Experimental Method and the Spiritualist Soul: the Case of Victor Cousin

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Experimental Method and the Spiritualist Soul: the Case of Victor Cousin Experimental Method and the Spiritualist Soul: The Case of Victor Cousin Delphine Antoine-Mahut ENS de Lyon, IHRIM, CNRS UMR 5317, LABEX “COMOD” Spiritualism designates a philosophy that lays claim to the separation of mind and body and the ontological and epistemological primacy of the former. In France, it is associated with the names of Victor Cousin and René Descartes, or more precisely with what Cousin made of Descartes as the founding father of a brittle rational psychology, closed off from the positive sciences, and as a critic in respect to the empiricist legacy of the idéologues. Moreover, by con- sidering merely the end result, severed from its polemical genesis, we are pre- vented from understanding how the category of experience constituted a crucial question for spiritualism itself. Through returning to the origin of these dis- cussions in the 1826 preface to Cousin’s Fragments philosophiques, this essay pursues a threefold path: to show (1) that the public birth of Cousinian spiritualism coincides with the affirmation of applying the experimental method, issuing from Bacon, to the study of facts of consciousness; (2) that Cousin’s later evolution follows a process of radicalization—that is, in this context, of ontologization and of reduction; and (3) that by recovering this genesis, we can distinguish many forms of spiritualisms committed to the ex- perimental method, both in alliance with the early Cousin and against the later Cousin. In this way, we can rediscover the interwoven philosophical links, lost in the process of institutionalization, between metaphysical demands and empiricist concerns, or between “French” philosophy and the legacy of Condillac. This contribution was translated by Daniel Whistler. I am also grateful to him for his re- marks on a first draft. Finally, I want to thank Giuseppe Bianco, Vincent Guillin, Gary Hatfield, Silvia Manzo and Samuel Lézé for their very helpful suggestions. Perspectives on Science 2019, vol. 27, no. 5 © 2019 by The Massachusetts Institute of Technology https://doi.org/10.1162/posc_a_00321 680 Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc_a_00321 by guest on 25 September 2021 Perspectives on Science 681 1. Introduction with a little bit of attention, will and practice, one will succeed in internal observation as in external observation. Though it is indeed more difficult than physics, by its nature psychology is in the end, like [physics], a science of observation, and thus it has the same right to the rank and title of genuine science. (Cousin [1828] 1861, Fourth Lecture, p. 82) Analyses of Victor Cousin’s(1792–1867) political ascension during the close of the 1830s in France are generally accompanied by an affirmation of his philosophical failure. When the latter is analysed, it is attributed to his instrumentalisation of the history of philosophy in the name of impos- ing a liberal, even reactionary ideology, and thus to the absence of any phi- losophy proper. Yet, the birth of Cousinian eclecticism coincides with a very clear philosophical demand: to surpass the sensualism of his predeces- sors out of the very principles of sensualism—that is, by acquiring for the new psychology the rights to an experimental method that had until then been reserved for the study of the natural sciences alone. In the central text, the 1826 preface to Fragments philosophiques, this demand is expressed in two ways. On the one hand, Cousin adopts the framework of the philos- ophy of experience such as it had been theorised by Bacon for the natural sciences and bequeathed to the idéologues via Locke and Condillac. On the other hand, he expands it, via a reference to Descartes, into a distinct do- main of facts capable of being illuminated by a genuinely experimental method—that is, into facts of consciousness (sensible facts, but also rational and volitional ones). In later versions of the same text, however, Cousin’s evolution has come to be identified as a movement of either purification or falsification. By describing it here as a hierarchization, I will show how Cousin progressively rationalizes and ontologizes the psychology that he pre- sented in 1826 as experimental. Such an interpretation opens the way to a philosophical understanding of Cousin’s philosophical failure in terms of a loss of the very essence of the French spiritualist project that links Maine de Biran to Bergson: the patient reform of empiricism that integrates its gains so as to ground a new science of man. Up until now, a threefold perspective on the variant of French spiritu- alism institutionally represented by Cousin has impeded any conception of the possibility of an authentic dialogue between it and the experimental sciences, notably psychology,1 for the purposes of grounding a new science of man. 1. In this way, a blockage has prevented the contribution of this spiritualism to the advent of modern anthropology from being seen. Consider Janicaud 1969, pp. 2, 4; Gusdorf 1974, Part V, chap. V, pp. 425–36. Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc_a_00321 by guest on 25 September 2021 682 Experimental Method and the Spiritualist Soul 1/ In order to reveal the nexus connecting Cousinian politics and phi- losophy in terms of the “occultation,”“instrumentalization,” or even “falsification”2 of all forms of intellectual alterity in his work, some readings—often very powerful ones—have established an impenetrable boundary between Cousin’s rational spiritualism and the work of the medical physiologists. Because he identified the science of man with psychology and excluded physiology from his philosophical project, Cousin and, through him, French spiri- tualism became extremely distanced from the methods and conclu- sions of physiology.3 2/ The recurrence—found in studies on Cousin and his “regiment”4— of this never-ending struggle between Gods and Giants has thus obscured the idea that the battlefield, as well as the stakes of the battle, could be shared by the different factions. In this case, it has obscured the idea that, in the quest for this Holy Grail of the science of man, spiritualism, like those that it identifies as sensual- ists, could have desired the same level of scientificity and could have demanded, on its own account and with genuine earnestness, the implementation in physiology of a more rigorous and more fruitful experimental method than physiologists had been able to lay claim to since the Baconian revolution. 3/ The third cause of drawing a strict boundary between Cousin’s psychological method and the physiological method of the doctors of the Paris and Montpellier schools5 is the frequent identification of Cousin with the explicit theses of his later texts, without any consideration for the possibilities opened up by his first courses and publications, which may subsequently have been abandoned or closed off in his later works.6 The absence of a genetic perspec- tive thereby glides over what is, in reality, a series of adjustments and corrections that occurred in a polemical context arising from Cousin’s coronation as the king of French philosophy, like Louis 2. See Bloch 1979 and 1997; Vermeren 1995; Daled 2005; Rey 2012. 3. One must underline that this theoretical choice renders unthinkable the category of spiritualist physiologist, even though this is precisely how those like Jacques Lordat (1773– 1870), principal representative of the Montpellier School and the duo-dynamist thesis, or even those like Claude-François-Hermann Pidoux (1802–1882), who demanded an “organic spiritualism,” defined themselves. 4. Consider Jules Simon (1814–1896), 1886. 5. See Raynaud 1998; Andrault 2013 and 2016. 6. The edition by Sylvain Matton, Renzo Ragghianti, and Patrice Vermeren of the 1820 course happily now fills this lacuna (Matton, Ragghianti and Vermeren 2019). Downloaded from http://www.mitpressjournals.org/doi/pdf/10.1162/posc_a_00321 by guest on 25 September 2021 Perspectives on Science 683 Philippe had been made king of the French7—that is, in a context in which Cousin, above all, sought to retain his crown. The most radical formulations of his maturity and old age are then taken as representatives of his entire project and, in this sense, as a constant of his philosophical failure. In contrast, by focusing on two major texts by Cousin—the 1826 and 1833 prefaces to Fragments philosophiques8 (the latter supplemented by the 1834 preface to Nouvelles considérations sur les rapports du physique et du moral de l’ homme, ouvrage posthume de Maine de Biran),9—I wish to show: 1/ that the theoretical and methodological framework Cousin estab- lishes to ground the new psychology is a framework that he shares with his adversaries. This framework is that of a philosophy of experience; 2/ that Cousin’s evolution pushed him to an extreme rational spiri- tualism that was not necessitated by his first texts. But more than just an aberration that is difficult to reconcile with the more powerful aspirations of his first writings, this evolution takes the form of a hierarchialization resulting from the necessity he felt to specify his eclecticism as a spiritualism distinguished from both empiricism10 and idealism.11 7. “The 1830 revolution that made Louis Philippe king of the French also made Cousin king of the philosophers. But Louis Philippe was only a constitutional king. Cousin was an absolute king” (Jules Simon 1887, p. 123). 8. The announcement for the 1838 edition is devoted to responding to accusations of pantheism and explaining the theoretical proximities and divergences between Cousin and Schelling. On this point, see Daniel Whistler’s contribution to this volume and Whistler, 2020. 9. Cousin, 1834. 10. In reviewing the continuation of the first edition of Joseph-Marie Degérando’s Histoire comparée des systèmes de philosophie, relativement aux principes des connaissances humaines (Paris, Heinrichs, 1804, 4 tomes), Cousin identifies empiricism as an excessive version of the philosophy of experience.
