Triangles, Tropes, and Τὰ Τοιαʋ̃τα: a Platonic Trope Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Triangles, Tropes, and Τὰ Τοιαʋ̃τα: a Platonic Trope Theory CHRISTOPHER BUCKELS | 9 Triangles, Tropes, and τὰ τοιαʋ ̃τα: A Platonic Trope Theory Christopher Buckels University of California [email protected] ABSTRACT A standard interpretation of Plato’s metaphys- ics holds that sensible particulars are images of Forms. Such particulars are fairly indepen- dent, like Aristotelian substances. I argue that this is incorrect: Platonic particulars are not Form images but aggregates of Form images, which are property-instances (tropes). Timaeus 49e-50a focuses on “this-suches” (toiauta) and even goes so far as to claim that they compose other things. I argue that Form images are this- suches, which are tropes. I also examine the geometrical account, showing that the geomet- rical constituents of the elements are also Form images. Thus everything in the sensible world is composed of tropes. Keywords : Particulars; Tropes; Plato; Timaeus; Substance; Metaphysics; Greek Philosophy https://doi.org/10.14195/2183-4105_18_1 10 | Triangles, Tropes, and τὰ τοιαʋ ̃τα: A Platonic Trope Theory 1. INTRODUCTION will explain and defend the second syllogism (which may be understood as laying out a con­ In the Timaeus, Plato offers an account sequence of the first syllogism), and the fourth of the world whereby macroscopic physical part will consider objections. As will become objects are composed of microscopic three­ clear in the paper, I take Timaeus’ metaphysics ­dimensional objects, which are, in turn, of particulars to be a version of a trope theory, composed of two­‑dimensional objects. Most, and so I take τὰ τοιαῦτα to be tropes, but I will if not all, properties of macroscopic objects are defend this claim in the fourth part; I will also explained by properties of microscopic objects, consider the traditional account of particulars which are in turn explained by the configu­ in the Timaeus whereby Form images are bod­ ration of two­‑dimensional objects. We seem ies (i.e., physical objects) rather than tropes. to have a completely reductionist, naturalist Let me begin by giving an initial character­ account of the world; why, then, is it accompa­ ization of a Platonic trope theory. Tropes are nied by supernatural entities such as Platonic often used to avoid commitment to universals; Forms? While I will explain why Forms are the universal or Form Whiteness, for example, crucial for the account of particulars in the could be the set of all whiteness tropes. Most Timaeus, I will be focusing not on Forms, but trope theories, therefore, are nominalist theo­ on sensible particulars, the three­‑dimensional ries. Timaeus is not, of course, a trope nomi­ objects we bump into on a day­‑to­‑day basis, nalist; his tropes coexist with transcendent as well as their constituents. I will argue that universals, Forms.1 In his terms, a trope is a Plato does not take these particulars as basic “this­‑such” (τὸ τοιοῦτον) or Form image — constituents of the physical world, but that the a trope­‑theoretic interpretation of Timaeus’ ultimate constituents of Timaeus’ sensible par­ ontology is thus not anachronistic, since he ticulars are what metaphysicians call tropes, himself introduces tropes, as I will show, albeit or property­‑instances; Timaeus calls them τὰ under the name of “this­‑suches” (τὰ τοιαῦτα).2 τοιαῦτα, “this­‑suches.” My argument follows: When one feels hot, one does not feel heat in general but a particular heat, this ­heat: a heat 1. Each thing that comes to be is τὸ trope. Thus the heat in a given fire is not a τοιοῦτον (this ­such). repeatable entity or “immanent universal,” 2. All and only things that come to be but a particular entity, distinct from each are images of Forms. other instance of heat. This is what I mean by 3. Therefore, τὰ τοιαῦτα (this­‑suches) are a trope: a particular, non­‑repeatable instance images of Forms. of a property. 4. Triangles are τὰ τοιαῦτα or are con­ While trope theorists generally take tropes structed from τὰ τοιαῦτα. to be fundamental entities out of which uni­ 5. All bodies are constructed from tri­ versals may be constructed, Timaeus’ tropes angles. are dependent upon transcendent universals, 6. Therefore, all bodies are constructed as “Form image” implies. So a heat trope is an from τὰ τοιαῦτα (images of Forms). image of Heat, and there can be many distinct images of the same Form of Heat, each image The second part of the paper will explain coming to be and then perishing as something and defend the first syllogism, the third part becomes and then ceases to be hot. I take Forms CHRISTOPHER BUCKELS | 11 to be immutable, non­‑spatiotemporal entities The context is a puzzle about the elements, that are universals insofar as they explain com­ which seem to be too unstable to admit of be­ monality in resembling things. Heat explains ing called any one thing, since they could, at the commonality in two hot things precisely any