Interpreting Quantum Mechanics in Terms of Random Discontinuous Motion of Particles

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Interpreting Quantum Mechanics in Terms of Random Discontinuous Motion of Particles Interpreting Quantum Mechanics in Terms of Random Discontinuous Motion of Particles by Shan Gao THESIS submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Unit for History and Philosophy of Science Centre for Time, SOPHI Faculty of Science Department of Philosophy Supervisors: Dr. Dean Rickles Prof. Huw Price University of Sydney Sydney, Australia March 2012 c Shan Gao 2011 All rights reserved This thesis is copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, without the prior written permission of the author. This thesis is dedicated to Erwin Schr¨odinger,who introduced the wave function, discovered its equation named after him, and argued that quantum mechanics is in- complete by his famous cat paradox. Abstract This thesis is an attempt to reconstruct the conceptual foundations of quantum mechanics. First, we argue that the wave function in quantum mechanics is a description of random discontinuous motion of particles, and the modulus square of the wave function gives the probability density of the particles being in certain locations in space. Next, we show that the linear non-relativistic evolution of the wave function of an isolated system obeys the free Schr¨odingerequation due to the requirements of spacetime translation invariance and relativistic invariance. Thirdly, we argue that the random discontinuous motion of particles may lead to a stochastic, nonlinear collapse evolution of the wave function. A discrete model of energy-conserved wavefunction collapse is proposed and shown to be consistent with existing experiments and our macroscopic experience. In addition, we also give a critical analysis of the de Broglie-Bohm theory, the many-worlds interpretation and other dynamical collapse theories, and briefly analyze the problem of the incompatibility between quantum mechanics and special relativity. 4 Acknowledgement The idea of random discontinuous motion of particles came to my mind when I was a post- graduate at the Institute of Electronics, Chinese Academy of Sciences in 1993. I am happy that finally it has a more logical and satisfying formulation in this PhD thesis. During the writing of the thesis, I have been supported financially by a University of Sydney Interna- tional Scholarship and a Postgraduate Scholarship in Quantum Foundations provided by the Unit for HPS and Centre for Time (SOPHI), as well as by two Lucy Firth Scholarships in Philosophy provided by the Department of Philosophy. I would like to express my deepest gratitude to my supervisors, Dean Rickles and Huw Price, whose understanding, motivation and personal guidance was indispensable during my PhD studies. I am deeply indebted to them for their continuous encouragement, stimulating suggestions and healthy criticism which helped me greatly during my research and writing of this thesis. Their professional approach and accuracy was particularly beneficial to my study. I wish to express my warm and sincere thanks to the head of the Unit for HPS, Ofer Gal, the postgraduate coordinator, Hans Pols, and Debbie Castle. I am grateful for their personal support and for their reassurance regarding technical conditions during my PhD work. I would like to take this opportunity to thank all the other members of the Unit for their help and encouragement throughout the years. I would like to gratefully thank David Miller, Rod Sutherland, Hans Westman and Owen Maroney for helpful discussions and useful suggestions. I owe a debt of gratitude to all the PhD students here who I shared good times and had fun with. My deepest gratitude goes to my parents, Qingfeng Gao and Lihua Zhao, who spared no effort to provide the best possible environment for me to grow up in and their constant support during my extended studies. They have always allowed me to have the freedom of choice, and for that I am truly grateful. I am also thankful to my brother, Yuan Gao, and to all my friends, as they have always been willing to share their thoughts with me and provide alternative viewpoints which have helped me think in a more holistic fashion. Finally, I am deeply indebted to my wife Huixia and my daughter Ruiqi for their un- flagging love and support throughout my study; this dissertation would have been simply impossible without them. Moreover, they have never let me forget the true values of life. 5 Publications 1. On Di´osi-Penrose criterion of gravity-induced quantum collapse, International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 49, 849-853 (2010). 