Joseph Agassi Technology: Philosophical and Social Aspects

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Joseph Agassi Technology: Philosophical and Social Aspects Joseph Agassi Technology: Philosophical and Social Aspects REVISED EDITION 2 Joseph Agassi © Joseph Agassi, 1985, 2005 Technology 3 For Pozzi Escot and Robert Cogan 4 Joseph Agassi TABLE OF CONTENTS EDITORIAL PREFACE xi PREFACE xiii ACKNOWLEDGEMENT xix INTRODUCTION 1 1. Control in General 1 2. Democratic Control in General 4 PART ONE : TECHNOLOGY AND CULTURE INTRODUCTION TO PART ONE 10 CHAPTER 1: TECHNOLOGY AND LEARNING 11 1. Technology and Science 11 2. Technology as Non-Cumulative 16 3. The Task of Defining Technology 21 4. Education for Technological Society 26 5. Concluding Remarks 31 CHAPTER 2: TECHNOLOGY AND ART 32 1. Assurance 32 2. Intuition 37 3. Repetition 40 4. Social Technology 50 5. Concluding Remarks 50 CHAPTER 3: TECHNOLOGY AND SOCIETY 52 1. Is Democracy Really Necessary? 52 2. Long-Range Large-Scale Technological Projects 55 3. Short-Range Cybernetics 64 4. The Ugly Face of Technological Bureaucracy 71 5. Concluding Remarks 76 PART TWO : TECHNOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY INTRODUCTION TO PART TWO 78 CHAPTER 4: MAGICAL AND SCIENTIFIC TECHNOLOGY 79 1. From the Scientific Point of View: Baconianism 79 Technology 5 2. From the Anthropological Point of View: Functionalism 83 3. From the Metaphysical Point of View: Fideism 87 4. From a Historical Point of View: The Scientific Revolution 92 5. Concluding Remarks 95 CHAPTER 5: THE IDEAL OF RATIONAL MAN 97 1. The Baconian-Cartesian Ideal 97 2. Idealizations versus Ideals 102 3. The Education of Rational Man 108 4. The Individualism of Rational Man 112 5. Concluding Remarks 115 CHAPTER 6: THE PRAGMATIST MESS OF POTTAGE 117 1. The Theory and Practice of Toleration 117 2. The Philosophical Foundations of Tolerance 121 3. The Definition of Truth 125 4. Truth as Ideal 128 5. Concluding Remarks 133 CHAPTER 7: PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR TECHNOLOGY 135 1. Philosophy of Life 135 2. Traditional Philosophy 140 3. Pragmatist Philosophy of Science 144 4. Pragmatism and Meaning 147 5. Concluding Remarks 151 CHAPTER 8: CONTEMPLATIVE PHILOSOPHY AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR TECHNOLOGY 152 1. Science and Rational Technology 152 2. Repeatability versus Reliability 157 3. Science and Common Sense 160 4. Metaphysical Frameworks 164 5. Concluding Remarks 169 CHAPTER 9: SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR TECHNOLOGY 171 1. Reductionism in Action 171 2. Error, Sin, and Optimism 176 3. Social Theory and Social Action 181 4. The Social Framework of Science and Technology 186 5. Concluding Remarks 190 6 Joseph Agassi CHAPTER 10: POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY AND ITS IMPLICATIONS FOR TECHNOLOGY 191 1. The Justification of Politics in Action 191 2. The Political Ineptness of Contemporary Liberals 196 3. Political Theory and Political Action 202 4. The Technocrat as a Frankenstein 205 5. Concluding Remarks 207 PART THREE : TOWARDS A CRITICAL PRAXEOLOGY INTRODUCTION TO PART THREE 212 CHAPTER 11: AN IMAGE OF A BETTER FUTURE 213 1. Towards a Theory of Practical Problems 213 2. Democracy, Dialogue, and Responsibility 219 3. An Image of a Half-Way Utopia 225 4. An Image of a Peaceful World 230 5. Concluding Remarks 233 CHAPTER 12: TECHNIQUES OF RAPID DEMOCRATIZATION 234 1. Sociotechnics and Technoethics 234 2. Towards a Theory of Research Incentives and Assessment 239 3. Towards a Theory of Democratic Mass-Movements 244 4. Towards a Theory of Responsible Democratic Leadership 250 5. Concluding Remarks 258 END NOTES 260 NAME INDEX 262 SUBJECT INDEX 266 Technology 7 EDITORIAL PREFACE This is a distinguished contribution to the philosophy and sociol- ogy of technology by one of the pioneers in these fields. The latter are comparatively new and they are not being cultivated vigorously enough. This is surprising given that technology, together with capital, was the motor of the industrial revolution that started in mid 18th century and that may never be completed. The neglect of the philosophy and sociology of technology seems to be due to three major factors. One is that many scholars confuse technology with science, so that when dealing with ei- ther of them they believe to have taken care of the other as well. A second reason is that most scholars do not realize the conceptual richness of technology: they do not understand that, unlike the traditional crafts, modern technology presupposes science and involves research, design, and planning, all of which pose intriguing conceptual problems. A third reason for the neglect is the traditional contempt of the scholar for every- thing that smells of manual work. This situation has started to change over the past few years, partly under the influence of Professor Agassi’s numerous writings and those of a few other scholars who have explained that technology presupposes and raises a number of interesting philosophical problems, and that technolo- gists, unlike