moment, change into different elements. by having an image of itself — numerically Should we say, when pointing at a bonfire, for distinct but qualitatively identical — in each example, ‘fire is this sort of thing’ rather than hot thing; i.e., two hot things resemble each ‘fire is this thing’, or should we say ‘this sort of other because each contains a heat trope. thing is fire’ instead of ‘this thing is fire’? A trope­‑bundle theorist would say that However one wishes to settle this dispute, sensible particulars are wholly constituted we can focus on “this­‑such” and identify two by tropes. Fire is a bundle of heat, color, etc. main interpretations of τὸ τοιοῦτον in the pas­ While I do not here defend a Platonic trope­ sage. The first, dubbed the ‘traditional transla­ bundle theory, my arguments naturally lead tion’ by its adherents, claims that τὰ τοιαῦτα to such an interpretation. My trope­‑theoretic are “temporary characteristics” rather than interpretation of the Timaeus differs from tra­ “self­‑subsistent” things (Zeyl 2000 lviii, n. 18). ditional interpretations in that it takes tropes The second, which Zeyl calls the ‘alternative rather than sensible particulars as images of translation,’ takes τὰ τοιαῦτα to be “distinct Forms. Instead of holding that sensible par­ and self­‑identical characteristics” or “recurrent, ticulars have their properties by participat­ stable, and determinate characters” (following ing in Forms, a trope­‑theoretic interpretation Cherniss 1954). I propose, for now, to follow a holds that sensible particulars have properties middle ground, calling them “characteristics;” by having tropes as constituents. Thus Forms we will leave aside whether they are “tempo­ and their images — in contemporary terms, rary” or “recurrent, stable, and determinate.” transcendent universals and tropes — play We are left with quite a bit of agreement. On the central role in Plato’s explanation of the the one hand, these characteristics are tempo­ sensible world, rather than sensible particulars rary in at least one sense: they may be at a cer­ playing the starring role. tain place for only a short time, and that place may be occupied by a different characteristic at any time. Thus the fiery characteristic may 2. τὰ τοιαʋ ̃τα be replaced by a watery characteristic at any moment. On the other hand, these character­ 2.1. EACH THING THAT COMES TO BE IS istics are stable and determinate in at least one τὰ τοιαʋ ̃τα sense: for as long as each exists—which may be only an instant—it is that characteristic and not Timaeus introduces τὰ τοιαῦτα at 49d5, some other. It may be identified as belonging in the midst of a very controversial passage.3 to a certain kind. So the fiery characteristic is At the heart of the controversy is whether we fiery for as long as it exists, even if is replaced should take Timaeus to say, “fire is τὸ τοιοῦτον by a watery characteristic in but a moment. (“this such” or “this sort of thing”), rather than On either translation, Timaeus generalizes τοῦτο (“this” or “that”)”, or, “τὸ τοιοῦτον, not his conclusions to “everything that comes to τοῦτο, is fire.” The debate is thus over which be” (49e7). Thus every generated entity is a terms are subjects and which are predicates. characteristic, not a ‘thing;’ the characteristic 12 | Triangles, Tropes, and τὰ τοιαʋ ̃τα: A Platonic Trope Theory may be replaced at any time by another char­ that it is an image (τόνδε τὸν κόσμον εἰκόνα acteristic, but it remains what it is as long as τινὸς εἶναι, 29b1­‑2), viz., an image of an eter­ it is. If we generalize this claim, it applies to nal, changeless model (παράδειγμα, 29a2­‑b2). any characteristic, e.g., that of being a garbage So the demiurge, a divine craftsman, looks to truck, not just to elements. And there is no rea­ Being in order to make the universe, which is son to think it does not apply completely gen­ an image of the Living Being that contains all erally, since Timaeus gives “hot” and “white” the intelligible living beings as parts just as as further examples. Even if we think that the the universe contains us and all the other vis­ properties of being hot and being white are ible creatures (30c2­‑d1). I take the “intelligible suggested from our discussion of fire, they are living beings” to be Forms of animal species, widely applicable to macroscopic objects, and e.g., the Form of Human Being, the Form of we are given no reason to restrict their use to Goat, etc. The Living Being that contains all describing elements. In fact, Timaeus cannot be the others would be, then, the Form of Living restricting his argument to elements, since he Being, i.e., the transcendent universal that ex­ extends it to “anything you can point to,” and plains what all living beings have in common.6 it is not, strictly speaking, possible to point to Thus we have reason to identify Being with an element, since they are microscopic particles Forms, an identification that is confirmed, (we can point to some fire or water, but these e.g., at 51d3­‑52a4.
