PLUTARCH on SELF and OTHERS* Plutarch Strongly

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

PLUTARCH on SELF and OTHERS* Plutarch Strongly PLUTARCH ON SELF AND OTHERS* 1. INTRODUCTION: THE RELATION OF SELF AND OTHER IN ANTIQUITY AND IN PLUTARCH Plutarch strongly opposed the Epicurean ideal of a sequestered life: man should not withdraw from society, but should as a social being, h¬çon koinwnikón, enter public life, where he meets the other1. Now it is clear that there are many possible attitudes which one can adopt towards the other. They vary from violence against, and manipulation of, the other to sincere concern for the good of the other, from paternalism to responsi- bility for the other, from exclusion to love, from neglect and indifference to an encounter between an I and a Thou, based on mutual respect. What then is Plutarch's position with regard to this question? How does he conceive the relation Self-Other? First of all, one should note that Plutarch’s specific way of putting the question is highly relevant. He always sets the problem from the perspective of the self, hardly ever from the perspective of the other. He wants to exam- ine which attitude one should adopt towards the other in order to act oneself in a virtuous way; he never asks which attitude should be adopted in order to take into account the wishes of the other, to bear in mind as far as possi- ble the other’s identity as being different from that of one’s own. For that very reason, it becomes particularly interesting to examine to what extent Plutarch’s ethics can precisely do justice to the perspective of the other. Now the first question that should be asked is whether it is a remotely realistic thing at all to expect a certain respect for the other as other in Antiquity. To what extent the ancients really cared about the problem of the identity of the other as being different from that of oneself? In fact, the problem had already received some attention in traditional thinking2, * I would like to thank Prof. P.A. Stadter for many valuable remarks on an earlier draft of this article. Where I still disagree with him, it has been with hesitation, and any faults that remain are, of course, entirely my own. I’m also much indebted to Prof. L. Van der Stockt, to Prof. G. Schepens and to Dr. S. Verdegem. 1 See especially the little essay De latenter vivendo (1128A-1130E); for Plutarch’s contro- versy against Epicureanism on this point, see also the final section of Adv. Colot. (1124D-1127E). 2 The seeds of the later problem were already present in ancient Greek thinking, which contains many pairs of opposites, often divided into a positive and a negative pole; see 246 G. ROSKAM and had become quite important in Plutarch’s time. As to the relation between Greeks and Romans, for instance, the basic difference between both peoples was discussed earlier already3 and was underlined more and more in the first centuries A.D.4, even though later authors tried to deny this difference5. In the same way, the differences between man and woman were emphasized long before Plutarch6, although in this case too, one sometimes tried, if not to deny, than certainly to nuance them7. It is clear, then, that in more than one domain, questions related to the prob- lem of the difference between self and other had received already much discussion when Plutarch and his contemporaries had to seek their own, personal answers. The question remains, however, whether such discussions in concrete contexts did also influence ethical thinking about the place of the other. Are there any traces of a moral position that could somehow do justice to the peculiar nature of the other as being different from that of the self? Usually, a respect for the other as other is absent from ancient thinking, even though there can be found some important, though limited, begin- nings. According to Aristotle’s theory of friendship, for instance, one wishes a friend good for his own sake8. However, in such ideal friend- ship, a friend is also another self9, so that respect for the friend is based on a kind of shared identity10. In different Hellenistic philosophical G.E.R. LLOYD, Polarity and Analogy. Two Types of Argumentation in Early Greek Thought, Cambridge 1966, p. 15-171. On the classical period, see P. CARTLEDGE, The Greeks. A Portrait of Self and Others, Oxford 2002. 3 See, e.g., Cicero, Tusc. disp. I 1-3 and Horace, Epist. II 1.156-163. 4 See, e.g., Lucian, De merc. cond. 40; Juvenal, Sat. III 58-125; Tacitus, Ann. II 88, III 60, IV 35, VI 18 etc.; more passages in H. HUNGER, Graeculus perfidus — ‰Italov îtamóv. Il senso dell’alterità nei rapporti Greco-Romani ed Italo-Bizantini, Roma 1987, p. 22-31. 