Immaterial Thoughts

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Immaterial Thoughts This result may not seem especially substantive or surprising—that we cannot doubt the existence of our minds. Descartes is being a little bit sneaky, however, as perhaps is Searle. Both are right to hold that we cannot doubt the existence of the highly conscious and highly reflective activity of attempting to doubt our beliefs, but that does not mean that our minds are to be equated with consciousness. There might be other parts of a person’s mind that she does not know as well, and whose existence is not so indubitable, but that again are still components of her mind. Descartes does not agree: At last I have discovered it—thought; this alone is inseparable from me. I am, I exist, that is certain. But for how long? For as long as I am thinking. At present I am not admitting anything but what is necessarily true. I am, then, in the strict sense only a thing that thinks; that is, I am a mind, or intelligence, or intellect, or reason. .25 As to the fact that there can be nothing in the mind, in so far as it is a thinking thing, of which it is not aware, this seems to me to be self-evident. [W]e cannot have any thought of which we are not aware at the very moment when it is in us.26 Descartes is correct that the existence of highly conscious thinking is indubitable while we are engaging in it, but that does not mean that there are not other elements of the mind whose existence is less well known, and it does not mean that the mind is to be identified with those of its elements that are well known. Are thoughts immaterial? 20 Thus far we have considered some arguments for the view that thinking is material, along with some of the possible extensions and implications of that view. There are also a number of compelling arguments for the view that minds are immaterial. One is that bodies are always composite and divisible into parts, but minds are simple and indivisible. Minds and bodies are therefore different kinds of things. Socrates puts forward a version of this argument: Is not anything that is composite and a compound by nature liable to be split up into its component parts, and only that which is noncomposite, if anything, is not likely to be split up? . The soul is most like the divine, deathless, intelligible, uniform, indissoluble, always the same as itself, whereas the body is most like that which is human, mortal, multiform, unintelligible, soluble, and never consistently the same.27 We find the same argument later in Descartes: [T]he body is by its very nature always divisible, while the mind is utterly indivisible. For when I consider the mind, . I am unable to distinguish any parts within myself. I understand myself to be quite single and complete. Although the whole mind seems to be united to the whole body, I recognize that if a foot or arm or any other part of the body is cut off, nothing has thereby been taken away from the mind.28 The two philosophers are defending the doctrine of substance dualism—the view that there are two kinds of things or substances in the universe. According to this view, there exist mental substances that are intangible and indivisible, and also physical substances that have dimension and are divisible. Minds are things that think and have ideas, and because they do not have dimension they cannot be decomposed into parts. Socrates adds that minds are different from bodies in that they are invisible.29 So minds appear to be very different from bodies: they are invisible and indivisible, and hence indestructible and deathless, or at the very least they do not perish as a result of the death of the body. 21 A potential problem for this argument is that there appears to be evidence that if some parts of the body are cut off or damaged, then—to use Descartes’ language —something is taken away from the mind. Socrates and Descartes may be correct that minds are not decomposable into parts, but when our brains shut down it appears that thinking shuts down as well. Socrates and Descartes would say that thinking may seem to shut down from an outsider’s perspective, but in fact it does not.30 22 Another argument for the view that minds are immaterial substances is that minds are free and independent in a way that they would not be if thinking was material. We make choices and are (at least in part) the author of our own trajectory. If our thinking was due entirely to the cells of our nervous system, we would have no more independence or autonomy than anything else in nature. 