Recommended publications
  • RN and Russell's Regress
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2001, 79 (3), pp. 395-408. RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM AND RUSSELL’S REGRESS Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra University of Edinburgh In a famous passage Bertrand Russell argued that any attempt, like that of Resemblance Nominalism, to get rid of universals in favour of resemblances fails [20, p. 48]. More precisely, Russell thought that no resemblance theory could avoid postulating a universal of resemblance without falling into a vicious infinite regress. And he added that admitting a universal of resemblance made it pointless to avoid other universals. In this paper I shall defend Resemblance Nominalism, a theory which gets rid of universals in terms of resemblances, from both of Russell’s points by arguing (a) Resemblance Nominalism can avoid the postulation of a universal of resemblance without falling into a vicious infinite regress (§V) and (b) even if Resemblance Nominalism had to admit a universal of resemblance, this would not make it pointless to avoid the postulation of other universals (§VI). But before doing so I shall briefly introduce Resemblance Nominalism (§I) and Russell’s regress (§II), and then I shall consider some failed arguments and strategies against the regress (§§III−IV). I. Resemblance Nominalism. Resemblance Nominalism is a solution to the Problem of Universals. I have argued elsewhere that the Problem of Universals, strictly understood, is what I call the Many over One, rather than the traditional One over Many [17, pp. 269-70]. The Many over One is the problem of explaining how a single particular can have a multiplicity of properties [17, pp. 269-70]. Thus solutions to the Problem of Universals account for what it is for any thing or particular a to have properties F, G, H etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Nuclear Bundles of Tropes and Ontological Dependence
    Nuclear Bundles of Tropes and Ontological Dependence JOSÉ TOMÁS ALVARADO OST DEFENDERS OF TROPE METAPHYSICS have maintained that particular objects should be reduced to bundles of tropes. Part of the attraction M of a trope metaphysic is the work that tropes can do for understanding the nature of both particulars and universals. On one hand, what we call ‘universals’ can be conceived as resemblance classes of tropes. On the other hand, particular objects are nothing but pluralities of tropes satisfying certain conditions (cf. for example, Williams 1953a, 1953b; Campbell 1981, 1990; Maurin 2002; Ehring 2011). But, what are exactly those conditions that make a plurality of tropes a particular object? It has not been easy to fill in the details of a trope theory of objects and, then, it is not surprising that a variety of different proposals have been put to the fore. Some have said that objects can be understood as mereological fusions of compresent tropes. Some have said that objects can be understood as pluralities of tropes that happen to be «co– instantiated». Some have said that «co–instantiation» is just a primitive fundamental ontological fact. Some have said that it is a relational trope, albeit an especial one. For example, a relational trope that is essentially a relation between the tropes that compose an object, although the related tropes are independent from each other (cf. Maurin 2002, pp. 164–166). For others the co–instantiation trope is a relational trope that happens to relate all the tropes composing an object, including itself (cf. Ehring 2011, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Trope Theory, Resemblance, and Russell's Regress
    Trope Theory, Resemblance, and Russell's Regress Florian Boge 12.07.2012 Structure • Introduction – what are tropes? – Nominalism about universals – Bundle theory – A refinement: nucleus theory • Similarity relations – A trope theoretical measure for relative resemblance • The resemblance regress – a fundamental problem for trope theory – Is it vicious? – Similarity as internal – A cognitivist approach as a possible solution • Perfect resemblance defined What are tropes? • Definition: Tropes are the particular properties (property instances) of a given concrete entity (cf. Campbell 1990, 18). They are abstract particulars. – Relatons = polyadic tropes – Qualitons = monadic tropes (cf. Bacon 2008, 2) • An entity is called abstract (in this context) iff. it is a part of some other entity, which can only be separated in thought (cf. Rojek 2008, 361). • Particulars (indviduals) = entities which only exist in one place at one time (interval) Spacio-temproal location as an important criterion for individuality according to trope theory: “[O]ur abstract particulars are particulars because they have a local habitation, even if no name. They exist as individuals at unique place- times.” (Campbell 1990, 3) What are tropes? • Examples: – The particular shape of a given chair – Bill Clinton‟s eloquence – „This redness‟, in contrast to „redness‟ in general • Supposed to provide an alternative to realism about universals Trope theory is a form of nominalism about universals Needs to explain our use of general terms Should be able to explain every day life‟s entities such as things, their appearance, their relations etc. Nominalism about universals • Nominalism about universals = attempt to provide an explanation of general terms (i.e. terms for types, properties, relations etc.) without appeal to universals • Universals = entities that are multiply exemplified i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Armstrong and Tropes Proof.Pdf
    Peter Simons Armstrong and Tropes “So the philosophy of tropes is riding high.” David Armstrong, U 125.¹ Appreciation 5 In 1974, while a graduate student at the University of Manchester, I rst heard David Armstrong give a talk. It was on various regress arguments against nominalism, later published in NR. At that time I was not a nominalist and the arguments seemed sound. What impressed me much more forcibly however was Armstrong’s refreshing direct- ness in addressing metaphysical issues. At that time, metaphysics was largely still 10 under the domination of the philosophy of language, and arguments about the na- ture of universals tended to go via consideration of predicates, semantics and so on. Armstrong’s rejection of bad old arguments from meaning cut through that tangle like Alexander’s sword through the Gordian knot, and we were left face to face with the metaphysical question itself: are there universals, or are there not? Just as in the phe- 15 nomenological tradition Roman Ingarden had broken away from Husserl’s transcen- dental anxietizing, so in the analytical tradition Armstrong broke away from Straw- son’s Aristotelian-Kantian linguistic metaphysics-lite and Quine’s Carnapian insou- ciance as to ultimates. The idea that metaphysics might regain her status as the Queen of Philosophy was implanted, and has stayed with me ever since. I owe David a great 20 intellectual debt for making this clear by living example. The next time I saw David was in 1990 at Zinal, by which time we and things had both moved on, and this essay is about some of those things.
    [Show full text]
  • William Ockham and Trope Nominalism
    University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department Classics and Religious Studies 1998 William Ockham and Trope Nominalism Stephen E. Lahey University of Nebraska-Lincoln, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/classicsfacpub Part of the Classics Commons Lahey, Stephen E., "William Ockham and Trope Nominalism" (1998). Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department. 85. https://digitalcommons.unl.edu/classicsfacpub/85 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Classics and Religious Studies at DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications, Classics and Religious Studies Department by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln. William Ockhsun and Trope Nominalism Can we take a medieval metaphysician out of his scholastic robes and force him into a metaphysical apparatus as seemingly foreign to him as a tuxedo might be? I believe that the terminological and conceptual differences that appear to prevent this can be overcome in many cases, and that one case most amenable to this project is the medieval problem of universals. After all, the problem for the medieval is, at base, the same as it is for contemporary philosophers, as for Plato: How do we account, ontologically, for many tokens of the same type? If one object has the property x and another, distinct object has the "same" property x, how to explain the apparent "samenessw of the property x? Is x one property or two? I will argue that William Ockharn's ontology, when considered in light of some contemporary philosophical thought, is remarkably fresh and vital, able seriously to be con- sidered as a tenable position, so long as we are clear about what Ockham is saying.
