Philosophical Perspectives on the Exact Sciences and Their History”

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophical Perspectives on the Exact Sciences and Their History” Master Projects (EPFL) “Philosophical perspectives on the exact sciences and their history” Some remarks on the measurement problem in quantum theory (Davide Romano) 1. An introduction to the quantum formalism In quantum mechanics, a generic physical state of a system is described by a unitary-norm vector � in Hilbert space ℋ. In the Dirac notation, this vector is called “ket” and it is represented by |� . ℋis a complex vector space with a norm given by � ∶= � � . The complex conjugated vector of |� is �| and it is called “bra”. Given the linearity of the Hilbert space, if two different physical states are possible for a quantum system, say |� and |� , then the linear superposition of these two states is another possible physical state for the system: |� =�!|� + �!|� Taken two generic ket, the inner product between them gives a complex number, which is a probability amplitude: � � = �!, with �! ∈ ℂ We can interpret the above expression as the probability amplitude of a physical transition from the state |� to the state |� Given a complete orthonormal basis in Hilbert space (we refer to the vectors of this basis as eigenvectors), we can represent any vector of that space as a generic linear superposition of eigenvectors. In QM, the most complete mathematical representation of the physical state of a system is given by its state-vector, which generally is a linear superposition of eigenstates. An eigenstate is an eigenvector of a hermitian operator (in the quantum formalism, each physical quantity or “observable” is described by a hermitian operator in Hilbert space): |� = ! �!|�! , where {�!} is a complete orthonormal basis of eigenvectors. 1 If we express a state-vector, i.e. |� , in the position basis representation (that is, we choose eigenstates of the position as eigenvector of the basis), we obtain the wave-function of the system: �! � = �! � ; wave function of the system � Mathematically, the wave function is a probability amplitude: its absolute square gives the density of probability about the position of a particle: � � ! ≔ �∗ � � � ; density of probability of the position of a particle. In order to have the probability to find the particle in a certain volume of space, we have to integer the density of probability in such a volume of space: !!!" ! ! � � �� ; probability to find the particle in the region �, � + �� 2. Time evolution and measurement of a system 2.1 Evolution of closed systems (linear evolution) The time evolution of a closed (or isolated) quantum system is given by the Schrödinger equation. The Schrödinger equation for a state-vector is: ! ! ! (1.a) �ℏ |� = + � |� ; � = + � is the Hamiltonian operator. !" !! !! The Schrödinger equation for a wavefunction is: ! !! ! (1.b) �ℏ � �, � = − + � � �, � !" !! !!! The Schrödinger equation is a linear differential equation: if we have two different solution �! and �!, then there is a linear superposition of them that is again a solution of the equation, � = � �! + � �!. This mathematical property is essential in order to hold in time the superposition principle of states that we have introduced before. The time evolution given by the Schrödinger equation is deterministic: given a state-vector (or a wavefunction) at a certain time and the initial conditions for 2 the system, we can predict the dynamical behavior of the quantum system for all times. So, where does the famous quantum probabilities come from? 2.2 The measure of a system (non linear evolution) When we perform a measure on a quantum system, or more generally when a quantum system interacts with a classical measurement apparatus (humans are only a subset of the set of all possible measurement apparata), the state-vector, which is described by a linear superposition of eigenstates, collapses in an istantaneous and random manner into one of its eigenstates (postulate of the collapse). The probability that the state-vector collapses into one definite eigenstate is given by the absolute square of the coefficient related to that eigenstate (Born rule): !"#$%&"!"'( ! ! (2) |� = ! �! |�! |�! ���ℎ � = �! ∶= �! � Now, we are ready to face the measurement problem! 3. The measurement problem Given a generic a quantum system |� = ! �! |�! , |� ∈ ℋ! and a classical apparatus |� ∈ ℋ!, we can describe the global system which is composed by the system and the apparatus through the state-vector |Ψ |Ψ = |� |� , |Ψ ∈ ℋ! ⊗ ℋ! The total state |Ψ is an entangled state between the system and the apparatus. At the initial time t=0, |Ψ is a factorized state, thus we can write |Ψ as a tensor product of two eigenstates which live in two different Hilbert spaces: 3 |Ψ 0 = |� 0 |� 0 = �! |�! 0 |� 0 ! During the time interval in which the experiment is performed, the state-vector of the global system evolves according to the Schrödinger equation. Because of the linearity of the equation, in the final state each eingenstate of the system is entangled with a different macroscopic physical state of the apparatus: !"