5 See, e.g., Julian, Orat. IV 152d-153a and Libanius, Orat. XV 25; much more material in J. PALM, Rom, Römertum und Imperium in der griechischen Literatur der Kaiserzeit, Lund 1959. 6 See, e.g., Plato, Leges VI 781ab; Republ. V 453b and e, 455c-e; Aristotle, Hist. an. IX 1, 608a-b. 7 See, e.g., Plato, Leges VII 804de and 805cd; Republ. V 451c-456a (A.W. PRICE, Love and Friendship in Plato and Aristotle, Oxford 1989, p. 167-171); Musonius Rufus, fragm. 3 and 4 Hense. 8 EN VIII 2, 1155b31; 4, 1156b9-11; 5, 1157a18-19; IX 1166a2-4; EE VII 6, 1240a24- 25; Rhet. II 4, 1380b36-1381a1; cf. also Cicero, De fin. I XX-69 on the position of some Epicureans. 9 EN IX 4, 1166a31-32; 9, 1170b6-7; EE VII 12, 1245a29-30 and 34-35; cf. also EN VIII 10, 1159b2-4. 10 Cf. A.W. PRICE, op. cit. (n. 7), p. 130: «To love another actively for his sake is above all to identify with him in action by making his acts also one’s own as realizations of choices that one shares with him»; cf. EN IX 9, 1170a2-4. PLUTARCH ON SELF AND OTHERS 247 schools, due attention is given to real differences in talents between indi- viduals11, although each individual should in the end realize the same ideal. In this case too, the perspective of the other as other is hardly taken into account. Extremely important in this context is Panaetius. In his famous per- sonae theory, he distinguishes four considerations that should be taken into account in order to determine the nature of propriety (tò prépon / decorum): the universal, rational nature of human beings (Cicero, De off. I XXX 107), one’s own individual nature (XXX 107-109), external cir- cumstances (XXXII 115) and one’s personal deliberate choice (ibid.). Accordingly, an individual should not only refrain from opposing his uni- versal human nature, but he should also follow his own particular nature instead of trying in vain to imitate the personal characteristics of others (XXXI 110-114). This implies that an action can be appropriate for one man, but inappropriate for another (XXXI 112). For instance, whereas sui- cide is the right alternative for a Cato, it would be wrong for others who have a less austere character (ibid.). And the behaviour that fits in very well with Ulysses would be completely at odds with Ajax (XXXI 113). In this way, Panaetius succeeded to develop an ethical theory that made it possible to give a certain place to the other without merely consider- ing him from the perspective of the self. With this position, Panaetius was a rara avis in Antiquity. Did Plutarch join him? To what extent Plutarch introduced a certain respect for the other as other in his ethical thinking? The question is important for two reasons. First of all, the problem of the relation between self and other returns in several domains of Plutarch’s thinking. Much work has been done here. Nonetheless, the great number of detailed studies have not made all aspects of Plutarch’s position equally clear. Did Plutarch, for instance, ever try to go beyond the different character of Greeks and Romans, in order to reach a unified Greco-Roman culture12? Or should he rather be regarded as a non-integrationist13? And whereas more than 11 See, e.g., Seneca, Epist. 52.3-6 (= Epicurus, fr. 192 Us.); Epist. 95.36-37; De benef. V 25.5; Musonius Rufus, fr. I 2.23-5.2 H.; Philo of Alexandria, Post. XX-71; Deus XIII 61- 64. 12 Cf. J. BOULOGNE, Le sens des ‘Questions Romaines’ de Plutarque, REG 100 (1987), p. 474-475; ID., Plutarque. Un aristocrate grec sous l’occupation romaine, Lille 1994, p. 35-54 and passim. 13 Cf. S.C.R. SWAIN, Hellenism and Empire. Language, Classicism, and Power in the Greek World AD 50-250, Oxford 1996, p. 137-186; cf. also T. DUFF, Plutarch’s Lives. Exploring Virtue and Vice, Oxford 1999, p. 291-308. 248 G. ROSKAM once Plutarch’s very positive treatment of women has been emphasized14, others also nuanced to a certain extent Plutarch’s philogyny15. Secondly, Plutarch’s great emphasis on mildness (praótjv) and humanity (filanqrwpía) seems to point to a certain respect for the other as other: To the Platonist or Aristotelian, eudaimonia (‘felicity’) is self-evidently the goal. It may involve preferring honour to pleasure, death to dis- grace, restraint to indulgence. But it can never lead one to think of the eudaimonia of some other person as to be preferred to one's own. What is notable in Plutarch is not his adhesion to these attitudes, but his tacit modifications of them. These come from the emphasis laid in all his moral judgments on mildness and humanity, praotes and philanthropia; these are qualities which, even if practised in a self-regarding sense, involve at least some degree of concern and understanding for the feel- ings and aims of others16.