    [Show full text]
  • The Racism of Philosophy's Fear of Cultural Relativism
    Journal of World Philosophies Articles/99 The Racism of Philosophy’s Fear of Cultural Relativism∗ _________________________________________ SHUCHEN XIANG Institute of Foreign Philosophy, Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies, Peking University, China ([email protected]) By looking at a canonical article representing academic philosophy’s orthodox view against cultural relativism, James Rachels’ “The Challenge of Cultural Relativism,” this paper argues that current mainstream western academic philosophy’s fear of cultural relativism is premised on a fear of the racial Other. The examples that Rachels marshals against cultural relativism default to the persistent, ubiquitous, and age-old stereotypes about the savage/barbarian Other that have dominated the history of western engagement with the non-western world. What academic philosophy fears about cultural relativism, it is argued, is the barbarians of the western imagination and not fellow human beings. The same structure that informs fears of cultural relativism, whereby people with different customs are reduced to the barbarian/savage of the western imagination, can be seen in the genesis of international law which arose as a justification for the domination of the Amerindian (parsed as “barbarians”). It is argued that implicit in arguments against cultural relativism is the preservation of the same right to dominate the Other. Finally, it is argued that the appeal of the fear of cultural relativism is that, in directing moral outrage at others, one can avoid reflecting on the failures of one’s own cultural tradition. Key words: racism; barbarian; moral universalism; cultural relativism; James Rachels; Amerindian; international law 1 Introduction This paper will illustrate how the structure of mainstream western philosophy’s fear of cultural relativism can be understood as a continuation of the pervasive racist beliefs that have dominated much of western history.
    [Show full text]
  • A Choice of Illusions: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature
    A Choice of Illusions: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature Alastair Morrison Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Columbia University 2015 © 2015 Alastair Morrison All rights reserved ABSTRACT A Choice of Illusions: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature Alastair Morrison This dissertation considers how defenses of traditional faith in Britain have adapted to new frontiers of cultural relativism and religious difference. Its contention is that poetry has become central to such defenses. Relativistic thinking would seem to dispose against metaphysical belief; poetry, as a parallel claimant for cultural and expressive particularity, and as a sensuously non-empirical rhetorical medium, offers a way of muffling the dissonance that might otherwise arise from positioning difference and particularity as pretext for claims of universal truth. This study traces formal and rhetorical innovations from the Victorian crisis of faith forward to literary modernism, with a brief conclusion contemplating related developments in more contemporary poetry and religious thought in Britain. Table of Contents Acknowledgements ii 1. Introduction: Belief, Relativism, and Modern Literature 1 i. works cited 11 2. Unction on the Tightrope: Religion as Culture in Victorian Britain 12 ii. works cited 60 3. T.E. Hulme: What Choice in Illusion? 63 iii. works cited 94 4. To Do the Right Thing for the Wrong Reason: The Justification of T.S. Eliot 96 iv. works cited 131 5. David Jones: Cultures in Parenthesis 134 v. works cited 164 6. Conclusion: Poetry and Postsecularism 166 vi. works cited 173 i Acknowledgements It is chastening to think how different this study might be were it not for the generous contributions others have made to it.