2. The wave function and quantum reality, in Proceedings of the International Conference on Advances in Quantum Theory, A. Khrennikov, G. Jaeger, M. Schlosshauer, G. Weihs (eds), AIP Conference Proceedings 1327, 334-338 (2011). 3. Meaning of the wave function, International Journal of Quantum Chemistry, 111, 4124- 4138 (2011). 4. Is gravity an entropic force? Entropy special issue \Black Hole Thermodynamics", Jacob D. Bekenstein (eds), 13, 936-948 (2011). 5. A quantum physical argument for panpsychism, Forthcoming in Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2012. 6 Contents 1 Introduction 10 2 Meaning of the Wave Function 13 2.1 Standard quantum mechanics and impulse measurements........... 14 2.2 Weak measurements................................ 16 2.3 Protective measurements.............................. 17 2.3.1 Measurements with natural protection.................. 18 2.3.2 Measurements with artificial protection................. 20 2.3.3 Further discussions............................. 21 2.4 On the mass and charge density of a quantum system............. 22 2.4.1 A heuristic argument............................ 22 2.4.2 The answer of protective measurement.................. 23 2.4.3 A specific example............................. 24 2.5 The physical origin of mass and charge density................. 26 2.5.1 The mass and charge density is effective................. 27 2.5.2 The ergodic motion of a particle is discontinuous............ 28 2.5.3 An argument for random discontinuous motion............. 30 2.6 The wave function as a description of random discontinuous motion of particles 31 2.6.1 An analysis of random discontinuous motion of particles........ 31 2.6.2 Interpreting the wave function...................... 33 3 Schr¨odinger'sEquation and the Conservation Laws 36 3.1 Spacetime translation and its invariance..................... 37 3.2 Relativistic invariance............................... 39 3.3 Derivation of the free Schr¨odingerequation................... 40 3.4 Further discussions................................. 41 3.5 On the conservation of energy and momentum................. 43 4 A Suggested Solution to the Measurement Problem 47 4.1 The reality of wavefunction collapse....................... 48 4.1.1 Against the de Broglie-Bohm theory................... 48 4.1.2 Against the many-worlds interpretation................. 52 4.2 A conjecture on the origin of wavefunction collapse............... 56 4.2.1 The chooser in discrete time........................ 56 4.2.2 Energy conservation and the choices................... 58 4.2.3 In search of a deeper basis......................... 59 4.3 A discrete model of energy-conserved wavefunction collapse.......... 61 4.4 On the consistency of the model and experiments................ 67 4.4.1 Maintenance of coherence......................... 67 4.4.2 Rapid localization in measurement situations.............. 68 4.4.3 Emergence of the classical world..................... 70 4.5 Critical comments on other dynamical collapse models............. 72 4.5.1 Penrose's gravity-induced wavefunction collapse model......... 72 4.5.2 The CSL model............................... 76 7 CONTENTS 5 Random Discontinuous Motion and Special Relativity 79 5.1 The picture of motion distorted by the Lorentz transformation........ 79 5.1.1 Single particle picture........................... 79 5.1.2 Picture of quantum entanglement..................... 81 5.1.3 Picture of wavefunction collapse..................... 82 5.2 On the absoluteness of simultaneity........................ 84 5.3 Collapse dynamics and preferred Lorentz frame................. 86 8 I think I can safely say that nobody understands quantum mechanics... Do not keep saying to yourself, if you can possible avoid it, \But how can it be like that?" because you will get `down the drain', into a blind alley from which nobody has escaped. Nobody knows how it can be like that. | Richard Feynman, 1964 1 Introduction Quantum mechanics, according to its Schr¨odingerpicture, is a non-relativistic theory about the wave function and its evolution. There are two main problems in the conceptual foun- dations of quantum mechanics. The first one concerns the physical meaning of the wave function in the theory. It has been widely argued that the probability interpretation is not wholly satisfactory because of resorting to the vague concept of measurement - though it is still the standard interpretation in textbooks nowadays. On the other hand, the meaning of the wave function is also in dispute in the alternatives to quantum mechanics such as the de Broglie-Bohm theory and the many-worlds interpretation (de Broglie 1928; Bohm 1952; Everett 1957; De Witt and Graham 1973). Exactly what does the wave function describe then? The second problem concerns the evolution of the wave function. It includes two parts. One part concerns the linear Schr¨odingerevolution. Why does the linear non-relativistic evolution