basic scientists, are accountable to both their employers and the public at large. In fact, the philosophy and sociology of technology are expanding quickly. There are professional societies and periodicals devoted to them, and an estimated 2000 courses on science, technology and society are currently being taught around the world. A major problem faced by any teacher or student of a course in the philosophy and sociology of technology is the dearth of good text- books on the subject. The present work, a product of two decades of re- search and teaching on three continents, is a suitable textbook for any course on the philosophical and sociological aspects of technology. It covers an extensive ground in a clear and concise manner, and without using professional jargon. Agassi’s book gives us a faithful and clear picture of contempo- rary technology as both a product of human ingenuity and a powerful means for altering the world - for better or worse. It is also an eloquent plea for the democratic control of technology, a cultural force that, though ambivalent, is never socially neutral. MARIO BUNGE Foundations Philosophy of Science Unit, McGill University, Montreal 8 Joseph Agassi PREFACE The progress of man by the education of the mind - there is no safety but in that. Vic tor Hugo, “The Mind and the Masses” All societies have technology and control it by diverse means and with the aid of diverse social and political institutions. The eighteenth century thinkers of the Enlightenment movement considered technology as a peculiarly high form of applied natural science and disregarded all tradition, including, incidentally, many traditional social controls of tech- nology. Adam Smith expressed the spirit of the age when he said, entre- preneurs should control the machines they own, not the government; the control of production as a whole should be effected by the individual con- sumers through the open market. In the nineteenth-century, thinkers of the Reaction to the Enlightenment movement emphasized the ill effects which industrialization causes, and called for the maintenance of tradi- tions and of communal life. Karl Marx expressed the view, which soon became more influential than those of most modern thinkers, that the technological stage of development of a society is the sole basic determi- nant of its social and political structures. In recent years, a new view is emerging, to the elaboration of which the present volume is devoted, which presents social and physical technology as strongly interacting to varying degrees of satisfaction. To achieve a satisfactory man-machine integration we need a new technology - which should coordinate and harmonize social and physical technology. Technologies, especially agrarian, have destroyed societies that could not control them well enough. Today technology threatens to de- stroy the human race. This is why the task of the new technology is both so important and so urgent. The bias of the present book is frankly political: we have to im- plement a drastic change in our policy towards the implementation of technology, and center less on the physical and more on the socia l side of technology: we should prefer the change of the organization of a system to the introduction of a new piece of machinery. And we should study the social side effects of technological innovation and decide whether they are desirable or not, and if not, what to do about it. Such decisions are political, and the chief political question is, what political machinery should exercise such controls. The political bias of the present book is frankly democratic: it opts for democratic control and, moreover, for a broad public participa- tion in the political process. The major task thus posed to us, before it is Technology 9 too late - .if it is not too late already - .is that of democratization. The democratization bias of the present book is, finally, educa- tional: there is no short-cut that circumvents education. Indeed, the major contribution of technology from time immemorial is that of creating more leisure time and more opportunities that are educational. All anti-technological schools of thought are here opposed as re- actionary and as impractical. We need new technologies to help us fight the ills of the extant technologies. We can use the means of mass com- munication to create mass movements and use these as means for rapid mass education for democracy and as means for pressure on legislatures to enact new means of democratic controls of technologies. Once we see democracy as the process of increased participation of citizens in the political process through education, we cannot fail to realize that the dissemination of political knowledge and information is essential to democracy and so calls for institutionalization - .of both the dissemination of information and of democratic control of it. This leads us to perceive at once the terrible crisis in contemporary political life, the credibility gap so-called, the popularity of the view that one cannot suc- ceed in politics without being a liar.