    [Show full text]
  • Herbert Hochberg • Kevin Mulligan (Eds.) Relations and Predicates
    Herbert Hochberg • Kevin Mulligan (Eds.) Relations and Predicates P h i l o s o p h i s c h e A n a l y s e P h i l o s o p h i c a l A n a l y s i s Herausgegeben von / Edited by Herbert Hochberg • Rafael Hüntelmann • Christian Kanzian Richard Schantz • Erwin Tegtmeier Band 11 / Volume 11 Herbert Hochberg • Kevin Mulligan (Eds.) Relations and Predicates ontos verlag Frankfurt . Lancaster Bibliographic information published by Die Deutsche Bibliothek Die Deutsche Bibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliographie; detailed bibliographic data is available in the Internet at http://dnb.ddb.de North and South America by Transaction Books Rutgers University Piscataway, NJ 08854-8042 [email protected] United Kingdom, Ire Iceland, Turkey, Malta, Portugal by Gazelle Books Services Limited White Cross Mills Hightown LANCASTER, LA1 4XS [email protected] 2004 ontos verlag P.O. Box 15 41, D-63133 Heusenstamm www.ontosverlag.com ISBN 3-937202-51-X 2004 No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in retrieval systems or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording or otherwise without written permission from the Publisher, with the exception of any material supplied specifically for the purpose of being entered and executed on a computer system, for exclusive use of the purchaser of the work Printed on acid-free paper ISO-Norm 970-6 Printed in Germany. Contents Introduction 7 Herbert Hochberg / Kevin Mulligan Absurd Claims 11 Lars Gustafsson Relations, Properties and Particulars 17 Herbert Hochberg (University of Texas at Austin, USA) Predication Theory: Classical vs Modern 55 Ignacio Angelelli (University of Texas at Austin, USA) Bareness, as in ‘“Bare” Particulars’: Its Ubiquity 81 Fred Wilson (University of Toronto, Canada) Objects as Hierarchical Structures: A Comprehensive Ontology 113 Donald W.
    [Show full text]
  • Hellwig.Pdf (350.8Kb)
    WHY TROPES CANNOT BE METAPHYSICALLY SIMPLE A Thesis by HEINRIK ZIEHM HELLWIG Submitted to the Office of Graduate Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS May 2008 Major Subject: Philosophy WHY TROPES CANNOT BE METAPHYSICALLY SIMPLE A Thesis by HEINRIK ZIEHM HELLWIG Submitted to the Office of Graduate Studies of Texas A&M University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS Approved by: Chair of Committee, Christopher Menzel Committee Members, Michael LeBuffe Hugh McCann Harold Boas Head of Department, Daniel Conway May 2008 Major Subject: Philosophy iii ABSTRACT Why Tropes Cannot Be Metaphysically Simple. (May 2008) Heinrik Ziehm Hellwig, B.A., John Carroll University Chair of Advisory Committee: Dr. Christopher Menzel A popular concept in contemporary metaphysics is that of metaphysical simplicity—the idea that an existent can have no parts. One reason for this is that the notion of a simple is crucial to discussions of the composition of single objects. Simples, if real, are the basic units that, when combined in various ways, make up all other objects. Keith Campbell claims that tropes—particularized properties—can be simple. In this essay I argue, against Campbell, that tropes cannot be simple. They are made up of at least two parts—a bare particular and a universal. In Section 1 I give an exhaustive account of what it is to be a simple. Then in Section 2 I discuss basic particulars and what conditions must hold for a simple to be basic.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defense of a Trope-Based Ontology for Conceptual Modeling: an Example with the Foundations of Attributes, Weak Entities and Datatypes
    In Defense of a Trope-Based Ontology for Conceptual Modeling: An example with the foundations of Attributes, Weak Entities and Datatypes Giancarlo Guizzardi 1,2 , Claudio Masolo 1, Stefano Borgo 1 1Laboratory for Applied Ontology (ISTC-CNR), Trento, Italy {guizzardi,masolo,borgo}@loa-cnr.it 2 Computer Science Department, Federal University of Espirito Santo, Vitoria-ES, Brazil Abstract. In recent years, there has been a growing interest in approaches that employ foundational ontologies as theoretical tools for analyzing and improv- ing conceptual modeling languages . However, some of these approaches do not always make explicit their ontological commitments. This leads to situations where criticisms resulting from the specific ontological choices made by a par- ticular approach are generalized to the enterprise of ontology as a whole. In this paper we discuss an example of such a case involving the BWW approach. First, we make explicit the ontological commitments underlying that approach by relating it to other possible philosophical alternatives. Second, we construct an ontological theory which commits to a different philosophical position. Third, we show how the ontology proposed here can be used to provide real- world semantics and sound modeling guidelines for the modeling constructs of Attributes, Weak Entities and Datatypes. Finally, we compare the ontology pro- posed here with BWW, thus demonstrating its benefits. 1 Introduction In recent years, there has been a growing interest in the use of foundational ontologies for: (i) evaluating conceptual modeling languages; (ii) developing guidelines for their use; (iii) providing real-world semantics for their modeling constructs (e.g., [5,7,18]). A well-known example of a foundational ontology in the conceptual model- ing/information systems area is the Bunge-Wand-Weber (BWW) ontology proposed by Wand and Weber in a series of articles (e.g., [5,20]) on the basis of the original meta- physical theory developed by Bunge in [2].
