenomenological insights and takes the notion of the “phenomenol- ogy of social encounters” in its broadest sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Authenticite, Ambiguity and Freedom : Recuperating the Philosophy Of
    AUTHENTICITE, AMBIGUITY AND FREEDOM: RECUPERATING THE PHILOSOPHY OF SIMONE DE BEAUVOIR FOR A CONTEMPORARY ETHICS OF AMBIGUITY TESSA SAUNDERS 2009 PHD Authenticite, Ambiguity and Freedom: Recuperating the Philosophy of Simone de Beauvoir for a Contemporary Ethics of Ambiguity Tessa Michelle Saunders Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Tasmania April 2009 STATEMENT OF ORIGINALITY I certify that this thesis contains no material which has been accepted for a degree or diploma by the University or any other institution, except by way of background information and duly acknowledged in the thesis, and to the best of the candidate's knowledge and belief no material previously published or written by another person except where due acknowledgement is made in the text of the thesis, nor does the thesis contain any material that infringes copyright. Tessa Saunders STATEMENT OF AUTHORITY FOR ACCESS TO COPYING This Thesis may be made available for loan and limited copying in accordance with the Copyright Act 1968. Tessa Saunders For Tom and James ABSTRACT Authenticiti, Ambiguity and Freedom: Recuperating the Philosophy of Simone de Beauvoir for a Contemporary Ethics of Ambiguity The existentialism of Jean-Paul Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir has been criticised for being a "rniserablism"; for throwing us into an absurd universe with no meaning; and for giving an account of freedom which concludes that each can do 'as one pleases' without regard for others due to an inherent lack of meaning in the world. It has been argued that, due to its insistence on an irreducible, 'radical' freedom, it is not possible to develop an ethics based on existentialism and, therefore, that it is of little use in providing any grounds for an ethics today.
    [Show full text]