23 A variant of this argument appears in Socrates. In Phaedo, there is a discussion of the relationship between harp strings and the music that they produce. The discussion begins when Socrates’ interlocutor insists that just because a thing is invisible, that does not mean that it is immaterial: One might make the same argument about harmony, lyre and strings, that a harmony is something invisible, without body, beautiful and divine in the attuned lyre, whereas the lyre itself and its strings are physical, bodily, composite, earthly, and akin to what is mortal. If then the soul is a kind of harmony or attunement, clearly, when our body is relaxed or stretched without due measure by diseases and other evils, the soul must be immediately destroyed, even if it be most divine, as are the other harmonies found in music and all the works of artists.31 Socrates responds with the claim that a harmony is very different from a mind. A harmony depends for its existence on the instrument that produces it; a harmony cannot go off in its own direction, independent of the strings, and if it did we would look for another musician hiding in the bushes. Nor can a harmony have an impact on the strings that produce it and make the strings proceed in a different order. Or perhaps a harmony can affect the strings, but only if it was produced and then guided by the vibrations of the strings to begin with. A mind is different: it is able to direct its body independently of the way that the body (or the brain) is behaving. Socrates writes, Do you think it natural for a harmony, or any other composite, to be in a different state from that of the elements of which it is composed? . Nor, as I think, can it act or be acted upon in a different way than its elements? . One must therefore suppose that a harmony does not direct its components, but is directed by them.32 Socrates has put his finger exactly on the problem. He is assuming that the dependence relation between thinking and the brain is very different from the dependence relation between music and an instrument. It sure seems to be different—if we are autonomous agents—and it seems outrageous to deny that we are autonomous at least to some degree. 24 We are at a critical juncture in the debate about whether or not thinking is material. One view is that all of our mental life is dependent on the brain and that if our ideas and decisions are able to guide our bodies, it is because our brains produced those states to begin with. Another view is that we have a kind of control and autonomy that would not be possible if the entirety of our mental life depended on the underlying cellular activity of the nervous system, and so it doesn’t. 25 Things come to a head in cases like that of the impressive politician and actor, Ronald Reagan. The reason why the case of President Reagan is so central is that a pillar of his political platform was to argue that individuals should exercise mind over matter and use willpower to pull themselves up from difficult circumstances. Reagan was a remarkable human being. His energy and charisma, the thoughts that came to him at just the right time, and his charm and poise—on the view that thinking is physical, every aspect of his mental life depended entirely on the underlying neuronal activity in his brain. On that view, Mr Reagan could not have summoned up willpower to neutralize the symptoms of his Alzheimer’s disease; the very faculty that he would need to employ to do that—his will—was among the things that the disease was holding hostage. On the view of Socrates and Descartes, minds are not the product of the nervous system. The original self and mind of an Alzheimer’s victim is still present somewhere, even if it appears to an outside observer that it has disappeared. The decisions of a person are not produced by the antecedent states of their brain, and no matter the configuration of their brain at any given moment, a lot of different decisions are possible for them. On this second view, our ideas and decisions are not like the music of a harp but are autonomous and have a life of their own. 26 We have to be very careful here. If we accept the first view (that thinking is produced in the brain), we might feel inclined to criticize our opponent. We might suggest that our opponent is wrong and that they should be held accountable for their blunder. But in that case we would be supposing that human beings do have control over their mental lives.
Recommended publications
  • Dualism Vs. Materialism: a Response to Paul Churchland
    Dualism vs. Materialism: A Response to Paul Churchland by M. D. Robertson Paul M. Churchland, in his book, Matter and Consciousness, provides a survey of the issues and positions associated with the mind-body problem. This problem has many facets, and Churchland addresses several of them, including the metaphysical, epistemological, semantic, and methodological aspects of the debate. Churchland, of course, has very strong views on the subject, and does not hide his biases on the matter. In this paper I shall reexamine the metaphysical aspect of the mind-body problem. The metaphysical question concerns the existential status of the mind and the body, and the nature of the relationship between them. Like Churchland, I shall not hide my biases on the matter. What follows may be thought of as a rewriting of the second chapter of Churchland's book ("The Ontological Issue") from a non-naturalistic perspective. Substance Dualism René Descartes argued that the defining characteristic of minds was cogitation in a broad 2 sense, while that of bodies was spatial extension. Descartes also claimed that minds were not spatially extended, nor did bodies as such think. Thus minds and bodies were separate substances. This view has come to be called substance dualism. Descartes's argument for substance dualism can be summarized as follows: (1) Minds exist. (2) Bodies exist. (3) The defining feature of minds is cogitation. (4) The defining feature of bodies is extension. (5) That which cogitates is not extended. (6) That which is extended does not cogitate. Therefore, (7) Minds are not bodies, and bodies are not minds.