The Wall Or the Door: German Realism Around 1800

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Wall Or the Door: German Realism Around 1800 The Wall or the Door: German Realism around 1800 De muur of de deur: Duits realism rond 1800 (met een samenvatting in het Nederlands) Proefschrift ter verkrijging van de graad van doctor aan de Universiteit Utrecht op gezag van de rector magnificus, prof.dr. G.J. van der Zwaan, ingevolge het besluit van het college voor promoties in het openbaar te verdedigen op woensdag 19 juni 2017 des middags te 2.30 uur door Tom Giesbers geboren op 23 juni 1985 te ‗s-Hertogenbosch Promotor: Prof.dr. P.G. Ziche Co-Promotor: Dr. D.K.W. van Miert In memory of my father ISBN: 978-94-6103-062-7 Acknowledgements: This book was made possible through generous funding from the NWO (Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research), as part of the project ‗Thinking classified - Structuring the world of ideas around 1800‘ (project number 360-20-330). I want to thank Paul Ziche for his enduring support. Over the last four years, he has been exceptionally encouraging with regards to my own commitment to independent research and new ideas. I also want to thank Fred Beiser and Joan Farrenkopf for making me feel welcome during my stay in Syracuse, NY during my stay there as a Fulbright scholar. I am also grateful for Ives Radrizzani, for graciously making the manuscript of the Denkbücher available. Finally, in my personal life, I want to thank my partner, Eline Janszen, and my family and friends for their help, in providing invaluable warmth and leisurely activities during the last four years. Table of contents: Introduction 1 1. The Pantheismusstreit: proto-realist origins 17 2. Realism around 1800 as negative realism 40 2.1 Jacobi‘s negative realism 40 2.2 Herder as a realist 99 2.3 Reinhold as a realist 139 2.4 Johann Neeb: ‗the senses are not the gateways to things‘ 156 2.5 Conclusion 168 3. German realism and the origins of philosophical nihilism 175 4. Jacobi‘s practical philosophy in the Werke 215 5. The limits of philosophy 265 5.1 Fichte‘s response to realism in the 1804-1805 Berlin lectures 265 5.2 Krug‘s pen and the emergence of relativism 299 6. Realism around 1800 and realism in the 19th century 1800 313 Conclusion 351 Appendix 1: Biographical information 364 Appendix 2: Realist dictionary 373 Literature 376 Summary (in Dutch) 387 Introduction 1. Realism as a philosophical position One of the most prominent defenses of philosophical realism was put forward by George Edward Moore. In 1903, he presented his hands as external objects in the world and concluded from this that an external world with at least two objects in it exists. Moore here clearly understood realism as a common-sense attitude for which one can argue by relying on ordinary perception and understanding. For many decades, this kind of realism, argued for by common-sense arguments, has been an archetype of philosophical realism. Another important development in thinking about realism in the 20th century has been scientific realism, which is concerned with the specific truth of scientific theories. In more recent years, drawing on the German idealist, phenomenological and French philosophical traditions, a continental realism has emerged. Some adherents to this realism are Quentin Meillassoux and Markus Gabriel. The type of realism that I will cover within the space of this book will be familiar to none of these types of realists. First of all, it will seem unfamiliar because it is a reconstruction of realism in a time period and in a context (German philosophy in 1780- 1820) that is normally considered to be far from realist in outlook. Instead, the standard accounts of the history of philosophy characterize this period as the heyday of German idealism. Secondly, the realism covered in this book will seem unfamiliar because it is of a kind that no one today would readily associate with that term. In the Moore-tradition, we have come to associate realism with a resolutely common-sense approach. In everyday understanding, ―realism‖ came to mean that we take things at face value. Because the kind of realism I am going to present here is so alien to our assumptions, I have even heard some scholars of German philosophy claim that there was no German realism to match German idealism. If I can show that there is a kind of 1 German realism around this time, we will have to adjust our notion of what realism can be, as well as rethink the trajectory of the history of philosophy and the history of the concept of realism. And if we are not to quarrel over the meaning of the term ―realism‖, then we will have to admit at least another conception of realism alongside these more traditional and contemporary forms of realism. I therefore take up two general tasks for this book. First