!!ö!"#$%& !"#$%&'#( |Ψ 0 = ! �! |�! 0 |� 0 |Ψ � = ! �!|�! |�! �! represents different macroscopic physical states of the classical apparatus: for example, a pointer which points to the left or to the right, a display which indicates a number, … These are also called pointer states and they are the analogous for the apparatus of the eigenstates for the system: in other words, they are all the possible physical states in which the apparatus can be after the measure. Do you see the problem? The final state of the global system is not a definite physical state, but it is a linear superposition of different macroscopic states. This is not in agreement with our experience: when we perform a measure on a quantum system, we always end up with a unique definite macroscopic result. This is the core of the measurement problem! 3.1 A pragmatic solution for standard quantum mechanics Solution in Standard QM: when a measure on a quantum system is performed by a classical apparatus, the state-vector of the quantum system collapses in one of its eigenstates (postulate of the collapse) with probability given by the square norm of the coefficient (Born’s rule). If we introduce in the quantum formalism the postulate of the collapse and the Born rule, then the theoretical predictions of the measurement outcomes performed on a quantum system are in perfect agreement with all the experimental results. So, what’s the problem? 4 3.2 Beyond the standard QM: quantum theory without observer For All Practical Purposes, there are no problems at all (and, in fact, for the vast majority of the physicists the measurement problem is not a real problem!) Nevertheless, if we are interested in the conceptual foundations of QM, we have to deal with the following issues: 1) With the introduction of the collapse postulate, QM is divided into two different regimes, which are governed by two different laws: when a quantum system is isolated, it evolves according to the Schrödinger equation, whereas when a system is “measured” or “observed”, then it collapses randomly in one of its eigenstates with probability given by the Born rule. But there is nothinG in the quantum formalism itself that defines what counts as an observer in the theory! If we don’t know what exactly counts as an observer, we don’t know precisely when the postulate of the collapse applies on the quantum systems, and the quantum formalism remains vague and ambiguous. 2) It seems quite strange that, before the observer enters into the picture, the global state does not have a definite result! This could easily lead to some paradox, like SchrödinGer’s cat: before we open the box, the cat is in a macroscopic superposition to be dead and alive at the same time (this paradox strongly lies on the validity of the eigenvalue-eigenstate link. For a critical discussion of such a postulate, see Wallace (2012)) . But this is absurd: a fundamental physical theory should give a precise and definite account of the physical state of the system even before the observer acts upon the system. Can really the cat be in a macroscopic superposition before we open the box? The reality which is described by a fundamental physical theory should be observer-independent. Note: Einstein’s main critique to the Copenhagen interpretation of QM was about the problem of the realism of that theory, not about the probabilistic nature of it (as it commonplace to think). 3) The collapse postulate introduces a distinction between a macroscopic world (measuring devices, observers, …) where the rules of classical mechanics hold (so, no superposition of states) and a microscopic world, which is described by the rules of quantum mechanics (so that superposition of states is permitted…). See, for example, the solution proposed by Griffiths’ textbook on QM for the Schrödinger’s cat paradox: “the essence of a measure is that a 5 macroscopic system has been modified. We have a meaure when a microscopic system (which is described by the laws of quantum mechanics) interacts with a macroscopic system (which is described by the rules of classical mechanics), leaving on the latter a permanent record. The macroscopic system itself is not authorized to be in a linear superposition of distinct states” (Griffiths, Introduction to Quantum Mechanics, section 12.4: Schrödinger’s cat). The distinction between microscopic and macroscopic systems seems to be artificial (ad hoc) and arbitrary (the boundary line between these two levels is not specifyed by the theory itself). Indeed, it is not easy to define precisely when a system, foe example, becomes macroscopic: how many particles we need in order to have a macroscopic system?. Moreover, the fact that a system is macroscopic is not always a guarantee of the classicality of it: we can have macroscopic quantum system (i.e., superconductors), which are macroscopic system that show a quantum behvior. So, “mascroscopicness” seems not to be the only requirement for the origin of the classical regime.
