Arendt on Thinking and Evil

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Arendt on Thinking and Evil Thinking, Conscience and Acting in Times of Crises Paul Formosa Thinking, Conscience and Acting in Times of Crises Introduction If there is one lesson that Hannah Arendt drew from her encounter with Adolf Eichmann in Jerusalem it was that the moral and political dangers of thoughtlessness had been grossly underestimated (Formosa, 2007a). However, the claim that thoughtlessness is a mass phenomenon is one that Arendt had already defended in The Human Condition. Indeed, the reason why Eichmann is, according to Arendt, so “terrifyingly normal” (EJ: 206), is precisely because he is primarily characterised by thoughtlessness, a trait he shares with his fellow “Animal Laborans”, the victorious “jobholders” of modern mass society (HC: 320-25; see also BPF: 4-13). Of course, the labelling of the ‘masses’ as thoughtless and inauthentic has been a persistent philosophical theme from Plato, through to Kant, Nietzsche, Heidegger and beyond. What is novel about Arendt’s claim is her argument that there is a link between mass thoughtlessness and mass evil, the type of large-scale evil that can only be perpetrated with the support of the masses. Arendt, however, remains cautious about recommending thoughtfulness per se as a panacea to modern mass thoughtlessness. While she closes The Human Condition, a book about action, with a few hopeful words beckoning towards the promise of thoughtfulness, her advocacy of the importance of action also leads her to claim that “non-thinking … seems so recommendable a state for political and moral affairs”. While thoughtlessness clearly “has its perils”, (LMT 177) as the example of Eichmann illustrates, thoughtfulness has its own problems, as the example of Heidegger illustrates. In the course of her 1964 interview with Günter Gaus, Arendt recalls her distaste for “intellectual business” that arose from witnessing the widespread and “relatively voluntary” Gleichshaltung (co-ordination) of German “intellectuals” with the Nazis in 1933 (EU: 10). This was the year that Heidegger, Arendt’s former teacher and friend, “entered the Nazi Party in a very sensational way” (EU: 187). Arendt, in a 1946 review, even lists Heidegger as one of “those outstanding scholars [who] did their utmost to supply the Nazis with ideas and techniques” (EU: 201). But Heidegger is for Arendt also a paragon of thoughtfulness who exposes the “incomprehensible triviality” (or banality) of “the they” and their “mere talk” (MDT: ix; see also Pitkin, 1998: 49-60). This raises the following question: how can thoughtfulness, in the guise of Heidegger, and thoughtlessness, in the guise of Eichmann, both (though to a very different extent) lead to ‘co-ordination’ with the Nazis? What does this tell us about the relation between thinking and evil? Arendt begins her account of thinking in The Life of the Mind with an attempt to answer this question. She asks there (LMT: 5) whether the mere activity of - 1 - Thinking, Conscience and Acting in Times of Crises Paul Formosa thinking is “among the conditions that make men abstain from evil-doing or even actually ‘condition’ them against it?” For Arendt, there are moral benefits to be gained from simply learning how to think, above and beyond those gained from learning what to think (RJ: 101). However, conditioning implies only that, as a result of thinking, a person will be less likely, inclined or disposed to perpetrate or support evil. But how might the sheer activity of thinking do this and do all types of thinking have this same effect? In order to answer this question I shall examine Arendt’s distinction between critical and professional thinking, and her account of conscience, in order to argue how and why critical (but not professional) thinking can condition against evil. Drawing on this argument, I then proceed to critically investigate Arendt’s account of the masses, conscience, and action in times of crises. Critical Thinking For Arendt, thinking along with willing and judging are the three autonomous, spontaneous and independent faculties that comprise the life of the mind. The activity of thinking, as with all the activities of the mind, is hidden from the world and thereby involves a “deliberate withdrawal from appearances” (LMT: 75). The hidden and withdrawn nature of the mind inevitably puts it in constant “tension” with action, which can only occur in the world of appearances (RJ: 105). Arendt bases her account of thinking on Kant’s distinction between reason (Vernunft), “the urge to think and to understand”, and intellect (Verstand), “which desires and is capable of certain, verifiable knowledge” (RJ: 163). This distinction, according to Arendt, “coincides with two altogether different mental activities, thinking and knowing, and two altogether different concerns, meaning … and cognition [respectively]” (LMT: 14). This is not to say that there is no thinking involved in knowing, but only that in such cases thinking