Recommended publications
  • Plato As "Architectof Science"
    Plato as "Architectof Science" LEONID ZHMUD ABSTRACT The figureof the cordialhost of the Academy,who invitedthe mostgifted math- ematiciansand cultivatedpure research, whose keen intellectwas able if not to solve the particularproblem then at least to show the methodfor its solution: this figureis quite familiarto studentsof Greekscience. But was the Academy as such a centerof scientificresearch, and did Plato really set for mathemati- cians and astronomersthe problemsthey shouldstudy and methodsthey should use? Oursources tell aboutPlato's friendship or at leastacquaintance with many brilliantmathematicians of his day (Theodorus,Archytas, Theaetetus), but they were neverhis pupils,rather vice versa- he learnedmuch from them and actively used this knowledgein developinghis philosophy.There is no reliableevidence that Eudoxus,Menaechmus, Dinostratus, Theudius, and others, whom many scholarsunite into the groupof so-called"Academic mathematicians," ever were his pupilsor close associates.Our analysis of therelevant passages (Eratosthenes' Platonicus, Sosigenes ap. Simplicius, Proclus' Catalogue of geometers, and Philodemus'History of the Academy,etc.) shows thatthe very tendencyof por- trayingPlato as the architectof sciencegoes back to the earlyAcademy and is bornout of interpretationsof his dialogues. I Plato's relationship to the exact sciences used to be one of the traditional problems in the history of ancient Greek science and philosophy.' From the nineteenth century on it was examined in various aspects, the most significant of which were the historical, philosophical and methodological. In the last century and at the beginning of this century attention was paid peredominantly, although not exclusively, to the first of these aspects, especially to the questions how great Plato's contribution to specific math- ematical research really was, and how reliable our sources are in ascrib- ing to him particular scientific discoveries.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy in Ancient Greek Biography. Turnhout: Brepols, 2016
    Revista Classica, v. 30, n. 2, p. 137-142, 2017 137 BONAZZI, Mauro; SCHORN, Stefan. Bios Philosophos: Philosophy in Ancient Greek Biography. Turnhout: Brepols, 2016. 313p. ISBN 978-2-503-56546-0 Gustavo Laet Gomes* * Mestre em Filosofia Bernardo C. D. A. Vasconcelos** pela Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais. guslaet@ gmail.com Bios Philosophos. Philosophy in Ancient Greek Biography (Brepols, 2016), organized by Mauro Bonazzi and Stefan Schorn, delivers a ** Mestre em Filosofia pela both deep and wide tour through the philosophical aspects of Greek Universidade Federal biographical production. On one hand, it does not concentrate only in de Minas Gerais. the later periods of Greek philosophy, when biographical production bernardovasconcelos abounded, but goes all the way back to the fourth century BCE, when @gmail.com biographical texts were fragmentary and mingled with other styles. On the other, it tries to unveil the philosophical motives in the works of authors who tend to be disregarded as historians, biographers, hagiographers or even as mere fans of the most prominent figures of their own schools. In our review, we will attempt to give a brief account of the ten articles that make up this volume, which, in turn, will hopefully provide an overview of the different connections between the biographies and biographers and their philosophical motives. Thomas Bénatouïl’s Pythagore chez Dicéarque: anectodes biographiques et critique de la philosophie contemplative (p. 11-36) proposes an inversion of the traditional interpretation regarding the testimony of Dicaearchus of Messana about the life of Pythagoras. Since antiquity, Dicaearchus’ reports tend to be seen as positive, because they present a Pythagoras devoid of mysticism and apparently more interested in practical matters.