Recommended publications
  • International Centre for Theoretical Physics
    XA<? 6 H 0 <! W IC/95/320 INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR THEORETICAL PHYSICS BOHM'S THEORY VERSUS DYNAMICAL REDUCTION G.C. Ghirardi and INTERNATIONAL ATOMIC ENERGY R. Grassi AGENCY UNITED NATIONS EDUCATIONAL, SCIENTIFIC AND CULTURAL ORGANIZATION MIRAMARE-TRIESTE VQL 'l 7 Ha ° 7 IC/95/320 ABSTRACT International Atomic Energy Agency and United Nations Educational scientific and Cultural Organization made that theories which exhibit parameter , INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR THEORETICAL PHYSICS BOHM'S THEORY VERSUS DYNAMICAL REDUCTION1 1. Introduction. We share today's widespread opinion that Standard Quantum Mechanics (SQM), in spite of its enormous successes, has failed in giving a G.C. Ghirardi satisfactory picture of the world, as we perceive it. The difficulties about International Centre for Theoretical Physics, Trieste, Italy, the conceptual foundations of the theory arising, as is well known, from and the so-called objectification problem, have stimulated various attempts to Department of Theoretical Physics. University di Trieste, Trieste, Italy overcome them. Among these one should mention the search for a and deterministic completion of the theory, the many worlds and many minds intepretations, the so called environment induced superselection rules, the R. Grassi quantum histories approach and the dynamical reduction program. In this Department of Civil Engineering, University of Udine, Udine, Italy. paper we will focus our attention on the only available and precisely formulated examples of a deterministic completion and of a stochastic and nonlinear modification of SQM, i.e., Bohm's theory and the spontaneous reduction models, respectively. It is useful to stress that while the first theory is fully equivalent, from a predictive point of view, to SQM, the second one qualifies itself as a rival of SQM but with empirical divergence so small that it can claim all the same experimental support.
    [Show full text]
  • International Centre for Theoretical Physics
    ... „. •::^i'— IC/94/93 S r- INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR THEORETICAL PHYSICS QUANTUM MECHANICS WITH SPONTANEOUS LOCALIZATION AND EXPERIMENTS F. Benatti INTERNATIONAL ATOMIC ENERGY G.C. Ghirardi AGENCY and R. Grassi UNITED NATIONS EDUCATIONAL, SCIENTIFIC AND CULTURAL ORGANIZATION MIRAMARE-TRIESTE 1 f I \ •» !r 10/94/93 International Atomic Energy Agency and United Nations Educational Scientific and Cultural Organization ABSTRACT INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR THEORETICAL PHYSICS We examine from an experimental point of v'iew the recently proposed models of spontaneous reduction. We compare their implications about decoherence with those of environmental effects. We discuss the treatment, within the considered models, of the so called quantum telegraph phenomenon and we show that, contrary to what has QUANTUM MECHANICS heen recently stated, no problems are met, Finally, we review recent interesting work WITH SPONTANEOUS LOCALIZATION investigating the implications of dynamical reduction for the proton decay. AND EXPERIMENTS ' F. Heiiatti Dip.irtimento di I-'iska Tcwicii, Univorsita di Trieste. Trieste, July, G.C. (ihirardi 1. INTRODUCTION International Centre for Theoretical Physics, Trieste, Italy One of the most intriguing features of Quantum Mechanics (QM) is that it provides and too good a description of microphenomena to be considered a mere recipe to predict Dipartiniento di Fisica Tc-orica, Univorsita di Trieste, Trieste, Italy probabilities of prospective measurement outcomes from given initial conditions and, and yet, as a fundamental theory of reality, it gives rise to serious conceptual problems, among which the impossibility, in its orthodox interpretation, to think of all physical II. CSrasfli observables of the system under consideration as possessing in all instances definite Dipartiinento di Kisira, Universita di Udinc, Udrne, Italy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Minimal Modal Interpretation of Quantum Theory