of all, I must make it plausible that there is indeed a realism or realist movement present in this period. One might expect this to be a difficult task considering my claim that German realism around 1800 is very different from what we now likely associate with realism. Fortunately, the historical material bears out this point beyond all doubt. This should be clear already from the fact that a number of books have ―realism― placed emphatically in their titles, such as Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi‘s David Hume über den Glauben, oder Idealismus und Realismus (1787), Erhard Georg Friedrich Wrede‘s Antilogie des Realismus und Idealismus (1791), Joseph Rückert‘s Der Realismus, oder, Grundsätze zu einer durchaus praktischen Philosophie (1801) and Franz Joseph Molitor‘s Der Wendepunkt des Antiken und Modernen oder Versuch den Realismus mit dem Idealismus zu versöhnen (1805). The first clear indication that there was a realism around this time, and moreover that realism indeed formed a broader philosophical movement, can be found in Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi‘s claim in David Hume über den Glauben, oder Idealismus und Realismus (1787) about what ‗we realists‘ believe (see [p.169]). This publication was enormously popular as well as influential for the early reception and criticism of Kant‘s philosophy. Jacobi will therefore be our principal figure, and I will show, throughout my book, that there are many other references to realism and many other uses of Jacobi‘s realist arguments in the public debate in Jacobi‘s time. My second task is to elaborate exactly what systematic commitments these realists have. In order to achieve 2 this, I will not compare it to a notion of realism that is familiar to today‘s readers, because this will not help us in understanding what concerns motivated the realists, and how these influenced their arguments and methodology. Since we tend to be much more aware of these concerns where today‘s types of realism are concerned, a direct comparison would not provide a very enlightening encounter, because we would hold realism around 1800 to our own standards without an attempt to reconstruct what their own standards were. Beyond these two concerns, which primarily aim at answering the reader‘s initial questions encountering this book, I also want to partialy answer the question likely to arise once a reader is satisfied with my answers to the above two concerns, namely, the question: Why, if the realists movement was really so important, have nearly all accounts of the history of philosophy forgotten German realism around 1800? There are some notable exceptions, such as, Zöller (2000) and Pluder (2012). But a first, tentative answer to this question has in fact already been given, at least in as far as today‘s accounts are concerned: Philosophical scholarship is not aware of this type of realism because it is so very different from today‘s versions of realism. It is so different in fact, that it is hard to identify as a realism at all, despite authors like Jacobi claiming that they are realists. We will, in part, show how German realism around 1800 was slowly changed into a, to modern eyes at least, more recognizable type of realism during the 19th century. For now, it is important to realize that realism around 1800 emerged in a period in which many terms were still without a canonical definition or a clear semantic range (cf. realism, empiricism) and many philosophical terms were only just being coined (cf. relativism, nihilism). The degree to which terminology changed, or was given novel meaning, is indicated by the fact that the realists, at no point in the debate, or in their private correspondence, make any effort to compare or connect their type 3 of realism to the medieval type, and Jacobi explicitly emphasizes that it is a wholly new kind of realism. The title of this book refers to a question that Johann Georg Hamann poses to Jacobi in response to the latter‘s attempt to formulate his philosophical position, which we will recount in chapter 1. Throughout the book we will, at times, return to this issue. Hamann gives us two options for reading a philosophical position, as a wall or as a door. This can still be worked out in several different ways, which is why I utilize this imagery as a versatile way of gauging the development of realism. The tension this imagery introduces between a wall and a door suggests a blockage and a passageway respectively, thereby giving the wall a negative connotation. However, in relation to the Kantian project, we can also construe the wall as a limiting project, which curtails illegitimate incursions and protects a sanctuary. The door then becomes an opening onto uncertain vistas. As I‘ll show, the full range of these vistas can be found with the realists.