remains a mere reasoning tool or “handmaiden” for the intellect’s quest for knowledge (LMT: 61; see also Deutscher, 2007: 16). With this distinction Arendt sees Kant as liberating thinking by differentiating it from knowledge, and thereby opening up room for reason to think about issues that lay beyond what can be known, but which remain of “the greatest existential interest to man” (LMT: 15). However, when thinking goes beyond the limits of what can be known, by asking questions about the meaning of facts or stories, or by addressing ethical or political issues, it remains a never-ending or open-ended activity. Arendt accentuates this non-finality, this going around in circles (LMT: 124), by likening thinking to “Penelope’s web,” in that it “undoes every morning what it has finished the night before” (LMT: 88). It is here that Arendt, despite her close affinities with Kant, makes her decisive break with Kantian moral theory. The critique of pure reason by reason, for Arendt, goes around forever in circles, whereas for Kant, it shows us (among other things) - 2 - Thinking, Conscience and Acting in Times of Crises Paul Formosa that a rational belief in freedom and the accompanying moral law can withstand the destructive power of such a critique. Arendt thus uses a Kantian distinction from the First Critique, between thinking and knowing, to deny a Kantian position from the Second Critique, namely that thinking can practically ground universally valid moral and political norms, rather than only destructively undermine them (RJ: 159-189). Arendt claims that thinking and meaning remain forever unstable and non-definitive, whereas Kant claims that we can strike solid ground in practical matters through critical reflection and the recognition of the absolute value of humanity. In any case, how might stopping and thinking, in order to re-present thought- objects in the pursuit of meaning, condition against evil? Indeed, this thesis might seem to be a non-starter for the following reasons. If the thesis is correct, then we would expect that the more frequent and the deeper a person thinks, the greater the conditioning effect. But there does not seem to be any such effect. As we have seen, Heidegger’s deep and frequent thoughtfulness did not prevent his “error” or “lack of judgment” (as Bernstein (1996: 174) puts it) in regard to his support of the Nazis in 1933. If we find a wide spread willingness to support the racist agenda of the Nazi party among both the thoughtful intellectual elites, such as Heidegger, and the thoughtless many, such as Eichmann (Villa, 1999: 86), then this would seem to refute Arendt’s claims about the conditioning effects of thinking. However, Arendt’s position is more complex, as she makes an important distinction between ‘critical thinkers’, of whom Socrates and Kant in particular, but also the likes of Lessing and Jaspers, are Arendt’s exemplars, and ‘professional thinkers’ (Denker von Gewerbe) (LMT: 3), of whom Heidegger is an important exemplar. The professional thinker is not simply someone whose job it is to think, for both Heidegger and Jaspers earned a living from thinking. Rather the difference lies in the way or mode of thinking, as I shall make clear below. This distinction is important for Arendt because not all thinking, but only critical thinking, has a conditioning effect against evil, or so I shall argue. All thinking for Arendt is withdrawn and isolated, or similarly private and monological. But only “critical thinking, according to Kant and according to Socrates, exposes itself to ‘the test of free and open examination,’ and this means that the more people participate in it, the better” (KPP: 39). Critical thinking is ‘representative’ or ‘enlarged’ thinking, and this involves thinking through an issue from as many different standpoints as possible (BPF: 241). For Kant this leads to “pluralism” as a “way of thinking”, whereby other citizens are needed as a necessary “touchstone”, though not a replacement, for one’s own thinking (2006: 7:128-30). It is this need for a touchstone that leads Kant to claim that the “freedom to speak and to publish” and to make “public use of one’s reason” is the most important political freedom (KPP: 39). This is because without a space for the public use of reason, without “the - 3 - Thinking, Conscience and Acting in Times of Crises Paul Formosa test of free and open examination,” Arendt argues that “no thinking and no opinion- formation are possible” (KPP: 40). While Arendt somewhat overstates the case to say that no thinking and no opinion forming are possible for the thinker without a public space for the testing of their ideas, she is right to point out that critical thinking does require such a space or, more accurately, can’t survive too long (or at least flourish) without it. Kant makes a similar point: “Thus one can very well say that this external power which wrenches away people’s freedom publicly to communicate their thoughts also takes from them the freedom to think” (1996a: 8:144).