Recommended publications
  • Michael Polanyi and Early Neoliberalism
    MICHAEL POLANYI AND EARLY NEOLIBERALISM Martin Beddeleem Keywords: Friedrich Hayek, Louis Rougier, Michael Polanyi, Mont-Pèlerin Society, neoliberalism, planning, Walter Lippmann ABSTRACT1 Between the late 1930s and the 1950s, Michael Polanyi came in close contact with a diverse cast of intellectuals seeking a renewal of the liberal doctrine. The elaboration of this “neoliberalism” happened through a transnational collaboration between economists, philosophers, and social theorists, united in their rejection of central planning. Defining a common agenda for this “early neoliberalism” offered an opportunity to discard the old laissez-faire doctrine and restore a supervisory role of the state. Ultimately, post-war dissensions regarding the direction of these efforts led Polanyi away from the neoliberal core. Between the publication of his pamphlet on the failures of economic planning in the Soviet Union in 1936 (CF, 61-95) and that of The Logic of Liberty in 1951, Michael Polanyi progressively lost interest in chemistry and started to investigate the political and sociological conditions necessary to scientific freedom and the pursuit of truth. During that time, he became involved with a group of scholars who, equally, perceived the democratic collapse of Europe as a wake-up call for a restatement of its liberal tradition. Whereas the values of individual dignity and social progress that liber- alism carried were needed then more than ever, they agreed that the method to achieve these ideals had become obsolete. Therefore, they focused their efforts on revamping a science of liberalism, which could answer the scientific claims of plannism and totalitar- ian ideologies. Tradition & Discovery: The Journal of the Polanyi Society 45:3 © 2019 by the Polanyi Society 31 For two decades, Michael Polanyi took part in the inception and the consolida- tion of “early neoliberalism” (Schulz-Forberg 2018; Beddeleem 2019), a period that predates the later development of neoliberalism from the 1960s onwards.
    [Show full text]
  • The Method of Antinomies: Oakeshott and Others Others and Oakeshott Antinomies: of Method the VOLUME 6 | ISSUE 1 + 2 2018 6 | ISSUE VOLUME
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Philosophy Faculty Publications Philosophy 2018 The ethoM d of Antinomies: Oakeshott nda Others Stephen Turner University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/phi_facpub Scholar Commons Citation Turner, Stephen, "The eM thod of Antinomies: Oakeshott nda Others" (2018). Philosophy Faculty Publications. 309. https://scholarcommons.usf.edu/phi_facpub/309 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Method of Antinomies: Oakeshott and Others STEPHEN TURNER Email: [email protected] Web: http://philosophy.usf.edu/faculty/sturner/ Abstract: Michael Oakeshott employed a device of argument and analysis that appears in a number of other thinkers, where it is given the name “antinomies.” These differ from binary oppositions or contradictories in that the two poles are bound to- gether. In this discussion, the nature of this binding is explored in detail, in large part in relation to Oakeshott’s own usages, such as his discussion of the relation of faith and skepticism, between collective goal-oriented associations and those based on contract, and between a legal regime based on neutral rules and one oriented to policy goals . Other examples might include Weber’s distinction between the politics of intention and the politics of responsibility. Moreover, such ambiguous concepts as “rights,” have antinomic interpretations. In each of these cases, the full realization of one ideal led, in practice, to consequenc- es associated with the other: in political practice, neither polar ideal was realizable without concessions to the other.