    [Show full text]
  • A Reading of Porphyry's on Abstinence From
    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA Los Angeles Justice Purity Piety: A Reading of Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Ensouled Beings A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy in Classics by Alexander Press 2020 © Copyright by Alexander Press 2020 ABSTRACT OF THE DISSERTATION Justice Purity Piety: A Reading of Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Ensouled Beings by Alexander Press Doctor of Philosophy in Classics University of California, Los Angeles, 2020 Professor David Blank, Chair Abstract: Presenting a range of arguments against meat-eating, many strikingly familiar, Porphyry’s On Abstinence from Ensouled Beings (Greek Περὶ ἀποχῆς ἐµψύχων, Latin De abstinentia ab esu animalium) offers a sweeping view of the ancient debate concerning animals and their treatment. At the same time, because of its advocacy of an asceticism informed by its author’s Neoplatonism, Abstinence is often taken to be concerned primarily with the health of the human soul. By approaching Abstinence as a work of moral suasion and a work of literature, whose intra- and intertextual resonances yield something more than a collection of propositions or an invitation to Quellenforschung, I aim to push beyond interpretations that bracket the arguments regarding animals as merely dialectical; cast the text’s other-directed principle of justice as wholly ii subordinated to a self-directed principle of purity; or accept as decisive Porphyry’s exclusion of craftsmen, athletes, soldiers, sailors, and orators from his call to vegetarianism.
    [Show full text]
  • Download Date | 6/9/19 10:06 AM Pseudo-Pythagorean Literature 73
    Philologus 2019; 163(1): 72–94 Leonid Zhmud* What is Pythagorean in the Pseudo-Pythagorean Literature? https://doi.org/10.1515/phil-2018-0003 Abstract: This paper discusses continuity between ancient Pythagoreanism and the pseudo-Pythagorean writings, which began to appear after the end of the Pythagorean school ca. 350 BC. Relying on a combination of temporal, formal and substantial criteria, I divide Pseudopythagorica into three categories: 1) early Hellenistic writings (late fourth – late second centuries BC) ascribed to Pytha- goras and his family members; 2) philosophical treatises written mostly, yet not exclusively, in pseudo-Doric from the turn of the first century BC under the names of real or fictional Pythagoreans; 3) writings attributed to Pythagoras and his relatives that continued to appear in the late Hellenistic and Imperial periods. I will argue that all three categories of pseudepigrapha contain astonishingly little that is authentically Pythagorean. Keywords: Pythagoreanism, pseudo-Pythagorean writings, Platonism, Aristote- lianism Forgery has been widespread in time and place and varied in its goals and methods, and it can easily be confused with superficially similar activities. A. Grafton Note: An earlier version of this article was presented at the colloquium “Pseudopythagorica: stratégies du faire croire dans la philosophie antique” (Paris, 28 May 2015). I would like to thank Constantinos Macris (CNRS) for his kind invitation. The final version was written during my fellowship at the IAS of Durham University and presented at the B Club, Cambridge, in Mai 2016. I am grateful to Gábor Betegh for inviting me to give a talk and to the audience for the vivid discussion.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotelian Elements in the Myth of Plutarch's De Facie
    CHAPTER EIGHT ARISTOTELIAN ELEMENTS IN THE MYTH OF PLUTARCH'S DE FACIE As the material dealt with in chapter 7 showed, recovery of the sources of Plutarch's myth in the De facie is a perilous undertaking. Like Plato, Plutarch is first and foremost a creative author of great literary talent who is quite capable of developing and using entirely new motifs in his writings to further his philosophical or literary aims. Where he does not expressly mention his sources, certainty about older authors which he may have used cannot be gained. At the same time it is to be assumed that Plutarch made repeated use of themes and stories found in the literature of his time, which he collected and studied assiduously. As far as Plato's work is concerned, this is borne out by almost every page of Plutarch's writings. Influence is likely in the case of other writers, but difficult to determine because their works have been lost. One thinks of such figures as Speusippus, Xenocrates, Heraclides Ponticus, and Stoics like Posidonius. Matters are even more complicated as far as Aristotle is concerned. Although passages in Plutarch's writings often recall texts from the Corpus Aristotelicum, it cannot be established conclusively that Plutarch drew on them. F. H. Sandbach, on the other hand, has argued strongly that Plutarch had no knowledge of the Corpus and was only acquainted with Aristotle's published work, now lost.1 Where Plutarch does not name his source, however, it is difficult to ascertain what he derived from these published works.