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN Curriculum Vitae Last updated 3/6/2019 I. Personal and Academic History .................................................................................................................... 1 List of Degrees Earned ........................................................................................................................................................ 1 Title of Ph.D. Thesis ........................................................................................................................................................... 1 Positions held ..................................................................................................................................................................... 1 Invited lectures and lecture series ........................................................................................................................................ 1 List of Honors, Prizes ......................................................................................................................................................... 4 Research Grants .................................................................................................................................................................. 4 Non-Academic Publications ................................................................................................................................................ 5 II. Professional Activities .................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • In Defence of Folk Psychology
    FRANK JACKSON & PHILIP PETTIT IN DEFENCE OF FOLK PSYCHOLOGY (Received 14 October, 1988) It turned out that there was no phlogiston, no caloric fluid, and no luminiferous ether. Might it turn out that there are no beliefs and desires? Patricia and Paul Churchland say yes. ~ We say no. In part one we give our positive argument for the existence of beliefs and desires, and in part two we offer a diagnosis of what has misled the Church- lands into holding that it might very well turn out that there are no beliefs and desires. 1. THE EXISTENCE OF BELIEFS AND DESIRES 1.1. Our Strategy Eliminativists do not insist that it is certain as of now that there are no beliefs and desires. They insist that it might very well turn out that there are no beliefs and desires. Thus, in order to engage with their position, we need to provide a case for beliefs and desires which, in addition to being a strong one given what we now know, is one which is peculiarly unlikely to be undermined by future progress in neuroscience. Our first step towards providing such a case is to observe that the question of the existence of beliefs and desires as conceived in folk psychology can be divided into two questions. There exist beliefs and desires if there exist creatures with states truly describable as states of believing that such-and-such or desiring that so-and-so. Our question, then, can be divided into two questions. First, what is it for a state to be truly describable as a belief or as a desire; what, that is, needs to be the case according to our folk conception of belief and desire for a state to be a belief or a desire? And, second, is what needs to be the case in fact the case? Accordingly , if we accepted a certain, simple behaviourist account of, say, our folk Philosophical Studies 59:31--54, 1990.
    [Show full text]
  • Maintaining Meaningful Expressions of Romantic Love in a Material World
    Reconciling Eros and Neuroscience: Maintaining Meaningful Expressions of Romantic Love in a Material World by ANDREW J. PELLITIERI* Boston University Abstract Many people currently working in the sciences of the mind believe terms such as “love” will soon be rendered philosophically obsolete. This belief results from a common assumption that such terms are irreconcilable with the naturalistic worldview that most modern scientists might require. Some philosophers reject the meaning of the terms, claiming that as science progresses words like ‘love’ and ‘happiness’ will be replaced completely by language that is more descriptive of the material phenomena taking place. This paper attempts to defend these meaningful concepts in philosophy of mind without appealing to concepts a materialist could not accept. Introduction hilosophy engages the meaning of the word “love” in a myriad of complex discourses ranging from ancient musings on happiness, Pto modern work in the philosophy of mind. The eliminative and reductive forms of materialism threaten to reduce the importance of our everyday language and devalue the meaning we attach to words like “love,” in the name of scientific progress. Faced with this threat, some philosophers, such as Owen Flanagan, have attempted to defend meaningful words and concepts important to the contemporary philosopher, while simultaneously promoting widespread acceptance of materialism. While I believe that the available work is useful, I think * [email protected]. Received 1/2011, revised December 2011. © the author. Arché Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy, Volume V, Issue 1: Winter 2012. pp. 60-82 RECONCILING EROS AND NEUROSCIENCE 61 more needs to be said about the functional role of words like “love” in the script of progressing neuroscience, and further the important implications this yields for our current mode of practical reasoning.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Unnoticed Implications of Churchland's Pragmatic Pluralism