Recommended publications
  • {TEXTBOOK} the Portable Hannah Arendt Ebook
    THE PORTABLE HANNAH ARENDT PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Hannah Arendt | 640 pages | 25 Sep 2003 | Penguin Books Ltd | 9780142437568 | English | London, United Kingdom The Portable Hannah Arendt: Arendt, Hannah: : Books Professor Hannah. On Revolution. Usually dispatched within 3 to 4 days. Next page. About the Author Hannah Arendt was born in Hanover, Germany, in , and received her doctorate in philosophy from the University of Heidelberg. In , she was briefly imprisoned by the Gestapo, after which she fled Germany for Paris, where she worked on behalf of Jewish refugee children. In , she was stripped of her German citizenship, and in she left France for the United States. Her many books include The Origins of Totalitarianism , The Human Condition and Eichmann in Jerusalem , in which she coined the famous phrase 'the banality of evil'. She died in What other items do customers buy after viewing this item? Only 2 left in stock. No customer reviews. How are ratings calculated? To calculate the overall star rating and percentage breakdown by star, we do not use a simple average. Instead, our system considers things like how recent a review is and if the reviewer bought the item on Amazon. It also analyses reviews to verify trustworthiness. Review this product Share your thoughts with other customers. Learn how to enable JavaScript on your browser. Overview: What Remains? What Remains? Jewess and Shlemihl Writing Rahel Varnhagen. What Is Authority? Home 1 Books 2. Add to Wishlist. Sign in to Purchase Instantly. Members save with free shipping everyday! See details. After the rise of the Nazis, she emigrated to America where she proceeded to write some of the most searching, hard-hitting reflections on the agonizing issues of the time: totalitarianism in both Nazi and Stalinist garb; Zionism and the legacy of the Holocaust; federally mandated school desegregation and civil rights in the United States; and the nature of evil.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Arendt's Critical Dialogue with Heidegger KOISHIKAWA Kazue
    Thinking and Transcendence: Arendt’s Critical Dialogue with Heidegger KOISHIKAWA Kazue Adjunct Faculty, University of Tsukuba Abstract : In the introduction to The Life of the Mind: Thinking (1977), Hannah Arendt explains that it was her observation of Adolf Eichmann’s “thoughtlessness” — his inability to think — at his trial in Jerusalem that led her to reexamine the human faculty of thinking, particularly in respect to its relation to moral judgment. Yet, it is not an easy task for her readers to follow how Arendt actually constructs her arguments on this topic in this text. The purpose of this paper is to delineate Arendt’s criticisms of Heidegger in order to articulate the characteristics of her own account of thinking in relation to morality. The paper first suggests the parallelism between Heidegger’s “wonder” and Arendt’s “love” as the beginning of philosophizing, i.e., thinking, and point out a peculiar circularity in Heidegger’s account of thinking. Secondly, the paper traces Arendt’s criticism of Heidegger’s account of thinking in §18 of the LM 1. Thirdly, the paper discusses why Arendt thinks Heidegger’s account of thinking is problematic by examining Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics (1929). Finally, based on the above analyses and discussions, the paper explores the nature of Arendt’s account of thinking to show how her conception of thinking provides a basis for moral judgment. In the introduction to The Life of the Mind: Thinking (1977), Hannah Arendt explains that it was her observation of Adolf Eichmann’s “thoughtlessness” — his inability to think — at his trial in Jerusalem that led her to reexamine the human faculty of thinking, particularly in respect to its relation to moral judgment.