Recommended publications
  • Kant, Hegel, Schelling, Nietzsche, and Heidegger
    German Philosophers: Kant, Hegel, Schelling, Nietzsche, and Heidegger Daniel Ferrer at Matrin Heidegger’s Todtnauberg haunt (Die Hütte, Rütte, Todtnauberg, Black Forest, Schwarzwald, Germany) By Daniel Fidel Ferrer 1 2011 Daniel Fidel Ferrer. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, digital, optical or by any information storage and retrieval system now known or hereafter invented; or otherwise without the prior permission in writing and signed by the author, Daniel Fidel Ferrer. Photo of Daniel Fidel Ferrer at Heidegger’s Todtnauberg haunt copyright ©Daniel Fidel Ferrer. Photo taken by Dr. Harald van Veghel with my 35 MM camera. Location: front page, title page. Die Hütte, Rütte, Todtnauberg, Black Forest, Schwarzwald, Germany, Deutschland. Some brief cataloging. Ferrer, Daniel Fidel (1952- ) German Philosophers: Kant, Hegel, Schelling, Nietzsche, and Heidegger Includes bibliographical references. Index. 1. Ontology. 2. Metaphysics. 3. Philosophy, German. 4.Thought and thinking. 5. Kant, Immanuel, 1724-1804. 6. Schelling, Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von, 1775-1854. 7. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 1770-1831. 8. Philosphy, Asian. 9. Philosophy, Indic. 10. Philosophy, Modern -- 20th century. 11. Philosophy, Modern -- 19th century. 12. Practice (Philosophy). 13. Philosophy and civilization. 14. Postmodernism. 15. Nietzsche, Friedrich Wilhelm, 1844-1900. 16. Heidegger, Martin, 1889-1976. -- 17. g r una nd cent. I. Ferrer, Daniel Fidel, 1952-. Dedication and Acknowledgements Family members. Families: Ferrer, Reavis, Kuhn, Lindstrom, Schmidt, and Yeager.
    [Show full text]
  • Laws of Thought and Laws of Logic After Kant”1
    “Laws of Thought and Laws of Logic after Kant”1 Published in Logic from Kant to Russell, ed. S. Lapointe (Routledge) This is the author’s version. Published version: https://www.routledge.com/Logic-from-Kant-to- Russell-Laying-the-Foundations-for-Analytic-Philosophy/Lapointe/p/book/9781351182249 Lydia Patton Virginia Tech [email protected] Abstract George Boole emerged from the British tradition of the “New Analytic”, known for the view that the laws of logic are laws of thought. Logicians in the New Analytic tradition were influenced by the work of Immanuel Kant, and by the German logicians Wilhelm Traugott Krug and Wilhelm Esser, among others. In his 1854 work An Investigation of the Laws of Thought on Which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities, Boole argues that the laws of thought acquire normative force when constrained to mathematical reasoning. Boole’s motivation is, first, to address issues in the foundations of mathematics, including the relationship between arithmetic and algebra, and the study and application of differential equations (Durand-Richard, van Evra, Panteki). Second, Boole intended to derive the laws of logic from the laws of the operation of the human mind, and to show that these laws were valid of algebra and of logic both, when applied to a restricted domain. Boole’s thorough and flexible work in these areas influenced the development of model theory (see Hodges, forthcoming), and has much in common with contemporary inferentialist approaches to logic (found in, e.g., Peregrin and Resnik). 1 I would like to thank Sandra Lapointe for providing the intellectual framework and leadership for this project, for organizing excellent workshops that were the site for substantive collaboration with others working on this project, and for comments on a draft.