    [Show full text]
  • Robert Heineman: Authority and the Liberal Tradition: Study Guide
    Scholars Crossing Faculty Publications and Presentations Helms School of Government 2003 Robert Heineman: Authority and the Liberal Tradition: Study Guide Steven Alan Samson Liberty University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.liberty.edu/gov_fac_pubs Part of the Other Social and Behavioral Sciences Commons, Political Science Commons, and the Public Affairs, Public Policy and Public Administration Commons Recommended Citation Samson, Steven Alan, "Robert Heineman: Authority and the Liberal Tradition: Study Guide" (2003). Faculty Publications and Presentations. 233. https://digitalcommons.liberty.edu/gov_fac_pubs/233 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Helms School of Government at Scholars Crossing. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications and Presentations by an authorized administrator of Scholars Crossing. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ROBERT HEINEMAN: AUTHORITY AND THE LIBERAL TRADITION: STUDY GUIDE, 2001-2003 Steven Alan Samson Introduction Commentary and Study Questions The author's thesis may be summarized as follows: "Contemporary American liberalism is incapable of supporting for any sustained period of time a government that acts with firmness and coherent direction." Several implications are immediately drawn. Others may be inferred. Liberalism has promoted a "tremendous expansion of government within the past several decades," resulting in a "government lacking in authority and direction." One inference is that our political means (the sophisticated apparatus and process of government) outstrip the political ends (the substantive human purposes) they are supposed to serve. Remember Rushdoony's inescapable concepts]. Sometimes political programs are established for no better reason than that they can be.
    [Show full text]
  • "The New Non-Science of Politics: on Turns to History in Polltical Sciencen
    "The New Non-Science of Politics: On Turns to History in Polltical Sciencen Rogers Smith CSST Working CRSO Working Paper #59 Paper #449 October 1990 The New Non-Science of Politics : On Turns to Historv in Political Science Prepared for the CSST Conference on "The Historic Turn in the Human Sciences" Oct. 5-7, 1990 Ann Arbor, Michigan Rogers M. Smith Department of Political Science Yale University August, 1990 The New Non-Science of Po1itic.s Rogers M. Smit-h Yale University I. Introducticn. The canon of major writings on politics includes a considerable number that claim to offer a new science of politics, or a new science of man that encompasses politics. Arlc,totle, Hobbos, Hume, Publius, Con~te,Bentham, Hegel, Marx, Spencer, Burgess, Bentley, Truman, East.on, and Riker are amongst the many who have clairr,ed, more or less directly, that they arc founding or helping to found a true palitical science for the first tlme; and the rccent writcrs lean heavily on the tcrni "science. "1 Yet very recently, sorno of us assigned the title "political scien:iSt" havc been ti-il-ning returning to act.ivities that many political scientist.^, among others, regard as unscientific--to the study of instituti~ns, usually in historical perspective, and to historica! ~a'lternsand processes more broadly. Some excellent scholars belie-ve this turn is a disast.er. It has been t.ernlod a "grab bag of diverse, often conf!icting approaches" that does not offer anything iike a scientific theory (~kubband Moe, 1990, p. 565) .2 In this essay I will argue that the turn or return t.o institutions and history is a reasonable response to two linked sets of probicms.