    [Show full text]
  • Open Letter to Hannah Arendt on Thinking
    Open Letter to Hannah Arendt on Thinking Ágnes Heller RESUMEN Agnes Heller se ocupa en este artículo de la primera parte de la última obra de Hannah Arendt, “Pensar”, de La vida del espíritu, con el ánimo de establecer una discusión sobre el valor de este actividad en la vida humana. Heller subraya su acuerdo general con la gran filósofa alemana-americana. Pero también critica su retórica y las debilidades teóricas de su argumento. Para Arendt, si queremos actuar políticamente tenemos que pararnos a pensar; para Heller, la vida humana es pensar. Palabras clave: Arendt/La vida del espíritu/Heidegger/pensar/mal/Kant/Wittgenstein ABSTRACT In this article, Agnes Heller deals with Arendt’s “On thinking”, the first part of her work The Life of the Spirit in order to open a discussion on its value to life. Heller stresses her agreement with the great German American philosopher. But also points to her rhetoric’s and pose some critical remarks on its theoretical flaws. To Arendt, in order to act politically, one has to stop and think; to Heller, human life is thinking. Key Words: Arendt/ The Life of the Mind/ Heidegger/ Thinking/ Evil/Kant/Wittgenstein Dear Hannah Arendt, Two decades ago I have already written an essay about your work on The Life of the Mind. Having been invited once again to a conference discussing also your work, I re-read the books in order to refresh my memory. After the second reading have I decided to speak this time only about the first volume, “On Thinking”, since this is the book you were still able to put in a proper shape, although no more to correct.
    [Show full text]
  • Minor in Philosophy Course Descriptions
    Department of Philosophy Professors: Louise Carroll Keeley, Nalin Ranasinghe; Associate Professors: J. Patrick Corrigan (Director, Rome Program 2017–19), Christian Göbel, Daniel P. Maher (Chairperson), Molly Brigid McGrath, Anthony D. Traylor; Assistant Professors: Veronica Roberts Ogle, Samuel A. Stoner. MISSION STATEMENT Philosophy is a reasoned quest for truths fundamental to all areas of inquiry. Animated by a love of ideas, philosophical inquiry attends to all that is of ultimate concern for human beings. Guided by the College’s commitment to embody the complementarity of faith and reason and its broader mission, the Philosophy Department of Assumption College is founded on the ongoing engagement of its faculty and students with the Catholic intellectual tradition. We seek intellectual friendship among all who take seriously the life of the mind. Grappling with fundamental questions of human existence with an eye toward discerning the truth is an essential dimension of this tradition. Our mission is to engage students in the activity of philosophy strengthened by this tradition. LEARNING OUTCOMES • Reading texts closely and carefully in context • Appreciating and evaluating positions in order to discern their fundamental principles • Writing clearly, insightfully, and in a well-ordered manner • Engaging respectfully and constructively in philosophical conversation • Constructing and assessing arguments and evaluating their formal structures MINOR IN PHILOSOPHY (6) The minor in Philosophy is designed to strengthen any major, broaden
    [Show full text]
  • Hannah Arendt's Shared Destiny with Rahel Varnhagen
    Hannah Arendt’s Shared Destiny with Rahel Varnhagen Hannah Arendt’s Shared Destiny with Rahel Varnhagen Donald J.Goldstein, Henley-Putnam University, San Jose, California, USA "All my life I considered myself Rahel and nothing else."1 ---Hannah Arendt Hannah Arendt was one of the most formidable philosophers and political commentators of the twentieth century. She left behind an enormous corpus of books that cover the range of topics of ontology, epistemology, political theory, linguistic analysis and historiography. She ignited debates that still rage on the Holocaust, civil rights, the ideal human life and the future of humankind. She was a Jew by birth and a Zionist by vocation, yet her writings transcend both characterizations. Arendt never renounced her Judaism, although she was entirely secular and distanced herself from her origins, not in rejection, but in an attempt to become an authentic actor/intellectual in the modern world. In an exchange of letters with her dissertation adviser, Karl Jaspers, Arendt explained: She was not trying to reify the “fate of Jews” by rooting Rahel in determinism of social condition and inheritance. Her work, instead, was a “preliminary” effort to indicate that a “certain possibility” which she “tentatively” called “fatefulness,” emerges in the process of conscious distancing from Jewish identity in order to recapture it more fully. It is the historical givenness of the Jewish people, which can be objectified so that it can be understood and reappropriated. This fatefulness . can occur only in a separation from Judaism.... An objectification is in fact there in a certain sense, but not an objectification of Jewish experience ..