    [Show full text]
  • Plato Journal
    DEZ 2013 ISSN 2079-7567 I3 eISSN 2183-4105 Established 1989 http://platosociety.org/ Papers William H.F. Altman “The Missing Speech of the Absent Fourth: Reader Response and Plato’s Timaeus-Critias” David Levy, “Socrates vs. Callicles: Examination and Ridicule in Plato’s Gorgias.” Nathalie Nercam, “En tout et pour tout (Théétète 204a-210b)” Matthew Robinson, “Competition, Imagery, and Pleasure in Plato’s Republic, 1-91” Scott J. Senn, “Ignorance or Irony in Plato’s Socrates?: A Look Beyond Avowals and Disavowals of Knowledge” INTERNATIONAL PLATO SOCIETY PLATO INTERNATIONAL PL ATO Société Platonicienne JOURNALInternationale Associazione Internazionale dei Platonisti Sociedad Internacional de Platonistas Internationale Platon-Gesellschaft Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra Coimbra Universiy Press 2 | Enicaper ficaed susta nondin is es nonim et dolore CREDITS EditOriAL BOARD INterNAtiONAL PLATO Francisco Gonzalez SOcietY EXecutiVE University of Ottawa COmmittee (2013-16) Irmgard Männlein-Robert President: Francisco Bravo Universität Tübingen Universidad Central de Venezuela Angela Ulacco President: Gabriele Cornelli Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg Universidade de Brasília Vice President: Tom Robinson ScieNtific BOArd University of Toronto Luc Brisson Ex-President: Mauro Tulli CNRS – UPR76 Centre Jean-Pépin, Paris Università degli Studi di Pisa Tomás Calvo Next President: Luc Brisson Universidad Complutense, Madrid CNRS – UPR76 Centre Jean-Pépin, Paris John Dillon Next President: Olivier Renaut Trinity College, Dublin Université Paris
    [Show full text]
  • Two Ways to Particularize a Property
    Two Ways to Particularize a Property Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 2015, 1(4), 635-652. Robert K. Garcia Texas A&M University [email protected] www.robertkgarcia.com Request from the author: If you would be so kind, please send me a quick email if … • you are reading this for a university or college course, or • you are citing this in your own work. It is rewarding to know how my work is being used, especially if it has been adopted as required or recommended reading. Thank you. Citation Information: • Garcia, Robert K. (2015) “Two Ways to Particularize a Property” Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 2015, 1(4), 635-652. Journal of the American Philosophical Association http://journals.cambridge.org/APA Additional services for Journal of the American Philosophical Association: Email alerts: Click here Subscriptions: Click here Commercial reprints: Click here Terms of use : Click here Two Ways to Particularize a Property ROBERT K. GARCIA Journal of the American Philosophical Association / Volume 1 / Issue 04 / December 2015, pp 635 - 652 DOI: 10.1017/apa.2015.21, Published online: 29 December 2015 Link to this article: http://journals.cambridge.org/abstract_S2053447715000214 How to cite this article: ROBERT K. GARCIA (2015). Two Ways to Particularize a Property. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 1, pp 635-652 doi:10.1017/apa.2015.21 Request Permissions : Click here Downloaded from http://journals.cambridge.org/APA, IP address: 50.24.68.155 on 31 Dec 2015 Journal of the American Philosophical Association (2015) 635–652 C American Philosophical ⃝ Association doi: 10.1017/apa.2015.21 Two Ways to Particularize a Property abstract: Trope theory is an increasingly prominent contender in contemporary debates about the existence and nature of properties.
    [Show full text]