    [Show full text]
  • Fighting for the Mantle of Science: the Epistemological Foundations of Neoliberalism, 1931-1951
    Université de Montréal Fighting for the Mantle of Science: The Epistemological Foundations of Neoliberalism, 1931-1951 par Martin Beddeleem Département de science politique Faculté des arts et des sciences Thèse présentée en vue de l’obtention du grade de Philosophiæ Doctor (Ph.D.) en science politique Décembre 2017 © Martin Beddeleem, 2017 RÉSUMÉ Cette thèse examine la genèse intellectuelle du néolibéralisme au prisme de son épistémologie. Elle interroge le développement de ses arguments concernant la production et la diffusion de la connaissance, guidée par l’hypothèse que la formulation d’une position épistémologique commune a été cruciale pour la consolidation de son programme idéologique. Je propose que le néolibéralisme, en provoquant une rupture avec le libéralisme classique, a opéré un recodage des principes libéraux à l’intérieur d’un cadre épistémologique basé sur le conventionnalisme, à l’aide de prémisses tirées des sciences naturelles, de la théorie économique, et de la philosophie des sciences. Afin d’obtenir un panorama contextuel de son émergence, cette thèse fournit une reconstruction des débats intellectuels des années 1930 en Angleterre sur deux plans principaux : le débat sur la planification de la science, et celui sur la planification de l’économie. Dans un climat propice aux idées planistes, perçues comme davantage rationnelles et scientifiques, les néolibéraux précoces s’attelèrent à montrer la portée limitée de la science positive pour orienter les décisions politiques. La montée du totalitarisme contribua à donner à leur discours une urgence singulière, puisqu’il expliquait le recours au collectivisme étatique par la prégnance d’opinions scientifiques erronées. Pendant la Seconde Guerre mondiale, la formation d’un réseau néolibéral déclencha une fertilisation croisée entre ces différents penseurs, dont l’agenda commun avait été défini au moment du Colloque Walter-Lippmann en 1938.
    [Show full text]
  • Crises of Modernity’ Discourses and the Rise of Financial Technologies in a Contested Mechanized World
    Philos. Technol. DOI 10.1007/s13347-017-0255-5 RESEARCH ARTICLE Open Access ‘Crises of Modernity’ Discourses and the Rise of Financial Technologies in a Contested Mechanized World Marinus Ossewaarde1 Received: 29 April 2016 /Accepted: 26 February 2017 # The Author(s) 2017. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract The aim of this article is to provide a discussion of scholarly ‘crisis of modernity’ discourses that have developed in the field of social philosophy. Re- visiting past and present discourses can be illuminating in at least three ways: it can reveal the broader picture of the present financialized and technologized world and the rise of financial technologies; it can provide scholars with new vocabularies, concepts, and metaphors to comprehend present-day phenomena and developments; and it can reveal the variety of commitments that are possible, today, too. This article starts with a discussion of the original ‘crisis of modernity’ discourses (avant la lettre), in which the clashing arguments of Comte and Tocqueville are featured, and a discussion of a second ‘crisis of modernity’ that developed in the context of the ‘Great Depression.’ Athird‘crisis of modernity’ discourse emerged in the wake of the financial crises of the 1970s. Such crises are still ongoing and discussed within the boundaries of the third ‘crisis of modernity’ discourse. How financial technologies do and do not fit within this third discourse is discussed in the remainder of this article. Keywords Crisis . Democracy. Financialization . Financial technologies . Ideology. Mechanization modernity discourses 1 Introduction In discourses on the ‘crises of modernity’ during the past two centuries, technology is an important theme for philosophical reflection.