    Contemporary Pragmatism Editions Rodopi Vol. 8, No. 1 (June 2011), 173–189 © 2011 Beyond Eliminative Materialism: Some Unnoticed Implications of Churchland’s Pragmatic Pluralism Teed Rockwell Paul Churchland’s epistemology contains a tension between two positions, which I will call pragmatic pluralism and eliminative materialism. Pragmatic pluralism became predominant as his episte- mology became more neurocomputationally inspired, which saved him from the skepticism implicit in certain passages of the theory of reduction he outlined in Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. However, once he replaces eliminativism with a neurologically inspired pragmatic pluralism, Churchland (1) cannot claim that folk psychology might be a false theory, in any significant sense; (2) cannot claim that the concepts of Folk psychology might be empty of extension and lack reference; (3) cannot sustain Churchland’s critic- ism of Dennett’s “intentional stance”; (4) cannot claim to be a form of scientific realism, in the sense of believing that what science describes is somehow realer that what other conceptual systems describe. One of the worst aspects of specialization in Philosophy and the Sciences is that it often inhibits people from asking the questions that could dissolve long standing controversies. This paper will deal with one of these controversies: Churchland’s proposal that folk psychology is a theory that might be false. Even though one of Churchland’s greatest contributions to philosophy of mind was demonstrating that the issues in philosophy of mind were a subspecies of scientific reduction, still philosophers of psychology have usually defended or critiqued folk psychology without attempting to carefully analyze Churchland’s theory of reduction.
    [Show full text]
  • Tools of Pragmatism
    Coping with the World: Tools of Pragmatism Mind, Brain and the Intentional Vocabulary Anders Kristian Krabberød Hovedoppgave Filosofisk Institutt UNIVERSITETET I OSLO Høsten 2004 Contents 1. Introduction.................................................................................................. 2 2. Different Ways of Describing the Same Thing ........................................... 7 3. Rorty and Vocabularies ............................................................................. 11 The Vocabulary-Vocabulary ...............................................................................................13 Reduction and Ontology......................................................................................................17 4. The Intentional Vocabulary and Folk Psychology: the Churchlands and Eliminative Materialism ................................................................................ 21 Eliminative Materialism......................................................................................................22 Dire Consequences..............................................................................................................24 Objecting against Eliminative Materialism..........................................................................25 1. The first objection: Eliminative materialism is a non-starter........................................27 2. The second objection: What could possibly falsify Folk Psychology?...........................29 3. The third objection: Folk Psychology is used
    [Show full text]
  • Paul Churchland
    fair body of moderately successful theory described the way this fluid Paul Churchland substance--called "caloric"-- flowed within a body, or from one body to another, and how it produced thermal expansion, melting, boiling, and Eliminative Materialism (1984)* so forth. But by the end of the last century it had become abundantly clear that heat was not a substance at all, but just the energy of motion of Eliminative materialism (or eliminativism) is the radical claim that our ordinary, the trillions of jostling molecules that make up the heated body itself. Te common-sense understanding of the mind is deeply wrong and that some or all of new theory--the "corpuscular/kinetic theory of matter and hear'--was the mental states posited by common-sense do not actually exist. Descartes fa- much more successful than the old in explaining and predicting the mously challenged much of what we take for granted, but he insisted that, for the thermal behavior of bodies. And since we were unable to identify caloric most part, we can be confident about the content of our own minds. Eliminative fluid with kinetic energy (according to the old theory, caloric is a material materialists go further than Descartes on this point, since they challenge of the exis- substance; according to the new theory, kinetic energy is a form of mo- tence of various mental states that Descartes took for granted. tion), it was finally agreed that there is no such thing as caloric. Caloric —William Ramsey1 was simply eliminated from our accepted ontology. As the eliminative materialists see it…our common-sense psycholo- A second example.