Recommended publications
  • International Centre for Theoretical Physics
    XA<? 6 H 0 <! W IC/95/320 INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR THEORETICAL PHYSICS BOHM'S THEORY VERSUS DYNAMICAL REDUCTION G.C. Ghirardi and INTERNATIONAL ATOMIC ENERGY R. Grassi AGENCY UNITED NATIONS EDUCATIONAL, SCIENTIFIC AND CULTURAL ORGANIZATION MIRAMARE-TRIESTE VQL 'l 7 Ha ° 7 IC/95/320 ABSTRACT International Atomic Energy Agency and United Nations Educational scientific and Cultural Organization made that theories which exhibit parameter , INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR THEORETICAL PHYSICS BOHM'S THEORY VERSUS DYNAMICAL REDUCTION1 1. Introduction. We share today's widespread opinion that Standard Quantum Mechanics (SQM), in spite of its enormous successes, has failed in giving a G.C. Ghirardi satisfactory picture of the world, as we perceive it. The difficulties about International Centre for Theoretical Physics, Trieste, Italy, the conceptual foundations of the theory arising, as is well known, from and the so-called objectification problem, have stimulated various attempts to Department of Theoretical Physics. University di Trieste, Trieste, Italy overcome them. Among these one should mention the search for a and deterministic completion of the theory, the many worlds and many minds intepretations, the so called environment induced superselection rules, the R. Grassi quantum histories approach and the dynamical reduction program. In this Department of Civil Engineering, University of Udine, Udine, Italy. paper we will focus our attention on the only available and precisely formulated examples of a deterministic completion and of a stochastic and nonlinear modification of SQM, i.e., Bohm's theory and the spontaneous reduction models, respectively. It is useful to stress that while the first theory is fully equivalent, from a predictive point of view, to SQM, the second one qualifies itself as a rival of SQM but with empirical divergence so small that it can claim all the same experimental support.
    [Show full text]
  • International Centre for Theoretical Physics
    ... „. •::^i'— IC/94/93 S r- INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR THEORETICAL PHYSICS QUANTUM MECHANICS WITH SPONTANEOUS LOCALIZATION AND EXPERIMENTS F. Benatti INTERNATIONAL ATOMIC ENERGY G.C. Ghirardi AGENCY and R. Grassi UNITED NATIONS EDUCATIONAL, SCIENTIFIC AND CULTURAL ORGANIZATION MIRAMARE-TRIESTE 1 f I \ •» !r 10/94/93 International Atomic Energy Agency and United Nations Educational Scientific and Cultural Organization ABSTRACT INTERNATIONAL CENTRE FOR THEORETICAL PHYSICS We examine from an experimental point of v'iew the recently proposed models of spontaneous reduction. We compare their implications about decoherence with those of environmental effects. We discuss the treatment, within the considered models, of the so called quantum telegraph phenomenon and we show that, contrary to what has QUANTUM MECHANICS heen recently stated, no problems are met, Finally, we review recent interesting work WITH SPONTANEOUS LOCALIZATION investigating the implications of dynamical reduction for the proton decay. AND EXPERIMENTS ' F. Heiiatti Dip.irtimento di I-'iska Tcwicii, Univorsita di Trieste. Trieste, July, G.C. (ihirardi 1. INTRODUCTION International Centre for Theoretical Physics, Trieste, Italy One of the most intriguing features of Quantum Mechanics (QM) is that it provides and too good a description of microphenomena to be considered a mere recipe to predict Dipartiniento di Fisica Tc-orica, Univorsita di Trieste, Trieste, Italy probabilities of prospective measurement outcomes from given initial conditions and, and yet, as a fundamental theory of reality, it gives rise to serious conceptual problems, among which the impossibility, in its orthodox interpretation, to think of all physical II. CSrasfli observables of the system under consideration as possessing in all instances definite Dipartiinento di Kisira, Universita di Udinc, Udrne, Italy.