    [Show full text]
  • Nine Lives of Neoliberalism
    A Service of Leibniz-Informationszentrum econstor Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre Make Your Publications Visible. zbw for Economics Plehwe, Dieter (Ed.); Slobodian, Quinn (Ed.); Mirowski, Philip (Ed.) Book — Published Version Nine Lives of Neoliberalism Provided in Cooperation with: WZB Berlin Social Science Center Suggested Citation: Plehwe, Dieter (Ed.); Slobodian, Quinn (Ed.); Mirowski, Philip (Ed.) (2020) : Nine Lives of Neoliberalism, ISBN 978-1-78873-255-0, Verso, London, New York, NY, https://www.versobooks.com/books/3075-nine-lives-of-neoliberalism This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/215796 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Terms of use: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. personal and scholarly purposes. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle You are not to copy documents for public or commercial Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, If the documents have been made available under an Open gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort Content Licence (especially Creative
    [Show full text]
  • University of Nevada Reno the Loss of the Philosophic Tradition and The
    University of Nevada Reno The Loss of the Philosophic Tradition and the Rise of the Positive Philosophy of Auguste Comte A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Political Science by Diana Jonmarie Dr. John Marini / Dissertation Advisor May, 2015 Copyright by Diana Jonmarie 2015 All Rights Reserved UNIVERSITY OF NEVADA THE GRADUATE SCHOOL RENO We recommend that the dissertation prepared under our supervision by DIANA JONMARIE entitled The Loss of the Philosophic Tradition and The Rise of the Positive Philosophy of Auguste Comte be accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY John Marini, Ph.D., Advisor Eric Herzik, Ph.D., Committee Member Robert Dickens, Ph.D., Committee Member Neal Ferguson, Ph.D., Committee Member Barbara Walker, Ph.D., Graduate School Representative David W. Zeh, Ph.D., Dean, Graduate School May, 2015 i ABSTRACT This study examines the loss of original principles that distinguish ancient Western philosophy as a valid conceptual framework for political theory and practice. I explore how the Philosophic Tradition as a centuries-old foundation of inquiry and discourse loses its significance and finally its authority in the postmodern world. With the exclusion of metaphysical reflection and reason as a basis for understanding human existential and political phenomena, the transition to Historicism and Philosophic Positivism effectively redefined the nature and application of politics. Critical to this research and serving as a focal point of this study are the works of theorist and originator of the Positive Philosophy, Auguste Comte. I analyze the author‘s several volumes, these dedicated to establishing a new foundation of political thought, one in which scientific inquiry would serve as the ground for seeking truth and knowledge and as a basis for methodologically directing social and political reorganization.
    [Show full text]
  • Rationalism in Public Law
    Graham Gee and Grégoire C. N. Webber Rationalism in public Law Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Gee, Graham and Webber, Grégoire C. N. (2013) Rationalism in public Law. Modern Law Review, 76 (4). pp. 708-734. ISSN 0026-7961 DOI: 10.1111/1468-2230.12031 © 2013 The Authors This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/47608/ Available in LSE Research Online: August 2014 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final accepted version of the journal article. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. Rationalism in Public Law Graham Gee * and Grégoire Webber ** (2013) 76 Modern Law Review 708 Abstract Rationalism is ‘the stylistic criterion of all respectable politics’. So lamented political philosopher Michael Oakeshott in a series of essays published in the 1940s and 1950s. Rationalism, for Oakeshott, is shorthand for a propensity to prioritise the universal over the local, the uniform over the particular and, ultimately, principle over practice.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 9 an Early Attempt to Turn Philosophy and Technology Into
    Technè 10:2 Winter 2006 Special Issue: Durbin, In Search of Discourse Synthesis/87 Chapter 9 An Early Attempt to Turn Philosophy and Technology into Philosophy of Technology: Joseph Pitt According to his own web account, Joseph Pitt has research interests in history and philosophy of science and technology, with an emphasis on the impact of technologies on scientific change. He was founding editor of the journal, Perspectives on Science: Philosophical, Historical, Social, published by MIT Press. His historical interests include Galileo, Hume, and American pragmatism. He is author of several books and numerous articles in the history and philosophy of science and technology. Recent books, for example, include: The Production and Diffusion of Public Choice: Reflections on the VPI Center, co-edited with Dhavad Saleh-Isfahani and Douglas Eckel (2003), and Thinking about Technology (2000). I will focus on the latter, as well as a set of critiques of that book that I edited for the SPT electronic journal, Techné. After four presidents of SPT—Mitcham, Michalos, Shrader-Frechette, and Wartofsky—to which I have added Bunge, Margolis, Agassi, and Byrne; and after four international meetings: Bad Homburg in (then West) Germany, New York City, Twente in the Netherlands, and Blacksburg, Virginia (Pitt was host there), and proceedings volumes for each of these—after all of that, Pitt was still not satisfied. In what we have seen so far, the early years had covered most of anybody's philosophical spectrum: metaphysics (Mitcham), the social responsibilities of technically trained experts (Michalos), ethical and philosophy of science analyses of particular expert projects (Shrader-Frechette), Marxism (Wartofsky), a systems/exact philosophy analysis of technology (Bunge), a philosophy of technology closely linked to major figures in analytical philosophy (Margolis), social-movement activism (Agassi), and a workers’ perspective for technological society (Byrne).