    [Show full text]
  • An Arendtian Critique of Aristotle's Concept of Praxis1
    The End of Action: An Arendtian Critique of Aristotle’s Concept of praxis1 Jussi Backman University of Helsinki Introduction Arendt’s concept of action, which she distinguishes from other human activities as the eminently political activity, is often regarded as a renewal of Aristotle’s concept of praxis. Arendt’s own remarks easily lead us to think that she is simply “rehabilitating” action from its Aristotelian subordination to contemplation. I will argue that in interpreting contemplation in its pure self-referentiality as the supreme kind of praxis, Aristotle is, in fact, realigning the pre-philosophical notion of action itself along the lines of the teleological means-end structure of production (poiēsis). Consequently, Arendt’s critique of philosophy’s traditional “forgetfulness” of action, which she sees as ultimately culminating in the totalitarian substitution of social production for political action, can be understood as a critique of the Aristotelian notion of praxis as such, along with its presuppositions. The roots of this critique can be traced back to Heidegger’s reading of Aristotle. 1 I would like to thank the editors and Dana R. Villa for their valuable comments on this paper, as well as Julia Honkasalo, Krista Johansson, Mika Ojakangas, and other organizers for the opportunity to present an earlier version of it at the anniversary symposium Practice, Thought, and Judgment: Hannah Arendt 100 years (Helsinki, November 2006). Among other studies closely related to the topic of this paper, I would like to mention Jussi Backman, “Für das Wohnen denken: Heidegger, Arendt und die praktische Besinnung.” In Alfred Denker, Günter Figal, Franco Volpi & Holger Zaborowski (eds.), Heidegger-Jahrbuch, vol.
    [Show full text]
  • 08 the Banality of Evil
    THE BANALITY OF EVIL: CONTROVERSY AND COMPLEXITY OF A CONCEPT Margarida Amaral THE BANALITY OF EVIL: CONTROVERSY AND COMPLEXITY OF A CONCEPT Margarida Amaral Universidade Católica Portuguesa Sociedade Científica 49 Gaudium Sciendi, Nº 17, Dezembro 2019 The Banality of Evil: Controversy and Complexity of a Concept Margarida Amaral The controversy raised by the concept of "banality of evil". s portrayed in the film Hannah Arendt by Margarethe von Trotta, the author came to the concept of "banality of evil" after offering Aherself, as a reporter of the New Yorker , to cover Eichmann's trial in Jerusalem. The New Yorker ’s editor, William Shawn, then allowed Hannah Arendt, the author of the acclaimed book The Origins of Totalitarianism , to go to Jerusalem and attend this trial. Hannah Arendt’s decision would certainly be related to the fact that Eichmann was responsible for sending the Jewish women still interned in the Gurs camp, among which Hannah Arendt had been, to concentration camps. Attending this man's trial would mean, for Hannah Arendt, to face her past and to recover from the malaise associated with intense and terrible memories. 1 Considering Eichmann's statements to the police and in the court itself, Hannah Arendt came upon a man who, contrarily to what she assumed, was not a monster or a demon, but a vulgar man who did not think. Faithful, as she always seemed to be, to her thoughts, Hannah Arendt stated in the articles written for the New Yorker , and later in the book inspired by them ( Eichmann in Jerusalem: a Report on the 1 Hannah Arendt recognized the personal dimension inherent in the importance of attending Eichmann's trial.