    [Show full text]
  • Kantian Reason and Hegelian Spirit
    GARY DORRIEN is the Reinhold Niebuhr and Kantian Reason What role, if any, did Immanuel Kant and Professor of Social Ethics at Union post-Kantian idealists such as Hegel play in Theological Seminary and Professor of “I have always told students that one cannot understand modern theology, including shaping modern theology? In Kantian Reason Religion at Columbia University. He is the Barthian theology, without a firm grasp of Kant. Dorrien’s work substantiates this and Hegelian Spirit, noted theologian Gary author of more than a dozen books, including Dorrien argues that Kantian and post-Kantian the highly acclaimed trilogy The Making of claim with an attention to detail that is nothing short of breathtaking. This book Hegelian Spirit idealism were instrumental in the foundation Liberal Theology (2001, 2003, 2006), and Social is a brilliant and much needed account of the influence of Immanuel Kant and the and development of modern Christian Ethics in the Making: Interpreting an American theology. Tradition (Wiley-Blackwell, 2008, 2010). tradition of post-Kantian idealism on modern theology.” William Stacy Johnson, Princeton Theological Seminary In this thought-provoking new work, Dorrien contends that while pre-Kantian rationalism offered a critique of religion’s authority, it “This is a brilliant and much needed book. Dorrien’s magisterial achievements to date held no theory about the creative powers lend his voice a special authority, but in this book, the reader is simply compelled of mind, nor about the spiritual ground and unifying reality of freedom. As Kant by the deft interplay of nuance and overview to trust his mentorship.
    [Show full text]
  • Foundations of Psychology by Herman Bavinck
    Foundations of Psychology Herman Bavinck Translated by Jack Vanden Born, Nelson D. Kloosterman, and John Bolt Edited by John Bolt Author’s Preface to the Second Edition1 It is now many years since the Foundations of Psychology appeared and it is long out of print.2 I had intended to issue a second, enlarged edition but the pressures of other work prevented it. It would be too bad if this little book disappeared from the psychological literature. The foundations described in the book have had my lifelong acceptance and they remain powerful principles deserving use and expression alongside empirical psy- chology. Herman Bavinck, 1921 1 Ed. note: This text was dictated by Bavinck “on his sickbed” to Valentijn Hepp, and is the opening paragraph of Hepp’s own foreword to the second, revised edition of Beginselen der Psychologie [Foundations of Psychology] (Kampen: Kok, 1923), 5. The first edition contains no preface. 2 Ed. note: The first edition was published by Kok (Kampen) in 1897. Contents Editor’s Preface �����������������������������������������������������������������������ix Translator’s Introduction: Bavinck’s Motives �������������������������� xv § 1� The Definition of Psychology ���������������������������������������������1 § 2� The Method of Psychology �������������������������������������������������5 § 3� The History of Psychology �����������������������������������������������19 Greek Psychology .................................................................19 Historic Christian Psychology ..............................................22
    [Show full text]
  • Between "Bildung" and "Wissenschaft": the 19Th-Century German Ideal of Scientific Education by Bas Van Bommel
    Between "Bildung" and "Wissenschaft": The 19th-Century German Ideal of Scientific Education by Bas van Bommel Prior to the 19th century, poetry, rhetoric, historiography and moral philosophy were considered particularly valuable to humane education, as they transmitted knowledge of beauty, goodness and truth. These so‐called "fine sciences" ("schöne Wissenschaften") were discredited by Immanuel Kant, who no longer recognised values as objects of scientific knowledge. Kant advanced an ideal of "rigorous science" entailing a novel concept of "scientific education" ("wissenschaftliche Bildung"): through methodically exploring the harmonious totality of human knowledge, the human mind would take on a correspondingly harmonious form. In the course of the 19th century, the disciplinary differentiation and specialisation that resulted from the new concept of rigorous science proved ever more difficult to reconcile with the educational ideal that had once been its motivating force. TABLE OF CONTENTS 1. Introduction 2. Bildung in the late 18th century: schöne Wissenschaften 3. The Kantian turn 4. Classical philology as "pure science": Friedrich August Wolf 5. Bildung transformed: classical philology as an educational science 6. The educational value of the natural sciences 7. The institutional impact of the German concept of scientific education 8. Scientific education abroad 9. The conflict between science and education 10. Conclusion 11. Appendix 1. Sources 2. Literature 3. Notes Indices Citation Introduction Mathematics and the natural sciences have worked their way up to unsuspected heights, and ... acquired a classicism that can almost compete with the aesthetic classicism of ancient literature.1 Without a doubt, the most influential concept in German university history is that of the "unity of teaching and research" ("Einheit von Lehre und Forschung").