    [Show full text]
  • Einstein's Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics L
    Einstein's Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics L. E. Ballentine Citation: American Journal of Physics 40, 1763(1972); doi: 10.1119/1.1987060 View online: https://doi.org/10.1119/1.1987060 View Table of Contents: http://aapt.scitation.org/toc/ajp/40/12 Published by the American Association of Physics Teachers Articles you may be interested in Einstein’s opposition to the quantum theory American Journal of Physics 58, 673 (1990); 10.1119/1.16399 Probability theory in quantum mechanics American Journal of Physics 54, 883 (1986); 10.1119/1.14783 The Shaky Game: Einstein, Realism and the Quantum Theory American Journal of Physics 56, 571 (1988); 10.1119/1.15540 QUANTUM MEASUREMENTS American Journal of Physics 85, 5 (2017); 10.1119/1.4967925 Einstein’s boxes American Journal of Physics 73, 164 (2005); 10.1119/1.1811620 Development of concepts in the history of quantum theory American Journal of Physics 43, 389 (1975); 10.1119/1.9833 an Association of Physics Teachers Explore the AAPT Career Center - access hundreds of physics education and other STEM teaching jobs at two-year and four-year colleges and universities. http://jobs.aapt.org December 1972 Einstein’s Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics L. E. BALLENTINE his own interpretation of the theory are less well Physics Department known. Indeed, Heisenberg’s essay “The Develop­ Simon Fraser University ment of the Interpretation of the Quantum Burnaby, B.C., Canada Theory,”2 in which he replied in detail to many (Received 23 May 1972; revised 27 June 1972) critics of the Copenhagen interpretation, takes no account of Einstein’s specific arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Trajectory Distribution for Weak Measurement of A
    Quantum Trajectory Distribution for Weak Measurement of a Superconducting Qubit: Experiment meets Theory Parveen Kumar,1, ∗ Suman Kundu,2, † Madhavi Chand,2, ‡ R. Vijayaraghavan,2, § and Apoorva Patel1, ¶ 1Centre for High Energy Physics, Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore 560012, India 2Department of Condensed Matter Physics and Materials Science, Tata Institue of Fundamental Research, Mumbai 400005, India (Dated: April 11, 2018) Quantum measurements are described as instantaneous projections in textbooks. They can be stretched out in time using weak measurements, whereby one can observe the evolution of a quantum state as it heads towards one of the eigenstates of the measured operator. This evolution can be understood as a continuous nonlinear stochastic process, generating an ensemble of quantum trajectories, consisting of noisy fluctuations on top of geodesics that attract the quantum state towards the measured operator eigenstates. The rate of evolution is specific to each system-apparatus pair, and the Born rule constraint requires the magnitudes of the noise and the attraction to be precisely related. We experimentally observe the entire quantum trajectory distribution for weak measurements of a superconducting qubit in circuit QED architecture, quantify it, and demonstrate that it agrees very well with the predictions of a single-parameter white-noise stochastic process. This characterisation of quantum trajectories is a powerful clue to unraveling the dynamics of quantum measurement, beyond the conventional axiomatic quantum
    [Show full text]
  • Tsekov, R., Heifetz, E., & Cohen, E
    Tsekov, R., Heifetz, E., & Cohen, E. (2017). Derivation of the local- mean stochastic quantum force. Fluctuation and Noise Letters, 16(3), [1750028]. https://doi.org/10.1142/S0219477517500286 Peer reviewed version Link to published version (if available): 10.1142/S0219477517500286 Link to publication record in Explore Bristol Research PDF-document This is the author accepted manuscript (AAM). The final published version (version of record) is available online via World Scientific at http://www.worldscientific.com/doi/abs/10.1142/S0219477517500286. Please refer to any applicable terms of use of the publisher. University of Bristol - Explore Bristol Research General rights This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies. Please cite only the published version using the reference above. Full terms of use are available: http://www.bristol.ac.uk/red/research-policy/pure/user-guides/ebr-terms/ Derivation of the Local-Mean Stochastic Quantum Force Roumen Tsekov Department of Physical Chemistry, University of Sofia, 1164 Sofia, Bulgaria Eyal Heifetz Department of Geosciences, Tel-Aviv