    The Minimal Modal Interpretation of Quantum Theory Jacob A. Barandes1, ∗ and David Kagan2, y 1Jefferson Physical Laboratory, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138 2Department of Physics, University of Massachusetts Dartmouth, North Dartmouth, MA 02747 (Dated: May 5, 2017) We introduce a realist, unextravagant interpretation of quantum theory that builds on the existing physical structure of the theory and allows experiments to have definite outcomes but leaves the theory's basic dynamical content essentially intact. Much as classical systems have specific states that evolve along definite trajectories through configuration spaces, the traditional formulation of quantum theory permits assuming that closed quantum systems have specific states that evolve unitarily along definite trajectories through Hilbert spaces, and our interpretation extends this intuitive picture of states and Hilbert-space trajectories to the more realistic case of open quantum systems despite the generic development of entanglement. We provide independent justification for the partial-trace operation for density matrices, reformulate wave-function collapse in terms of an underlying interpolating dynamics, derive the Born rule from deeper principles, resolve several open questions regarding ontological stability and dynamics, address a number of familiar no-go theorems, and argue that our interpretation is ultimately compatible with Lorentz invariance. Along the way, we also investigate a number of unexplored features of quantum theory, including an interesting geometrical structure|which we call subsystem space|that we believe merits further study. We conclude with a summary, a list of criteria for future work on quantum foundations, and further research directions. We include an appendix that briefly reviews the traditional Copenhagen interpretation and the measurement problem of quantum theory, as well as the instrumentalist approach and a collection of foundational theorems not otherwise discussed in the main text.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics: a General Purview
    Mississippi State University Scholars Junction Collge of Arts and Sciences Publications and Scholarship College of Arts and Sciences 10-1-2020 Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics: A General Purview Prajwal Mohanmurthy Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsjunction.msstate.edu/cas-publications Recommended Citation Mohanmurthy, Prajwal, "Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics: A General Purview" (2020). Collge of Arts and Sciences Publications and Scholarship. 14. https://scholarsjunction.msstate.edu/cas-publications/14 This Preprint is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Arts and Sciences at Scholars Junction. It has been accepted for inclusion in Collge of Arts and Sciences Publications and Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholars Junction. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Fall 2020 December 5, 2020 Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics A General Purview Dr. Prajwal MohanMurthy 1 Argonne National Laboratory University of Chicago 9700 S Cass Ave, Lemont, IL 60439, U.S.A Department of Physics and Astronomy Mississippi State University PO Box 5167, Mississippi State, MS 39762, U.S.A Quantum mechanics revolutionized physics in early 20th century and lead to one of the two field theories, the standard model, which is a crowing achievement of our contemporary times. However, paradoxes within the quantum mechanics, were recognized early on. These paradoxes have paved way to multiple interpretations of quantum mechanics over the century. These interpretations do not particularly affect the validity of the empirically established observations and measurements. We will attempt to introduce a few major interpretations of quantum mechanics and present their advantages and disadvantages in a very limited fashion.