Recommended publications
  • New—England Transcendentalism
    FRENCH PHILOSOPHERS AND NEW—ENGLAND TRAN SCENDENTALISM FRENCH PHILOSOPHERS AND NEW—ENGLAND TRANSCENDENTALISM BY WALTER L. LEIGHTON H A THESIS SUBMITTED FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE DEPARTMENT OF ENGLISH LITERATURE AT THE UNIVERSITY OF VIRGINIA Huihetg’itp of Eirginia CHARLOTTESVILLE, VIRGINIA 1908 To C. W. K. WHO HAS GIVEN ME BOTH THE ENCOURAGEMENT AND OPPOR'I‘UNIT‘I." FOIL THE WRITING OF THIS THESIS . PREFACE HE writings of the Transcendentalists of New England have been from youth of especial interest to me. An investi- gation of the phenomena of New-England Transcendentalism was instigated by a reading of the chapter on 'l‘ranscendentalism in Professor Barrett Wendell’s Literary History of America. The idea of making a specialty of the French influence in its relation to New-England Transcendentalism as a subject for a doctorate thesis was intimated to me by Professor LeB. R. Briggs, Dean of the Harvard University faculty. Thanks for assistance in the course of actually drawing up the dissertation are due— first, to Dr. Albert Lefevre, professor of philosophy at the University of Virginia, for valuable suggestions concerning the definition of Transcendentalism ; next, to Dr. It. H. Wilson and adjunct-professor Dr. E. P. Dargan, of the depart— ment of Romance Languages at the University of Virginia, for kind help in the work of revision and correction, and, finally, to Dr. Charles W. Kent, professor at the head of the department of English at the University of Virginia, for general supervision of - my work on the thesis. In the work of compiling and writing the thesis I have been _ swayed by two motives: first, the purpose to gather by careful research and investigation certain definite facts concerning the French philosophers and the Transcendental movement in New England; and, secondly, the desire to set forth the information amassed in a cursory and readable style.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliothèque De Flers Et À Divers
    BEAUSSANT LEFÈVRE Commissaires-Priseurs Bibliothèque de Flers et à divers Alain NICOLAS Expert PARIS – DROUOT – 13 JUIN 2014 Ci-dessus : Voltaire, n° 203 En couverture : Mucha - Flers, n° 168 BIBLIOTHÈQUE DE FLERS et à divers VENDREDI 13 JUIN 2014 à 14 h Par le ministère de Mes Eric BEAUSSANT et Pierre-Yves LEFÈVRE Commissaires-Priseurs associés Assistés de Michel IMBAULT BEAUSSANT LEFÈVRE Société de ventes volontaires Siren n° 443-080 338 - Agrément n° 2002-108 32, rue Drouot - 75009 PARIS Tél. : 01 47 70 40 00 - Télécopie : 01 47 70 62 40 www.beaussant-lefevre.com E-mail : [email protected] Assistés par Alain NICOLAS Expert près la Cour d’Appel de Paris Assisté de Pierre GHENO Archiviste paléographe Librairie « Les Neuf Muses » 41, Quai des Grands Augustins - 75006 Paris Tél. : 01.43.26.38.71 - Télécopie : 01.43.26.06.11 E-mail : [email protected] PARIS - DROUOT RICHELIEU - SALLE n° 7 9, rue Drouot - 75009 Paris - Tél. : 01.48.00.20.20 - Télécopie : 01.48.00.20.33 EXPOSITIONS – chez l’expert, pour les principales pièces, du 5 au 10 Juin 2014, uniquement sur rendez-vous – à l’Hôtel Drouot le Jeudi 12 Juin de 11 h à 18 h et le Vendredi 13 Juin de 11 h à 12 h Téléphone pendant l’exposition et la vente : 01 48 00 20 07 Ménestrier, n° 229 CONDITIONS DE LA VENTE Les acquéreurs paieront en sus des enchères, les frais et taxes suivants : pour les livres : 20,83 % + TVA (5,5 %) = 21,98 % TTC pour les autres lots : 20,83 % + TVA (20 %) = 25 % TTC La vente est faite expressément au comptant.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cult of Socrates: the Philosopher and His Companions in Satie's Socrate