University, Tel-Aviv, Israel Eliahu Cohen H.H. Wills Physics Laboratory, University of Bristol, Tyndall Avenue, Bristol, BS8 1TL, U.K (Dated: May 16, 2017) Abstract We regard the non-relativistic Schr¨odinger equation as an ensemble mean representation of the stochastic motion of a single particle in a vacuum, subject to an undefined stochastic quantum force. The local mean of the quantum force is found to be proportional to the third spatial derivative of the probability density function, while its associated pressure is proportional to the second spatial derivative. The latter arises from the single particle diluted gas pressure, and this observation allows to interpret the quantum Bohm potential as the energy required to put a particle in a bath of fluctuating vacuum at constant entropy and volume.
    [Show full text]
  • The Minimal Modal Interpretation of Quantum Theory
    The Minimal Modal Interpretation of Quantum Theory Jacob A. Barandes1, ∗ and David Kagan2, y 1Jefferson Physical Laboratory, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA 02138 2Department of Physics, University of Massachusetts Dartmouth, North Dartmouth, MA 02747 (Dated: May 5, 2017) We introduce a realist, unextravagant interpretation of quantum theory that builds on the existing physical structure of the theory and allows experiments to have definite outcomes but leaves the theory's basic dynamical content essentially intact. Much as classical systems have specific states that evolve along definite trajectories through configuration spaces, the traditional formulation of quantum theory permits assuming that closed quantum systems have specific states that evolve unitarily along definite trajectories through Hilbert spaces, and our interpretation extends this intuitive picture of states and Hilbert-space trajectories to the more realistic case of open quantum systems despite the generic development of entanglement. We provide independent justification for the partial-trace operation for density matrices, reformulate wave-function collapse in terms of an underlying interpolating dynamics, derive the Born rule from deeper principles, resolve several open questions regarding ontological stability and dynamics, address a number of familiar no-go theorems, and argue that our interpretation is ultimately compatible with Lorentz invariance. Along the way, we also investigate a number of unexplored features of quantum theory, including an interesting geometrical structure|which we call subsystem space|that we believe merits further study. We conclude with a summary, a list of criteria for future work on quantum foundations, and further research directions. We include an appendix that briefly reviews the traditional Copenhagen interpretation and the measurement problem of quantum theory, as well as the instrumentalist approach and a collection of foundational theorems not otherwise discussed in the main text.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics: a General Purview
    Mississippi State University Scholars Junction Collge of Arts and Sciences Publications and Scholarship College of Arts and Sciences 10-1-2020 Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics: A General Purview Prajwal Mohanmurthy Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarsjunction.msstate.edu/cas-publications Recommended Citation Mohanmurthy, Prajwal, "Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics: A General Purview" (2020). Collge of Arts and Sciences Publications and Scholarship. 14. https://scholarsjunction.msstate.edu/cas-publications/14 This Preprint is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Arts and Sciences at Scholars Junction. It has been accepted for inclusion in Collge of Arts and Sciences Publications and Scholarship by an authorized administrator of Scholars Junction. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Fall 2020 December 5, 2020 Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics A General Purview Dr. Prajwal MohanMurthy 1 Argonne National Laboratory University of Chicago 9700 S Cass Ave, Lemont, IL 60439, U.S.A Department of Physics and Astronomy Mississippi State University PO Box 5167, Mississippi State, MS 39762, U.S.A Quantum mechanics revolutionized physics in early 20th century and lead to one of the two field theories, the standard model, which is a crowing achievement of our contemporary times. However, paradoxes within the quantum mechanics, were recognized early on. These paradoxes have paved way to multiple interpretations of quantum mechanics over the century. These interpretations do not particularly affect the validity of the empirically established observations and measurements. We will attempt to introduce a few major interpretations of quantum mechanics and present their advantages and disadvantages in a very limited fashion.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding the Born Rule in Weak Measurements