    [Show full text]
  • Lessons of Bell's Theorem: Nonlocality, Yes; Action at a Distance, Not Necessarily
    Lessons of Bell's Theorem: Nonlocality, yes; Action at a distance, not necessarily. Wayne C. Myrvold Department of Philosophy The University of Western Ontario Forthcoming in Shan Gao and Mary Bell, eds., Quantum Nonlocality and Reality { 50 Years of Bell's Theorem (Cambridge University Press) Contents 1 Introduction. page 1 2 Does relativity preclude action at a distance? 2 3 Locally explicable correlations. 5 4 Correlations that are not locally explicable 9 5 Bell and Local Causality 11 6 Quantum state evolution 13 7 Local beables for relativistic collapse theories 17 8 A comment on Everettian theories 19 9 Conclusion 20 10 Acknowledgments 20 11 Appendix 20 References 25 1 Introduction. 1 1 Introduction. Fifty years after the publication of Bell's theorem, there remains some con- troversy regarding what the theorem is telling us about quantum mechanics, and what the experimental violations of Bell inequalities are telling us about the world. This chapter represents my best attempt to be clear about what I think the lessons are. In brief: there is some sort of nonlocality inherent in any quantum theory, and, moreover, in any theory that reproduces, even approximately, the quantum probabilities for the outcomes of experiments. But not all forms of nonlocality are the same; there is a distinction to be made between action at a distance and other forms of nonlocality, and I will argue that the nonlocality required to violate the Bell inequalities need not involve action at a distance. Furthermore, the distinction between forms of nonlocality makes a difference when it comes to compatibility with relativis- tic causal structure.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading List on Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics David Wallace, June 2018
    Reading list on philosophy of quantum mechanics David Wallace, June 2018 1. Introduction .............................................................................................................................................. 2 2. Introductory and general readings in philosophy of quantum theory ..................................................... 4 3. Physics and math resources ...................................................................................................................... 5 4. The quantum measurement problem....................................................................................................... 7 4. Non-locality in quantum theory ................................................................................................................ 8 5. State-eliminativist hidden variable theories (aka Psi-epistemic theories) ............................................. 10 6. The Copenhagen interpretation and its descendants ............................................................................ 12 7. Decoherence ........................................................................................................................................... 15 8. The Everett interpretation (aka the Many-Worlds Theory) .................................................................... 17 9. The de Broglie-Bohm theory ................................................................................................................... 22 10. Dynamical-collapse theories ................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1909.06340V3 [Quant-Ph] 20 Jul 2020
    From Quantum Foundations, to Spontaneous Quantum Gravity - An overview of the new theory - Tejinder P. Singh Tata Institute of Fundamental Research, Homi Bhabha Road, Mumbai 400005, India [email protected] ABSTRACT Spontaneous localisation is a falsifiable dynamical mechanism which modifies quantum me- chanics, and explains the absence of position superpositions in the macroscopic world. How- ever, this is an ad hoc phenomenological proposal. Adler's theory of trace dynamics, working on a flat Minkowski space-time, derives quantum (field) theory, and spontaneous localisation, as a thermodynamic approximation to an underlying noncommutative matrix dynamics. We describe how to incorporate gravity into trace dynamics, by using ideas from Connes' non- commutative geometry programme. This leads us to a new quantum theory of gravity, from which we can predict spontaneous localisation, and give an estimate of the Bekenstein- Hawking entropy of a Schwarzschild black hole. CONTENTS I. Introduction 2 II. Spontaneous Localisation 7 arXiv:1909.06340v3 [quant-ph] 20 Jul 2020 III. Spontaneous Localisation: Track 2 10 IV. The theory of trace dynamics 14 V. The theory of trace dynamics: Track 2 17 VI. Incorporating gravity in trace dynamics 24 VII. Incorporating gravity in trace dynamics: Track 2 27 1 VIII. Including Yang-Mills fields 39 IX. Physical applications and predictions of Spontaneous Quantum Gravity 40 X. A comparison with other quantum gravity approaches 41 XI. Concluding Remarks 43 References 45 I. INTRODUCTION We have recently proposed a new candidate quantum theory of gravity [1], which we have named Spontaneous Quantum Gravity. The theory is built on the following principle: There ought to exist a reformulation of quantum (field) theory which does not depend on classical time [2].