    [Show full text]
  • THE HORNSWOGGLE PROBLEM1 Patricia Smith Churchland, Department of Philosophy, University of California at San Diego, La Jolla, CA 92093, USA
    Journal of Consciousness Studies, 3, No. 5ñ6, 1996, pp. 402ñ8 THE HORNSWOGGLE PROBLEM1 Patricia Smith Churchland, Department of Philosophy, University of California at San Diego, La Jolla, CA 92093, USA. Abstract: Beginning with Thomas Nagel, various philosophers have propsed setting con- scious experience apart from all other problems of the mind as ëthe most difficult problemí. When critically examined, the basis for this proposal reveals itself to be unconvincing and counter-productive. Use of our current ignorance as a premise to determine what we can never discover is one common logical flaw. Use of ëI-cannot-imagineí arguments is a related flaw. When not much is known about a domain of phenomena, our inability to imagine a mechanism is a rather uninteresting psychological fact about us, not an interesting metaphysical fact about the world. Rather than worrying too much about the meta-problem of whether or not consciousness is uniquely hard, I propose we get on with the task of seeing how far we get when we address neurobiologically the problems of mental phenomena. I: Introduction Conceptualizing a problem so we can ask the right questions and design revealing experiments is crucial to discovering a satisfactory solution to the problem. Asking where animal spirits are concocted, for example, turns out not to be the right question to ask about the heart. When Harvey asked instead, ëHow much blood does the heart pump in an hour?í, he conceptualized the problem of heart function very differently. The recon- ceptualization was pivotal in coming to understand that the heart is really a pump for circulating blood; there are no animal spirits to concoct.
    [Show full text]
  • Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind by Paul Churchland
    BOOK REVIEWS obscurity of purpose makes his continual referencesto science seem irrelevantto our views about the nature of minds. This can only rein- force what Wilson would call the OA prejudices that he deplores. JANET LEVIN Universityof SouthernCalifornia ThePhilosophical Review, XCI, No. 2 (April 1982) SCIENTIFIC REALISM AND THE PLASTICITY OF MIND. By PAUL CHURCHLAND. New York and London, Cambridge University Press, 1979. Pp. x, 157. $19.95. Paul Churchland's book is an attempt to show how one can have a literal, realistic attitude to current scientific theory and at the same time see our current system of concepts as inconclusive, temporary, far fromany cadence. He wants to let us have both a Putnam-like scien- tific realism and a Feyerabend-like acknowledgment of the plasticity of our understanding. His main target is our understanding of mind, both because it is natural to expect that their scientifictheorizing will have some radical impact on our ordinary thinking,and because of the connections between one's theory of mind and one's theory of know- ledge. And, though Churchland is not explicit on this point, some of the most puzzling questions about realism and referencearise about the vocabulary of mind. Churchland begins by describing the continuity of commonsense and scientificbelief, arguing, much in the manner of Hanson, Good- man, or a number of others, that perceptual experience is something that is informed as much by one's beliefs as by what strikesone's re- ceptors. What is interestinghere is not so much these conclusions as his attempt to describe the malleability of perception by prior belief in such a way that it allows perception to bear a referentialrelation to the physical realities that prompt it.
    [Show full text]
  • Introductory Lectures: the Nature and History of Cognitive Science Chapter 4: Philosophy’S Convergence Towards Cognitive Science by Dr
    Introductory Lectures: The Nature and History of Cognitive Science Chapter 4: Philosophy’s Convergence Towards Cognitive Science By Dr. Charles Wallis Last revision: 9/24/2018 Chapter Outline 4.1 Introduction 4.2 The Scientific Explosion of the Early 20th Century 4.3 The Logical and Mathematical Explosion of the Early 20th Century 4.4 The Rise Logical Empiricism 4.5 Logical Behaviorism 4.6 Three Problems for Logical Behaviorism 4.7 Identity Theories: Reduction Through Reference Equivalence Rather Than Meaning Equivalence 4.8 Identity Theories: Type-Type Identity 4.9 Two Arguments For Type-Type Identity Theory 4.10 Identity Theories: Token-Token Identity 4.11 Functionalism 4.12 Computationalism 4.13 Property Dualism 4.14 Eliminative Materialism 4.15 Glossary of Key Terms 4.16 Bibliography The 20th Century and the Semantic Twist 4.1 Introduction Recall that ontological frameworks provide a general framework within which theorists specify domains of inquiry and construct theories to predict, manipulate, and explain phenomena within the domain. Once researchers articulate an ontological framework with sufficient clarity they begin to formulate and test theories. Chapter two ends with the suggestion that oppositional substance dualists face two major challenges in their attempt to transition from the articulation of an ontological framework to the formulation and testing of theories purporting to predict, manipulate, and explain mental phenomena. On the one hand, oppositional substance dualists have problems formulating theories providing explanations, predictions, and manipulations of the continual, seamless interaction between the mental and the physical. Philosophers often call this the interaction problem. On the other hand, the very nature of a mental substance--substance defined so as to share no properties with physical substance--gives rise to additional challenges.