    Understanding the Born Rule in Weak Measurements Apoorva Patel Centre for High Energy Physics, Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore 31 July 2017, Open Quantum Systems 2017, ICTS-TIFR N. Gisin, Phys. Rev. Lett. 52 (1984) 1657 A. Patel and P. Kumar, Phys Rev. A (to appear), arXiv:1509.08253 S. Kundu, T. Roy, R. Vijayaraghavan, P. Kumar and A. Patel (in progress) 31 July 2017, Open Quantum Systems 2017, A. Patel (CHEP, IISc) Weak Measurements and Born Rule / 29 Abstract Projective measurement is used as a fundamental axiom in quantum mechanics, even though it is discontinuous and cannot predict which measured operator eigenstate will be observed in which experimental run. The probabilistic Born rule gives it an ensemble interpretation, predicting proportions of various outcomes over many experimental runs. Understanding gradual weak measurements requires replacing this scenario with a dynamical evolution equation for the collapse of the quantum state in individual experimental runs. We revisit the framework to model quantum measurement as a continuous nonlinear stochastic process. It combines attraction towards the measured operator eigenstates with white noise, and for a specific ratio of the two reproduces the Born rule. This fluctuation-dissipation relation implies that the quantum state collapse involves the system-apparatus interaction only, and the Born rule is a consequence of the noise contributed by the apparatus. The ensemble of the quantum trajectories is predicted by the stochastic process in terms of a single evolution parameter, and matches well with the weak measurement results for superconducting transmon qubits. 31 July 2017, Open Quantum Systems 2017, A. Patel (CHEP, IISc) Weak Measurements and Born Rule / 29 Axioms of Quantum Dynamics (1) Unitary evolution (Schr¨odinger): d d i dt |ψi = H|ψi , i dt ρ =[H,ρ] .
    [Show full text]
  • Lessons of Bell's Theorem: Nonlocality, Yes; Action at a Distance, Not Necessarily
    Lessons of Bell's Theorem: Nonlocality, yes; Action at a distance, not necessarily. Wayne C. Myrvold Department of Philosophy The University of Western Ontario Forthcoming in Shan Gao and Mary Bell, eds., Quantum Nonlocality and Reality { 50 Years of Bell's Theorem (Cambridge University Press) Contents 1 Introduction. page 1 2 Does relativity preclude action at a distance? 2 3 Locally explicable correlations. 5 4 Correlations that are not locally explicable 9 5 Bell and Local Causality 11 6 Quantum state evolution 13 7 Local beables for relativistic collapse theories 17 8 A comment on Everettian theories 19 9 Conclusion 20 10 Acknowledgments 20 11 Appendix 20 References 25 1 Introduction. 1 1 Introduction. Fifty years after the publication of Bell's theorem, there remains some con- troversy regarding what the theorem is telling us about quantum mechanics, and what the experimental violations of Bell inequalities are telling us about the world. This chapter represents my best attempt to be clear about what I think the lessons are. In brief: there is some sort of nonlocality inherent in any quantum theory, and, moreover, in any theory that reproduces, even approximately, the quantum probabilities for the outcomes of experiments. But not all forms of nonlocality are the same; there is a distinction to be made between action at a distance and other forms of nonlocality, and I will argue that the nonlocality required to violate the Bell inequalities need not involve action at a distance. Furthermore, the distinction between forms of nonlocality makes a difference when it comes to compatibility with relativis- tic causal structure.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading List on Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics David Wallace, June 2018