    [Show full text]
  • Universidade Do Estado Do Rio De Janeiro Centro De Ciências Sociais Instituto De Filosofia E Ciências Humanas Gabriel Dirma De
    Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro Centro de Ciências Sociais Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas Gabriel Dirma de Araujo Leitão Friedrich Jacobi sobre a crença, ou realismo e idealismo transcendental Rio de Janeiro 2017 Gabriel Dirma de Araujo Leitão Friedrich Jacobi sobre a crença, ou realismo e idealismo transcendental Tese apresentada como requisito parcial para a obtenção do título de Doutor em Filosofia, ao Programa de Pós-graduação em Filosofia, da Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro. Área de concentração: Filosofia Moderna e Contemporânea. Orientador: Prof. Dr. Ricardo José Corrêa Barbosa Rio de Janeiro 2017 CATALOGAÇÃO NA FONTE UERJ/REDE SIRIUS/ BIBLIOTECA CCS/A L533 Leitão, Gabriel Dirma de Araujo Friedrich Jacobi sobre a crença, ou realismo e idealismo transcendental / Gabriel Dirma de Araujo Leitão. – 2017. 291f. Orientador: Ricardo José Corrêa Barbosa.. Tese (Doutorado) - Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro. Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas. Bibliografia. 1. Filosofia alemã - Teses. 2. Idealismo alemão – Teses. 3. Realismo – Teses. I. Barbosa, Ricardo José Corrêa, 1961-. II. Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro. Instituto de Filosofia e Ciências Humanas. III. Título. CDU 1(430) Autorizo, apenas para fins acadêmicos e científicos, a reprodução total ou parcial desta tese, desde que citada a fonte. ______________________________ ___________________________ Assinatura Data Gabriel Dirma de Araujo Leitão Friedrich Jacobi sobre a crença, ou realismo e idealismo transcendental Tese apresentada, como requisito parcial para a obtenção do título de Doutor em Filosofia, ao Programa de Pós-graduação em Filosofia, da Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro. Área de concentração: Filosofia Moderna e Contemporânea.
    [Show full text]
  • Hume, Jacobi, and Common Sense
    1 HUME, JACOBI, AND COMMON SENSE AN EPISODE IN THE RECEPTION OF HUME IN GERMANY AT THE TIME OF KANT Jacobi's dispute with Mendelssohn over the alleged Spinozism of Lessing 0 was to be important for the development of subsequent German philosophy, especially because it quickly became intertwined with the reception of Kant's critical philosophy. So far as this paper is concerned, however, we are inter- ested in it only because in the course of it Jacobi appealed to Hume's authority to defend his use of the term "faith" or "belief" (both rendered in German as Glaube ). This appeal, as we shall see, set in motion as intricate a play of conflicting views as can be found in the history of philosophy. It forced hidden ambiguities to light, and exposed conceptual affinities and differences where none would have been suspected. Jacobi himself did not have Hume particularly in mind in his original attack on Mendelssohn. His concern was to publicize what he took to be the Spinozistic implications of Enlightenment philosophy. Yet one can understand why, in retrospect, Jacobi could have appealed to Hume's authority. For Jacobi's brief against Mendelssohn was based on the claim that, when divorced from its basis in sensations and left to its own devices, reason could quite consistently argue itself into conclusions untenable at the level of common experience. Jacobi had accordingly pleaded with Mendelssohn to abandon his rationalistic ways, and to heed to a more primordial authority than that of philosophy--namely to an innate certainty about what is real, a certainty that animates our experiences from the beginning and pervades all levels of language.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Practical Postulates and the Limits of the Critical System