    [Show full text]
  • Hannah Arendt's Thesis on Different Modes of Evil
    Hannah Arendt’s Thesis on Different Modes of Evil Jari Kauppinen University of Helsinki In my report of it [The Eichmann trial in Jerusalem] I spoke of “the banality of evil.” Behind that phrase, I held no thesis or doctrine, although I was dimly aware of the fact it went counter to our tradition of thought – literary, theological, or philosophic – about the phenomenon of evil. Hannah Arendt, The Life of the Mind The Thesis of Evil Hannah Arendt’s “thesis” of evil is well known. It starts with a famous claim: “The problem of evil will be the fundamental question of postwar intellectual life in Europe.”1 The Arendtian thesis or “doctrine” of evil consists of several different claims. The first and the most important one is the claim that evil is historical. Evil has different historical modes. In The Origins of Totalitarianism Arendt notes that without the Second World War “we might never have known the truly radical nature of Evil.”2 Thus, the problem concerns the temporality of evil: how can we distinguish the new evil from the old one? Terminologically, as often noticed, Arendt is inconsistent. She speaks about absolute evil, about “radical evil” in quotation marks, and once about radical evil without quotation marks.3 Usually commentators identify absolute evil with radical evil. It denotes the worst evil, although it is not clear that we cannot face something that would be worse than the historical situation to which Arendt refers. Hence, Arendt’s radical evil should not be confused with the Kantian radical 1 Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem.
    [Show full text]
  • Kriterion Miolo 110.P65 3/1/2005, 09:47294 PROLEGOMENON for an ETHICS of VISIBILITY in HANNAH ARENDT 295
    PROLEGOMENON FOR AN ETHICS OF VISIBILITY IN HANNAH ARENDT* Bethânia Assy** ABSTRACT This paper aims to discuss the Arendtian notions of appearance and perception in order to promote a displacement of those conceptions from the generally associated domain of passive apprehension of the faculty of knowledge towards the domain of a praxiology of action and language, based on an active perception. Arendt’s appropriations on the Heideggerian “to take one’s <it> place” (sich hin-stellen) will be discussed, as well as the Augustinian “finding oneself in the world” (diligere). A twofold disposition of appearance will be distinguished: producing and position, whose transposed to the Arendtian notion of world correspond, respectively, to fabrication (poiesis) of the world, man’s objective in-between space, and to action (praxis) in the world, man’s subjective in-between space. Those conceptual replacements, in a broad sense, uphold a closer imbrication between the activities of the mind and acting, stricto sensu, and consequently, foment not only the valorization of the public space, but the visibility of our acts and deeds as well, calling out the dignity of appearance in ethics. Key-words Ethics of visibility, Hannah Arendt, Martin Heidegger, Active Perception, Appearance * Paper delivered at Prof. Axel Honneth’s Forschungskolloquium zur Sozialphilosophie in the Philosophy Department at Frankfurt University during my stay as visiting scholar in the Summer Semester/2003. An the same occasion this paper was also delivered at Kolloquium des Hannah Arendt-Zentrums, at the Carl Von Ossietzky University, Oldenburg, directed by Antonia Grunenberg. I am particularly in debt to the comments of Antonia Grunenberg, Hans Scheulen, Zoltan Szankay, Francisco Ortega, Axel Honneth, Rainer Forst and Rahel Jaeggi.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography
    Bibliography Abbreviations ASDErasmioperaomnia, Amsterdam, 1969–. CAH2 The Cambridge AncientHistory,2nd ed., Cambridge, 1984–2005. CIL Corpus Inscriptionum Latinarum,Berlin, 1863–. DIVO Elisa Guadagnini and Giulio Vaccaro, Dizionario dei volgarizzamenti,http://tlion. sns.it/divo/. Eph.Tull. Ephemerides Tullianae,https://www.tulliana.eu/ephemerides/frames.htm. FRHist Timothy Cornell(ed.), The Fragments of the Roman Historians,Oxford, 2013. FRP Adrian S. Hollis (ed.), Fragments of Roman Poetry.c.60BC–AD 20,Oxford,2009. GL Heinrich Keil (ed.), Grammatici Latini,Leipzig, 1857–1880. LB JeanLeClerc(ed.), Desiderii Erasmi Operaomnia,Leiden, 1703–1706. MRR T. RobertS.Broughton, The Magistrates of the Roman Republic,New York, 1951– 1952 (Supplement1986 supersedes Suppl. 1960). OLD2 Peter G.W.Glare(ed.), Oxford Latin Dictionary, 2nd ed., Oxford2012. ORF4 EnricaMalcovati (ed.), Oratorum Romanorum fragmenta,4th ed., Torino 1976. Throughout this volume, references to ancient works aregiven according to the abbreviations of the OxfordClassical Dictionary. ForRenaissanceauthors,weused the abbreviations of Johann Ramminger’swebsite Neulateinische Wortliste. Ein Wörterbuch des Lateinischen von Petrarca bis 1700 (http://www.neulatein.de/words/start.htm). Workscited Abbot 2000: James C. Abbot, The Aeneid and the Conceptofdolus bonus,in: “Vergilius” 46, 59–82. Achard 1981: Guy Achard, Pratique rhétorique et idéologie politique dans les discours ‘optimates’ de Cicéron,Leiden. Ahl1976: Frederik M. Ahl, Lucan. An Introduction,Ithaca/London. vonAlbrecht 2003: Michael von Albrecht, Cicero’sStyle.ASynopsis. Followed by Selected Analytic Studies,Leiden/Boston. Alfonsi 1975: Luigi Alfonsi, Dal proemio del De inventione alle virtutes del De officiis,in: “Ciceroniana” 2, 111–120. Allen 1906–1958: Percy Stafford Allen et al. (eds.), Opus epistolarum Des. Erasmi Roterodami,Oxford.
    [Show full text]
  • Hannah Arendt and the Faculty of Thinking- a Partner to Think, a Witness To
    Revista Ética & Filosofia Política (Volume 9, Número 1, junho/2006) Hannah Arendt and The Faculty of Thinking- 1 A Partner to Think, a Witness to Act Bethânia Assy2 “Thinking was her [Arendt’s] passion, and thinking with her was a moral activity. She was intensely moral, but completely unmoralistic.” 3 (Hans Jonas) I. A Vision in Thought – The ‘Outward Sensible Appearance’ of the Mind The intriguing paradoxical condition of the faculty of thinking allows “the mind to withdraw from the world without ever being able to leave it or transcend it.”4 It justifies in the first place the use of metaphorical language, imagination and re-presentation, to quote the terms Arendt uses to articulate the imbrications among thinking, judging, speech, and the visible world. Either in silent critical thought or in judgment, what is at stake are the outlooks and events of the appearing world transposed into ordinary language.5 In the case of thinking activity, a silent “conceptual metaphorical speech” turns to be its adequate operation, since thinking “must prepare the particulars given to the sense in such a way that the mind is able to handle them in their absence; it must, in brief, de-sense them.”6 Thinking is already conceived into speech before it is communicated, spoken out and understood by others. Likewise, thinking requires this same visibility of being heard and understood by others, “just as a creature endowed with the sense of vision is meant to see and to be seen. Thought without speech is inconceivable; ‘thought and speech anticipate one another. They continually take each other’s place.’”7 Thought derives from human beings lived experience and therefore must remain tied to them.
    [Show full text]