    [Show full text]
  • Women in Early Pythagoreanism
    Women in Early Pythagoreanism Caterina Pellò Faculty of Classics University of Cambridge Clare Hall February 2018 This dissertation is submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Alla nonna Ninni, che mi ha insegnato a leggere e scrivere Abstract Women in Early Pythagoreanism Caterina Pellò The sixth-century-BCE Pythagorean communities included both male and female members. This thesis focuses on the Pythagorean women and aims to explore what reasons lie behind the prominence of women in Pythagoreanism and what roles women played in early Pythagorean societies and thought. In the first chapter, I analyse the social conditions of women in Southern Italy, where the first Pythagorean communities were founded. In the second chapter, I compare Pythagorean societies with ancient Greek political clubs and religious sects. Compared to mainland Greece, South Italian women enjoyed higher legal and socio-political status. Similarly, religious groups included female initiates, assigning them authoritative roles. Consequently, the fact that the Pythagoreans founded their communities in Croton and further afield, and that in some respects these communities resembled ancient sects helps to explain why they opened their doors to the female gender to begin with. The third chapter discusses Pythagoras’ teachings to and about women. Pythagorean doctrines did not exclusively affect the followers’ way of thinking and public activities, but also their private way of living. Thus, they also regulated key aspects of the female everyday life, such as marriage and motherhood. I argue that the Pythagorean women entered the communities as wives, mothers and daughters. Nonetheless, some of them were able to gain authority over their fellow Pythagoreans and engage in intellectual activities, thus overcoming the female traditional domestic roles.
    [Show full text]
  • Heraclides of Pontus 1St Edition Download Free
    HERACLIDES OF PONTUS 1ST EDITION DOWNLOAD FREE Elizabeth Pender | 9781351515955 | | | | | Heraclides Ponticus Chapter 6. During Plato's third trip to Sicily, Heraclides served as head of the Academy and was almost elected its head on the death of Speusippus. Britannica Quiz. Book Description. Used hardcover First. Let us know if you have suggestions to improve this article requires login. Heraclides is a Greek astronomer who proposed that the earth rotates on its axis once a day and who may have believed that Heraclides of Pontus 1st edition sun was the centre of the Heraclides of Pontus 1st edition system. His writings, all lost except for a few fragments, include literary criticism and works on musicology. He wrote on the movements of the planets. The public laws of the state of Rhode-Island and Providence Plantations. Ancient Greek astronomy. He is the author of Aristotle on Emotion and founder of the Theophrastus Project. His interests were diverse. Used fine hardcover. His vast bibliography, which unfortunately does not survive today, spanned the fields of physics, astronomy, metaphysics and meteorology. Heraclides Ponticus. During Plato's third trip to Heraclides of Pontus 1st edition, Heraclides served as head of the Academy and was almost elected its head on the death of ides' interests were : Taylor And Francis. Bernard Bolzano. Eighth Day Books. Interdisciplinary instruction. Seller rating : This seller has earned a 5 of 5 Stars rating from Biblio customers. Learn More. October 22, Biblio is open and shipping orders. The volume contains a new edition of the sources for Heraclides' life and thought. Social Responsibility Did you know that sinceBiblio has used its profits to build 16 public libraries in rural villages of South America? Astronomy and Space Quiz.
    [Show full text]
  • GREEK MUSIC. the General Conviction That the True
    GREEK MUSIC. THE general conviction that the true nature of ancient Greek music is practically incomprehensible in modern times arises from many causes, of which the most potent are:— 1. That hitherto all explanations have been based on the extant formal treatises, which deal either with the decadent elaborations of solo cithara- playing, or the purely theoretical calculations of the self-styled Pythagorean school, which latter professedly despised the actual performance of music. 2. The attempts to elucidate the subject make no allowance for the fact that the extant specimens of noted music extend over a period of at least eight centuries, and no one explanation is likely to fit either the whole of these or the casual references to music to be found in general Greek literature. 3. Thanks mainly to Aristoxenus, the modern mind has become so permeated by the quarter-tone theory of the enharmonic genus, that even so simple a record as the celebrated Euripides fragment has been generally interpreted as involving this minute interval. The arguments against this theory, at least as regards vocal music, are weighty and almost conclusive ; but their full development requires more space than is available here. This article is an attempt to summarise the main conclusions arrived at from a careful consideration of authenticated history, the representations of musical instruments, the complete notation, and the casual references to music of various Greek writers, especially Plato, Aristotle, and Plutarch. It is manifestly impossible to give the authority for each statement, but a few of the more important references will be given.