    Utah State University DigitalCommons@USU Undergraduate Honors Capstone Projects Honors Program Spring 2013 The Cult of Socrates: The Philosopher and His Companions in Satie's Socrate Andrea Decker Moreno Utah State University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.usu.edu/honors Part of the Music Commons Recommended Citation Moreno, Andrea Decker, "The Cult of Socrates: The Philosopher and His Companions in Satie's Socrate" (2013). Undergraduate Honors Capstone Projects. 145. https://digitalcommons.usu.edu/honors/145 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Honors Program at DigitalCommons@USU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Undergraduate Honors Capstone Projects by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@USU. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE CULT OF SOCRATES: THE PHILOSOPHER AND HIS COMPANIONS IN SATIE’S SOCRATE by Andrea Decker Moreno Thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of HONORS IN UNIVERSITY STUDIES WITH DEPARTMENTAL HONORS in Music – Vocal Performance in the Department of Music Approved: Thesis/Project Advisor Departmental Honors Advisor Dr. Cindy Dewey Dr. Nicholas Morrison Director of Honors Program Dr. Nicholas Morrison UTAH STATE UNIVERSITY Logan, UT Spring 2013 The Cult of Socrates: The philosopher and his companions in Satie's Socrate Satie's Socrate is an enigma in the musical world, a piece that defies traditional forms and styles. Satie chose for his subject one of the most revered characters of history, the philosopher Socrates. Instead of evaluating his philosophy and ideas, Satie created a portrait of Socrates from the most intimate moments Socrates spent with his followers in Plato's dialogues.
    [Show full text]
  • APPENDICES It Would Seem That Hume Had Predecessors, Or at The
    APPENDICES 1. THE PRECURSORS OF HUME (p. 58) It would seem that Hume had predecessors, or at the very least precursors, in the Middle Ages, in particular Robert Holkot in the twelfth century, about whom little is actually known (cf. IR 90, 342 [Loewenberg 87, 302]). As for Nicholas de Ultricuria [Nicolas of Autrecourt], who had previously been known only as an atomist and whose name has been suggested by Hastings RASHDALL ('Nicholas de Ultricuria, a Medieval Hume,' Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 7 [1906-1907] 3 ff.), among the texts cited the only thing we see that really applies to this question consists of the following lines from Nicholas's Thesis 15: Quibuscunque acceptis, que possunt esse causa alicujus effectus, nescimus evidenter quod ad positionem eorum sequatur effectus positio ["Whatever conditions we take to be the cause of any effect, we do not evidently know that, those conditions being posited, it follows that the effect must be posited also" (Rashdall 10)], and this passage perhaps does not quite suffice to demonstrate the English author's claim. It is highly significant that both Robert and Nicolas professed atomistic opinions, and it is at least quite probable that, for these two aspects of their doctrines, they were closely linked to the Arab Mutakallimun, whom they probably knew through the resumes and refutations of Jewish thinkers, notably Maimonides, and who, in addition to a radical atomism, maintained the impossibility of any logical connection between cause and effect (see Isaac HUSIK, A History of Mediaeval Jewish Philosophy, New York: Macmillan, 1916, pp. xxi-xxii, xxvii, 249).