    Reading list on philosophy of quantum mechanics David Wallace, June 2018 1. Introduction .............................................................................................................................................. 2 2. Introductory and general readings in philosophy of quantum theory ..................................................... 4 3. Physics and math resources ...................................................................................................................... 5 4. The quantum measurement problem....................................................................................................... 7 4. Non-locality in quantum theory ................................................................................................................ 8 5. State-eliminativist hidden variable theories (aka Psi-epistemic theories) ............................................. 10 6. The Copenhagen interpretation and its descendants ............................................................................ 12 7. Decoherence ........................................................................................................................................... 15 8. The Everett interpretation (aka the Many-Worlds Theory) .................................................................... 17 9. The de Broglie-Bohm theory ................................................................................................................... 22 10. Dynamical-collapse theories ................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • A Simple Approach to Measurement in Quantum Mechanics
    A Simple Approach To Measurement in Quantum Mechanics Anthony Rizzi Institute for Advanced Physics, [email protected] Abstract: A simple way, accessible to undergraduates, is given to understand measurements in quantum mechanics. The ensemble interpretation of quantum mechanics is natural and provides this simple access to the measurement problem. This paper explains measurement in terms of this relatively young interpretation, first made rigorous by L. Ballentine starting in the 1970’s. Its facility is demonstrated through a detailed explication of the Wigner Friend argument using the Stern-Gerlach experiment. Following a recent textbook, this approach is developed further through analysis of free particle states as well as the Schrödinger cat paradox. Some pitfalls of the Copenhagen interpretation are drawn out. Introduction The measurement problem in quantum mechanics confounds students and experts. arXiv:quant-ph/ 09 Feb 2020 The problem arose near the founding of the formal discipline of quantum mechanics with especially the debates between Einstein and Bohr. There is much notable history, but since I do not aim to give an exhaustive history, only the necessary points of an outline, I only note the following points. Einstein held, among other things, the most basic form of ensemble interpretation saying: “The attempt to conceive the quantum-theoretical description as the complete description of the individual systems leads to unnatural theoretical interpretations, which become immediately unnecessary if one accepts the interpretation that the description refers to ensembles of systems and not to individual systems.”1 Heisenberg and Bohr, both working in Copenhagen, Denmark, made a working model of measurement which developed into the somewhat ill defined Copenhagen interpretation.
    [Show full text]
  • Jhep01(2021)118
    Published for SISSA by Springer Received: July 7, 2020 Revised: October 31, 2020 Accepted: December 3, 2020 Published: January 20, 2021 JHEP01(2021)118 The path integral of 3D gravity near extremality; or, JT gravity with defects as a matrix integral Henry Maxfield and Gustavo J. Turiaci Department of Physics, University of California, Santa Barbara, CA 93106, U.S.A. E-mail: [email protected], [email protected] Abstract: We propose that a class of new topologies, for which there is no classical solution, should be included in the path integral of three-dimensional pure gravity, and that their inclusion solves pathological negativities in the spectrum, replacing them with a nonperturbative shift of the BTZ extremality bound. We argue that a two dimensional calculation using a dimensionally reduced theory captures the leading effects in the near extremal limit. To make this argument, we study a closely related two-dimensional theory of Jackiw-Teitelboim gravity with dynamical defects. We show that this theory is equivalent to a matrix integral. Keywords: 2D Gravity, Black Holes, Conformal Field Theory, Nonperturbative Effects ArXiv ePrint: 2006.11317 Open Access, c The Authors. https://doi.org/10.1007/JHEP01(2021)118 Article funded by SCOAP3. Contents 1 Introduction2 1.1 The spectrum of 3D pure gravity2 1.2 3D gravity in the near-extremal limit5 1.3 JT gravity with defects6 1.4 Outline of paper7 JHEP01(2021)118 2 The path integral of 3D gravity7 2.1 Dimensional reduction7 2.2 The classical solutions: SL(2; Z) black holes.9 2.3 Kaluza-Klein
    [Show full text]