    [Show full text]
  • The Celestial Eschatology and Its Transformations
    CHAPrERFIVE THE CELESTIAL ESCHATOLOGY AND ITS TRANSFORMATIONS Plato has removed the Isles of the Blessed to somewhere in the sky, according to the presuppositions of his ontology and cosmology: what is lower is coarser, the elements are ranged on a vertical scale from gross ( earth, water) to finer (air, aether, starry fire). However, after death, only the souls of the righteous have the privilege of abiding at the earth's surface, or even higher, in close vicinity to the eternal ideas. Moreover, neither the staying on the True Earth, nor the contemplation of the hyperuranian essences are in all cases supposed to be everlasting. For smaller merits, they last only for a definite period of time, after which the soul must choose again an incarnation on the earth. After judgement, the soul of the Unjust goes to the underground Hell, where the generally verticallity of Plato's system is again respected:the worse the soul, the deeper she goes into the bowels of the earth, and the worst of all, those of the tyrants and criminals, go down into the deepest region of the Tartarus. King Ardiaeus, for instance, had been sentenced to a punishment of that kind. We have already mentioned many times that Plato's legacy has had the tendency to transfer the underground Hell to the sky. As for the author of this transformation, opinions vary, but many scholars believe that Heraclides Ponticus would be the most likely candidate. Heraclides Ponticus, born at Heraclea on the Pontus between 388-373, frequented the Academy in 364 or before.
    [Show full text]
  • Επιστημονικό Περιοδικό Papyri - Scientific Journal Δέλτοι Delti Τόμος 4, 2015 Volume 4, 2015 [email protected] ΠΕΡΙΕΧΟΜΕΝΑ TABLE of CONTENTS
    ΑΚΑΔΗΜΙΑ ΘΕΣΜΩΝ ΚΑΙ ΠΟΛΙΤΙΣΜΩΝ ACADEMY OF INSTITUTIONS AND CULTURES Πᾶσά τε ἐπιστήμη χωριζομένη δικαιοσύνης καὶ τῆς ἄλλης ἀρετῆς πανουργία, οὐ σοφία φαίνεται. Πλάτωνος, “Μενέξενος”, [246e – 247a]. And every form of knowledge when sundered from justice and the rest of virtue is seen to be plain roguery rather than wisdom. Plato, “Menexenus”, [246e – 247a]. Plato. Platonis Opera, ed. John Burnet. Oxford University Press. 1903 Πάπυροι - Επιστημονικό Περιοδικό Δέλτοι τόμος 4, 2015 Papyri - Scientific Journal Delti volume 4, 2015 ΘΕΣΣΑΛΟΝΙΚΗ 2015 - THESSALONIKI 2015 ISSN : 2241-5106 ISSN : 2241-5106 Τίτλος : Πάπυροι - Επιστημονικό Περιοδικό Δέλτοι τόμος 4, 2015 Publication Name : Papyri - Scientific Journal Delti volume 4, 2015 Εκδότης : ΑΚΑΔΗΜΙΑ ΘΕΣΜΩΝ ΚΑΙ ΠΟΛΙΤΙΣΜΩΝ Publisher : ACADEMY OF INSTITUTIONS AND CULTURES Copyright © ΑΚΑΔΗΜΙΑ ΘΕΣΜΩN ΚΑΙ ΠΟΛΙΤΙΣΜΩΝ ACADEMY OF INSTITUTIONS AND CULTURES Έτος : 2015, Θεσσαλονίκη Year : 2015, Thessaloniki, Macedonia Hellas Web site : www.academy.edu.gr Email : [email protected] Σχεδιασμός και επιμέλεια έκδοσης : Γεώργιος Ελ. Κούρταλης Design Issue and custody : Georgios El. Kourtalis ΑΚΑΔΗΜΙΑ ΘΕΣΜΩΝ ΚΑΙ ΠΟΛΙΤΙΣΜΩΝ ACADEMY OF INSTITUTIONS AND CULTURES , . …. ΧΘΟρώΥΚμΥεΔθΙΔαΟ Υγ,ὰΙσρτ οπροίαλ ιττουε ίΠᾳε ολοὐπ οζνηνληοσύιασκοῃύ τ ποοὺλέςμ τοῶυ,νΕ πιτέάλφαιςο ςν,ό [2.37.1]μους παράδειγμα δὲ μᾶλλον αὐτοὶ ὄντες τισὶν ἢ μιμούμενοι ἑτέρους καὶ ὄνομα μὲν διὰ τὸ μὴ ἐς ὀλίγους ἀλλ᾽ ἐς πλείονας οἰκεῖν δημοκρατία κέκληται Πάπυροι – Επιστημονικό Περιοδικό Π σά τε πιστήμη χωριζομένη δικαιοσύνης κα τ ς λλης ρετ ς πανουργία, ο σοφία φαίνεται. Πλάτων, “Μενέξενος”, [246 e – 247a]. ᾶ ἐ ὶ ῆ ἄ ἀ ῆ ὐ Εκδότης: ΑΚΑΔΗΜΙΑ ΘΕΣΜΩΝ ΚΑΙ ΠΟΛΙΤΙΣΜΩΝ Ταχυδρομική Διεύθυνση: Αριστοτέλειο Πανεπιστήμιο Θεσσαλονίκης, Τ.Κ. 54124, Θεσσαλονίκη, Ελλάς, Τ.Θ. 494 του Α.Π.Θ.