    [Show full text]
  • Emerson's Hidden Influence: What Can Spinoza Tell the Boy?
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Honors Theses Department of Philosophy 6-15-2007 Emerson's Hidden Influence: What Can Spinoza Tell the Boy? Adam Adler Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_hontheses Recommended Citation Adler, Adam, "Emerson's Hidden Influence: What Can Spinoza Tell the Boy?." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2007. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_hontheses/2 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. EMERSON’S HIDDEN INFLUENCE: WHAT CAN SPINOZA TELL THE BOY? by ADAM ADLER Under the Direction of Reiner Smolinski and Melissa Merritt ABSTRACT Scholarship on Emerson to date has not considered Spinoza’s influence upon his thought. Indeed, from his lifetime until the twentieth century, Emerson’s friends and disciples engaged in a concerted cover-up because of Spinoza’s hated name. However, Emerson mentioned his respect and admiration of Spinoza in his journals, letters, lectures, and essays, and Emerson’s thought clearly shows an importation of ideas central to Spinoza’s system of metaphysics, ethics, and biblical hermeneutics. In this essay, I undertake a biographical and philosophical study in order to show the extent of Spinoza’s influence on Emerson and
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophical Polemic in Havana Revisited by Vicente Medina
    The Philosophical Polemic in Havana Revisited by Vicente Medina The Philosophical Polemic in Havana Revisited* by Vicente Medina English Abstract The polemic was an important cultural event in 19th-century Cuba. From 1838 to 1840, issues of metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, pedagogy, and the influence of Victor Cousin’s eclecticism were discussed in the island’s leading newspapers. A brief historical account preceding the polemic is offered. I argue that the predominant view of the polemic, which is motivated by a widespread desire for Cuba’s independence from Spain, is misleading in its promotion of an emancipatory myth. Lastly, I argue that José de la Luz y Caballero’s appeal to patriotism during the polemic unwittingly established a dangerous precedent for self-appointed guardians of patriotism to condition public debates. Resumen en español La polémica fue un importante evento cultural durante el siglo diecinueve en Cuba. Entre 1838 a 1840 se debatieron en los principales periódicos de la isla temas en torno a la metafísica, la epistemología, la ética, la pedagogía y la influencia del eclecticismo de Víctor Cousin. Narro brevemente algunos de los hechos históricos que antecedieron esta polémica. Sostengo que es inexacta la interpretación predominante que esta polémica fue motivada por el deseo de independizar a Cuba de España. Tal interpretación promueve un mito de emancipación. Según mi análisis, cuando en su intervención en la polémica José de la Luz y Caballero apela al patriotismo, establece sin saberlo un precedente peligroso que usarán los autodenominados protectores del patriotismo para restringir los debates públicos. Resumo em português A polêmica foi um importante evento cultural durante o século dezenove em Cuba.
    [Show full text]
  • Effects of the Agrégation De Philosophie on Twentieth- Century French Philosophy
    Effects of the Agrégation de Philosophie on Twentieth- Century French Philosophy AL A N D . S C HRI ft much attention has been paid to developments in French philosophy over the past half century, and it has been frequently noted that the recent history of French philosophy differs significantly from its counterparts in England, Germany, and the United States. While many reasons for these differences have been suggested, in what follows I would like to suggest that there is an important and unique French institution—one with no equivalent in the English-speaking or German academic systems—that has had a significant impact on developments in French philosophy throughout the twentieth century. This institution is the Agrégation de Philosophie, and its effects are virtually unknown among philosophers outside France. Even within France—while knowledge of and experience with the agréga- tion is part of the intellectual formation and career of virtually every academic educated in France, including every philosopher teaching in a university and the majority of philosophers teaching the classe de philosophie in French lycées—French philosophers themselves seem relatively unaware and uninterested in the history of the agrégation and the effects that this history has had on philosophical practices in France. What I hope to do in the following pages is explain how the agréga- tion de philosophie works, and suggest that its impact on the education of French philosophy students and the teaching corps in both the university and lycée helps explain a number of developments in French philosophy over the past century. I will also explain why the French philosophical tradition differs from its American counterpart in some very significant ways.