    [Show full text]
  • Dynamical Reduction Models: Present Status and Future Developments
    Dynamical reduction models: present status and future developments Angelo Bassi Dipartimento di Fisica Teorica, Universit`adegli Studi di Trieste, Strada Costiera 11, 34014 Trieste, Italy. Mathematisches Institut der Ludwig-Maximilians Universit¨at, Theresienstr. 39, 80333 M¨unchen, Germany. E-mail: [email protected], [email protected] Abstract. We review the major achievements of the dynamical reduction program, showing why and how it provides a unified, consistent description of physical phenomena, from the microscopic quantum domain to the macroscopic classical one. We discuss the difficulties in generalizing the existing models in order to comprise also relativistic quantum field theories. We point out possible future lines of research, ranging from mathematical physics to phenomenology. 1. Quantum Mechanics, measurements and environment Standard Quantum Mechanics is known to talk only about the outcomes of measurements, but it has nothing to say about the world as it is, independently of any measurement or act of observation. This is a source of serious difficulties, which have been clearly elucidated e.g. by J. Bell [1]: It would seem that the theory is exclusively concerned about ‘results of measurements’, and has nothing to say about anything else. What exactly qualifies some physical systems to play the role of ‘measurer’? Was the wavefunction of the world waiting to jump for thousands of millions of years until a single-celled living creature appeared? Or did it have to wait a little bit longer, for some better qualified system ... with a Ph.D.? arXiv:quant-ph/0701014v2 8 Feb 2007 Measuring devices, like photographic plates and bubble chambers, are very sophisticated and highly structured physical systems, which anyhow are made up of atoms; we then expect them to be ultimately described in quantum mechanical terms by means of the Schr¨odinger equation.
    [Show full text]
  • Benefits of Objective Collapse Models for Cosmology and Quantum Gravity Contents 1 Introduction
    Benefits of Objective Collapse Models for Cosmology and Quantum Gravity Elias Okon Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México Circuito Maestro Mario de la Cueva s/n, Distrito Federal, 04510, Mexico E-mail: [email protected] Daniel Sudarsky Instituto de Ciencias Nucleares, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México Apartado Postal 70-543, Distrito Federal, 04510, México E-mail: [email protected] Abstract: We display a number of advantages of objective collapse theories for the resolution of long-standing problems in cosmology and quantum gravity. In particular, we examine applications of objective reduction models to three important issues: the origin of the seeds of cosmic structure, the problem of time in quantum gravity and the information loss paradox; we show how reduction models contain the necessary tools to provide solutions for these issues. We wrap up with an adventurous proposal, which relates the spontaneous collapse events of objective collapse models to microscopic virtual black holes. Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Objective collapse theories 3 3 Seeds of cosmic structure 5 3.1 Thestandardstoryanditsflaws . ....... 6 3.2 Cosmic structure in light of collapse theories . ............... 9 4 Time in quantum gravity 11 4.1 Theproblem ...................................... 12 4.2 A solution involving collapse . ......... 14 5 Black holes and information 15 5.1 Theparadox ...................................... 15 5.2 Objective collapse and the loss of unitarity . ............. 19 6 Self-consistent bootstrapping and theory construction 21 7 Summary 23 1 Introduction An honest application of quantum mechanics to cosmology requires, by necessity, the use of an observer independent interpretation of the theory. That is, a version of the quantum formalism not fundamentally based on the notion of measurement or on that of an observer external to 1 the studied system.
    [Show full text]
  • The Weight of Collapse: Dynamical Reduction Models in General Relativistic Contexts
    The weight of collapse: dynamical reduction models in general relativistic contexts Elias Okon Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México Circuito Maestro Mario de la Cueva s/n, Distrito Federal, 04510, Mexico E-mail: [email protected] Daniel Sudarsky Instituto de Ciencias Nucleares, Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México Apartado Postal 70-543, Distrito Federal, 04510, México E-mail: [email protected] Abstract: Inspired by possible connections between gravity and foundational question in quantum theory, we consider an approach for the adaptation of objective collapse models to a general relativistic context. We apply these ideas to a list of open problems in cosmology and quantum gravity, such as the emergence of seeds of cosmic structure, the black hole information issue, the problem of time in quantum gravity and, in a more speculative manner, to the nature of dark energy and the origin of the very special initial state of the universe. We conclude that objective collapse models offer a rather promising path to deal with all of these issues. 1 Introduction The project of constructing a quantum theory of gravity is often regarded as entirely independent of the one devoted to clarifying foundational questions within standard quantum theory—the latter, a task mostly performed in the non-relativistic domain. There are, however, very suggestive indications that the two topics are intimately connected. To begin with, the standard interpretation of quantum mechanics, crucially dependent on the notions of measurement or observer, seems ill-suited to be applied to non-standard contexts, such as radiating black holes or the early universe.