    [Show full text]
  • Michael Polanyi and Karl Popper: the Fraying of a Long-Standing Acquaintance Struan Jacobs and Phil Mullins
    Michael Polanyi and Karl Popper: The Fraying of a Long-Standing Acquaintance Struan Jacobs and Phil Mullins ABSTRACT Key Words: Michael Polanyi and Karl Popper, critical rationalism and post-critical philosophy, Popper’s open society and Polanyi’s dynamic orders. Based upon archival correspondence and their publications, this essay analyzes the interaction of Karl Popper and Michael Polanyi. Popper sent Polanyi for review in 1932 an early draft of The Logic of Discovery. Friedrich Hayek helped both Polanyi and Popper publish some of their writings in the forties. Polanyi renewed his acquaintance with Popper in the late forties when Popper took a position at the London School of Economics and they met to discuss common interests. In the early fifties, as Polanyi prepared and presented his Gifford Lectures and published The Logic of Liberty, Polanyi became increasingly clear and articulate in distinguishing his social philosophy and philosophy of science from Popper’s ideas. Polanyi’s 1952 paper “The Stability of Belief” forthrightly presented Polanyi’s post-critical ideas that Popper overtly rejected in an important letter. After this, they had little to do with each other. I. Introduction1 In the books and essays of Michael Polanyi, there are only a handful of references to Karl Popper; likewise, in Popper’s books and essays, there are only a few references to Polanyi. Most of the references in each figure’s later writings are pointedly critical, although sometimes veiled and cryptic, as the following examples show. There is an unnamed
    [Show full text]
  • Ten Paradoxes of Technology
    Ten Paradoxes of Technology Andrew Feenberg [draft: not for distribution] The “Prologue” to this book is based on articles published in sev- eral Chinese business journals. The interest in Chinese business circles Preface in Western technology studies is significant, however marginal at pre- sent. China is the poster child for standard development strategies de- In recent years, the industrial revolution has gone global in a big spite increasingly visible catastrophic side-effects. Critique may yet way. The so-called “postindustrial society” has “made in China” writ- play a role in encouraging the necessary correctives. ten all over it. Rates of growth in major undeveloped countries have The first chapter is an expanded version of a lecture delivered in skyrocketed as they take over manufacturing for the entire world. But 2009 in Brasilia to the international conference of the Social Technol- the results are far from reassuring. The dark side of all this progress is ogy Network. The Social Technology Network addresses the limita- increasing inequality and environmental crisis. tions of neo-liberal development strategies with new ideas adapted to These facts form the context for the growing interest in the study the situation of the tens of millions of the excluded. The lecture chal- of technology in the developing world. Awareness that standard strate- lenged standard views of technology with ten “paradoxes” reflecting gies of development are not working for everyone suggests possibilities what we have learned in recent years in science and technology studies that go well beyond environmental protection and banking regulation. and philosophy of technology. The social constructivist turn in technol- We can begin to imagine a better and more purposeful design of mod- ogy studies lies in the background of this lecture.
    [Show full text]