    [Show full text]
  • Research and Experiment in Early Greek Thought by Tyler Mayo A
    Research and Experiment in Early Greek Thought by Tyler Mayo A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Classical Studies) in the University of Michigan 2019 Doctoral Committee: Professor Francesca Schironi, Chair Professor Sara Ahbel-Rappe Professor Richard Janko Associate Professor Ian Moyer Tyler Edward Mayo [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0002-2442-7127 To my mother and father ii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS First, ad consuetudinem maiorum, I would like to begin by acknowledging and expressing my gratitude to the members of my committee: Professors Richard Janko, Ian Moyer, and Sara Abhel-Rappe. Their suggestions and criticisms helped me to rethink some, and alter other, points within this dissertation to its improvement, and saved me from numerous errors within the text, many of which surely still lurk within these pages and are my responsibility alone. However, I owe a special debt to my chair, Francesca Schironi, whose support not only made this dissertation possible, but who acted as a mentor throughout my entire time at Michigan. Her honesty and counsel were always welcome, and her careful philology can be seen within these pages, although I fear only as an imperfect reflection. Outside Angell Hall, others made my studies in Ann Arbor possible. The Posch family— John, Dyanna, Isabel, and most recently, Jude—acted as a family away from home, not least for their generous hospitality in boarding me. I shall always remember and cherish their ξενία. My wife Liz is certainly owed a place of honor in the beginning of this dissertation. Her support was essential in its creation as in all other things.
    [Show full text]
  • Zartaloudis (University of Kent) and Anton Schütz (Birkbeck College, University of London)
    Encounters in Law and Philosophy ENCOUNTERS IN LAW AND PHILOSOPHY S T A S I SERIES EDITORS: Thanos Zartaloudis (University of Kent) and S C Anton Schütz (Birkbeck College, University of London). i v i l This series interrogates, historically and theoretically, the encounters W a r Thanos between philosophy and law. Each volume published takes a unique a s approach and challenges traditional approaches to law and philosophy. a P o l i t i c A new contribution to Agamben’s continuing a ZARTALOUDIS l P genealogy of power a r a d i In this inaugural volume of the Encounters in Law and Philosophy g m series, Giorgio Agamben focuses upon the on-going warfare European THE BIRTH state power has waged against its most malignant enemy: civil war itself. The survival of the State is seen to depend on its ability to preserve the OF NOMOS political community from factional enmity. Agamben first investigates the Athenian theme of ‘Stasis’ – the city’s struggle against internal G I revolt – before turning to a new reading of Hobbes’s Leviathan and its O approach to the peril of the commonwealth’s exposure to civil strife, R G division and revolution. I O At the heart of this book is the issue of state powers in their A G continuous decline – an issue that is key to the renewal of political, A M philosophical and legal thought. B E N Giorgio Agamben is one of the most vigorous thinkers of our time. He is best known for his recent Homo Sacer series of publications interrogating power and biopolitics.
    [Show full text]