    [Show full text]
  • Towards a Theory of Wavefunction Collapse Part 2: Arxiv:1701.01765V3
    Towards a theory of wavefunction collapse Part 2: Collapse as abrupt reconfigurations of wavefunction’s evolution in a dynamically expanding spacetime Garrelt Quandt-Wiese 1 Schlesierstr. 16, 64297 Darmstadt, Germany [email protected] http://www.quandt-wiese.de A new approach to wavefunction collapse is proposed. The so-called Dynamical Spacetime approach enhances semiclassical gravity and enables it for an expla- nation of wavefunction collapse by postulating that the spacetime region on which quantum fields exist and on which the wavefunction’s evolution can be regarded is bounded towards the future by a spacelike hypersurface, which is dynamically ex- panding towards the future. Collapse is displayed in the way that the wavefunction’s evolution becomes unstable at certain critical expansions of spacetime, at which it reconfigures via a self-reinforcing mechanism quasi-abruptly to an evolution re- sembling a classical trajectory. Thereby, spacetime geometry changes in favour of the winning state, which causes the path of the other state to vanish by destructive interference. This mechanism for collapse can explain the quantum correlations in EPR experiments without coming into conflict with relativity and the Free Will theo- rem. The Dynamical Spacetime approach is mathematically formulated on basis of the Einstein-Hilbert action and predicts for the Newtonian limit the same lifetimes of superpositions as the gravity-based approaches of Diosi´ and Penrose. A second important feature of the Dynamical Spacetime approach is its capability to forecast reduction probabilities. It can explain why all experiments performed so-far confirm Born’s rule, and predict deviations from it, when solids evolve into three-state su- perpositions.
    [Show full text]
  • A Conjecture Concerning Determinism, Reduction, and Measurement in Quantum Mechanics ∗
    A conjecture concerning determinism, reduction, and measurement in quantum mechanics ∗ Arthur Jabs Alumnus, Technical University Berlin. Voßstr. 9, 10117 Berlin, Germany [email protected] (15 August 2017) Abstract. Determinism is established in quantum mechanics by tracing the probabilities in the Born rules back to the absolute (overall) phase constants of the wave functions and recognizing these phase constants as pseudorandom numbers. The reduction process (collapse) is independent of measurement. It occurs when two wavepackets overlap in ordinary space and satisfy a certain criterion, which depends on the phase constants of both wavepackets. Reduction means contraction of the wavepackets to the place of overlap. A measurement apparatus always fans out the incoming wavepacket into spatially separated eigenpackets of the chosen observable. When one of these eigenpackets together with a wavepacket in the apparatus satisfy the criterion, the reduction associates the place of contraction with an eigenvalue of the observable. The theory is nonlocal and contextual. Keywords: determinism, overall phases, hidden variables, reduction, collapse, localization, quantum measurement, Born rule PACS: 01.70.+w; 03.65.{w; 03.65.Ta; 03.65.Vf 1 Introduction 2 2 The absolute phase constants 3 3 Reduction 6 4 The spacetime nature of measurements 8 5 Reproducing the Born rules 13 Appendix A. Valuation of the absolute phase 16 Appendix B. Approximation in Eq. (5.4) 17 Notes and references 18-21 ∗An earlier version of this article was paper-published in Quant. Stud.: Math. Found. 3 (4) 279-292 (2016). The content of the present version is the same but the presentation is improved.
    [Show full text]