    [Show full text]
  • The Bergsonian Moment: Science and Spirit in France, 1874-1907
    THE BERGSONIAN MOMENT: SCIENCE AND SPIRIT IN FRANCE, 1874-1907 by Larry Sommer McGrath A dissertation submitted to Johns Hopkins University in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Baltimore, Maryland June, 2014 © 2014 Larry Sommer McGrath All Rights Reserved Intended to be blank ii Abstract My dissertation is an intellectual and cultural history of a distinct movement in modern Europe that I call “scientific spiritualism.” I argue that the philosopher Henri Bergson emerged from this movement as its most celebrated spokesman. From the 1874 publication of Émile Boutroux’s The Contingency of the Laws of Nature to Bergson’s 1907 Creative Evolution, a wave of heterodox thinkers, including Maurice Blondel, Alfred Fouillée, Jean-Marie Guyau, Pierre Janet, and Édouard Le Roy, gave shape to scientific spiritualism. These thinkers staged a rapprochement between two disparate formations: on the one hand, the rich heritage of French spiritualism, extending from the sixteenth- and seventeeth-century polymaths Michel de Montaigne and René Descartes to the nineteenth-century philosophes Maine de Biran and Victor Cousin; and on the other hand, transnational developments in the emergent natural and human sciences, especially in the nascent experimental psychology and evolutionary biology. I trace the influx of these developments into Paris, where scientific spiritualists collaboratively rejuvenated the philosophical and religious study of consciousness on the basis of the very sciences that threatened the authority of philosophy and religion. Using original materials gathered in French and Belgian archives, I argue that new reading communities formed around scientific journals, the explosion of research institutes, and the secularization of the French education system, brought about this significant, though heretofore neglected wave of thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Reception in France: Theories of the Categories in Academic
    Kant’s Reception in France: Theories of the Categories in Academic Philosophy, Psychology, and Social Science Warren Schmaus Illinois Institute of Technology Downloaded from http://direct.mit.edu/posc/article-pdf/11/1/3/1789191/106361403322286698.pdf by guest on 30 September 2021 It has been said that Kant’s critical philosophy made it impossible to pursue either the Cartesian rationalist or the Lockean empiricist program of provid- ing a foundation for the sciences (e.g., Guyer 1992). This claim does not hold true for much of nineteenth century French philosophy, especially the eclectic spiritualist tradition that begins with Victor Cousin (1792–1867) and Pierre Maine de Biran (1766–1824) and continues through Paul Janet (1823–99). This tradition assimilated Kant’s transcendental apper- ception of the unity of experience to Descartes’s cogito. They then took this to be the method of a philosophical psychology that reveals the active self as sub- stance or cause and thus provides the epistemological grounding for these cate- gories. However, to dismiss these philosophers as simply confused or mistaken would be to overlook the historical role that their interpretations of Kant played in the subsequent development of philosophy and the social sciences in France. Speciªcally, Émile Durkheim’s (1858–1917) sociological theory of the categories was deeply inºuenced by the eclectic spiritualist tradition and yet at the same time developed in reaction to it, as he thought that its psycho- logical account of the categories failed to bring out their shared or universal character and the extent to which our conceptions of the categories are cultural products.