    [Show full text]
  • Common Responses to the Hard Problem
    Common Responses to the Hard Problem Benjamin Stucky Semir Zeki Editorial in Book Consciousness: Theories in Neuroscience Multiple and Philosophy of Mind Consciousnesses? Original Paper Zeki (2003) The disunity of consciousness Chapter 5 Separation of mind from brain? Book: Transcendent Mind Non-aware arithmetic? Paper: Sklar et al. (2012) Reading and They use a different doing arithmetic nonconsciously definition of consciousness compared to our course! Privacy of Language? BBC Radio 4: Wittgenstein‘s Beetle in a Box Analogy youtube.com/watch?v=x86hLtOkou8 materialism somtimes physicalism matter dualism substance or property matter consciousness idealismidealism consciousness neutralneutralidealism monismmonism one substance neither matter nor mind Common responses to the hard question as categorized by Chalmers (2003) Consciousness and its Place in Nature A materialism there is no epistemic (knowledge) gap consciousness does not exists is fully definable by or eliminativism functions functionalism, behaviors behaviorism information computationalism A materialism water earth air fire Folk Psychology Argument: “ […] the correct account of cognition […] will bear about as much resemblance to Folk Psychology as modern chemistry bears to fourspirit alchemy. “ - Paul Churchland Alchemical symbols from: en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Alchemical_symbol A materialism Illusion/Belief Argument: “[…] something that is true: I am not introspectively aware that mental images are brain-processes to something that is false: I am introspectively aware that mental images are not brain-processes.” - DM Armstrong Cartoon by ciosuconstantin: toonpool.com/cartoons/Illusion_8114 A materialism Chinese room John Searle I do not understand Chinese. I am in a closed room an receive questions in Chinese. I answer them by using a rulebook which allows for perfect Chinese-English translation.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Mind CRITICAL CONCEPTS in PHILOSOPHY
    4-Volume Set Philosophy of Mind CRITICAL CONCEPTS IN PHILOSOPHY Edited and with a new introduction by Sean Crawford, University of Manchester, UK Philosophy of mind is concerned with fundamental issues about the relation between mind and body and mind and world, and with the nature of the diverse variety of mental phenomena, such as thought, self-knowledge, consciousness, perception, sensation, and emotion. Philosophers of mind explore some of the most perplexing questions about our mental lives. For instance: • How exactly is the mental related to the physical? • How is it that our thoughts can reach out to reality and refer to objects distant in time and space? • What is consciousness? Can it be explained by science? For as long as humanity has sought an understanding of its place in the universe, philosophy of mind has been at the centre of philosophy, but it flourishes now as it has never done before. This new title in the Routledge’s Major Works series, Critical Concepts in Philosophy, meets the need for an authoritative reference work to make sense of the subject’s enormous literature and the continuing explosion in research output. Edited by Sean Crawford, a prominent scholar in the field, it is a four-volume collection of classic and contemporary contributions to all of the major debates in philosophy of mind. With comprehensive introductions to each volume, newly written by the editor, which place the collected material in its historical and intellectual context, Philosophy of Mind— is an essential work of reference and is destined to be valued by philosophers of mind-as well as those working in allied areas such as metaphysics, epistemology, and philosophy of language; and cognate disciplines such as psychology—as a vital research tool.
    [Show full text]