    [Show full text]
  • The Brain in the Third Republic: Science, Pedagogy, and National Regeneration
    The Brain in the Third Republic: Science, Pedagogy, and National Regeneration Larry S. McGrath Before Parisian crowds overflowed his celebrated lectures at the Collège de France, Henri Bergson came to the provincial town of Clermont-Ferrand in 1883 to teach the philosophy course in a lycée (the French equivalent of high school). Bergson opened the first lesson on psychology, the centerpiece of the course, with a thorough introduction to human neurology, and proceeded to critique the reductionist implications of the nascent science: “If sadness were in the heart, if thought were in the head, it would occupy a place there, which by dissecting one could end up finding on the end of a scalpel…But thought does not reside in the brain.”1 Bergson was no materialist. The lesson reflected his philosophy of the mind’s creative powers advanced in Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience (1889) and Matière et mémoire (1896). But well before he won the Nobel Prize for literature in 1927, Bergson instructed his students using cerebral diagrams replete with anatomical descriptions and physiological localizations of the brain’s functions. The lesson also betrayed an ideological cleavage at the heart of philosophy’s public mission under the Third Republic: Bergson was both an independent thinker indebted to the nation’s rich spiritualist tradition, extending from René Descartes and Michel de Montaigne to Victor Cousin, and a civil servant tasked with inculcating laïque and scientific values in the classroom. Bergson belonged to a generation of lycée philosophy instructors entrusted as the public stewards of still-budding brain research.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Reid's Common-Sense Philosophy in the Development Of
    Thomas Reid’s Common-Sense Philosophy in the Development of Nineteenth-Century French Spiritualism by James Crombie Université Sainte-Anne 1695 Route 1, Pointe-de-l’Église Nova Scotia, Canada james.crombie <at> usainteanne.ca Conference 19th-Century French Philosophy: The 'Spiritualist' Tradition and its Critics, 14-15 September 2017, Manchester Metropolitan University, Manchester, UK This presentation calls attention to the surprising level of influence which the Scottish philosopher Thomas Reid (1710-1796) had on nineteenth-century French philosophy – especially among professional teachers of philosophy in French universities – in particular among those identified as belonging to the so-called ‘spiritualist’ tradition. Some of the political, social, personal – and even philosophical – reasons for this phenomenon will be adumbrated. There were many figures who could be considered to be influential Reidians during the nineteenth-century in France. This presentation will focus on the major players: firstly, Royer-Collard; secondly, Cousin, Damiron and Jouffroy. Some attention will be paid, thirdly, to some of the members of the third generation: Adolphe Garnier, Amédée Jacques, Émile Saisset, Jules Simon, Adolphe Bertereau and Adolphe Franck. Pierre Maine de Biran and Joseph- Marie Degérando (aka de Gérando) are mentioned but not Pierre Prévost who, in Geneva, was publishing on the subject of Reid before he was discovered in Paris by Royer-Collard. Thomas Reid This portrait is reputed to be the only surviving visual likeness of Thomas Reid. It was painted by Sir Henry Raeburn in 1796, upon the urging of James Gregory, on the occasion of a visit by Reid, in the year in which Reid died, at the age of 86.
    [Show full text]
  • Maine De Biran's Leibniz
    This is a repository copy of A Universal and Absolute Spiritualism: Maine de Biran's Leibniz. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/97861/ Version: Accepted Version Book Section: Dunham, J. (2016) A Universal and Absolute Spiritualism: Maine de Biran's Leibniz. In: Meacham, D. and Spadola, J., (eds.) The Relationship between the Physical and the Moral in Man. Bloomsbury . ISBN 9781472579676 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ A Universal and Absolute Spiritualism Maine de Biran’s Leibniz Jeremy Dunham (University of Sheffield) In France during the nineteenth century the production of new editions, interpretations, and expositions of early modern philosophical texts was a flourishing activity. However, it is important to recognise when examining the scholarly works of this period that such interpretation and exposition was almost never produced without an agenda. A favourable interpretation of one of the giants of early modern philosophy that shows them to be the natural ‘father’ of one’s own philosophical perspective could act as a significant legitimation of this view and, consequently, could become a weapon in philosophical combat.
    [Show full text]