    Kant’s Practical Postulates and the Limits of the Critical System Sebastian Gardner The topic that I wish to consider is the significance, both systematic and historical, for Kant’s system as a whole, of the postulates of pure practical reason, more specifically, of the two theological postulates concerning the existence of God and personal immortality which form the basis of Kant’s moral theology. My discussion will focus on the problems of Kant’s moral theology in the eyes of his early contemporaries, for whom it constituted a crux in Kant’s project. Different views were taken by Kant’s contemporaries of what exactly these problems signified regarding the future of Critical philosophy. For the thinkers I will be looking at here, the miscarriage of the moral theology constituted a fatal fault in the Kantian project. For the German Idealists, the moral theology instead provided a vital clue as to how the Kantian system could be transformed into a more radical idealism, while confirming that it needed to be. The role of the practical postulates in the development of German Idealism demands a separate treatment; what I will argue here is simply that the practical postulates do indeed represent a point at which Kant’s philosophical system displays a deep and interesting tension, in light of which both historical responses are prima facie intelligible. I. Kant on practical cognition Let me begin with some examples of Kant’s use, in connection with the moral theology and practical postulation, of the concept of practical cognition, praktische Erkenntnis. The following, key statements are taken from the second and third Critiques: [T]he concept of freedom, insofar as its reality is proved by an apodictic law of practical reason, constitutes the keystone of the whole structure of a system of pure reason, even of speculative reason; and all other concepts (those of God and immortality) ..
    [Show full text]
  • On James's Arguments for Freedom, and Their Relation to Kant's
    8. Round Kant or Through Him? On James’s Arguments for Freedom, and their Relation to Kant’s Robert Stern My title is a reference to a famous remark that James makes about Kant: I believe that Kant bequeathes to us not one single conception which is both indispensable to philosophy and which philosophy either did not possess before him, or was not destined inevitably to acquire after him through the growth of men’s reflection upon the hypotheses by which science interprets nature. The true line of philosophic progress lies, in short, it seems to me, not so much through Kant as round him to the point where now we stand. (WWJ 5:139)1 This comes at the end of his 1904 essay “The Pragmatic Method,” where he is arguing that Kant’s critical philosophy is not really much of an advance on the approach of the “English- speaking philosophers,” who he sees as the ancestors of pragmatism insofar as they “introduced the custom of interpreting the meaning of conceptions by asking what difference they make for life.” “Thus,” James claims, “when all is said and done, it was they, not Kant, who introduced ‘the critical method’ into philosophy, the one method fitted to make philosophy a study worthy of serious men. For what seriousness can possibly remain in debating philosophic propositions that will never make an appreciable difference to us in action? And what matters it, when all propositions are practically meaningless, which of them be called true or false?” Given this 1 References to James 1975-88 are given with the abbreviation WWJ, followed by volume and page number.
    [Show full text]
  • Jacobi and the Pantheism Controversy
    · Chapter 2 . Jacobi and the Pantheism Controversy 2.1. The Historical Significance of the Pantheism Controversy Along with the publication of the Kritik der reinen Vernunft in May 1781, the most significant intellectual event in late eighteenth-century Germany was the so-called pantheism controversy between F. H. Jacobi and Moses Mendelssohn. 1 The controversy began in the summer of 1783,2 initially as a private quarrel between Jacobi and Mendelssohn. But, two years later, the dispute became public and engaged almost all the best minds of late eighteenth-century Germany. Among the celebrities who took part in it were Kant, Herder, Goethe, and Hamann. Furthermore, each party to the dispute had a large supporting cast, including such later stars as Thomas Wizen­ mann, who defended Jacobi, and Karl Leonhard Reinhold, who popularized Kant. It is difficult to imagine a controversy whose cause was so incidental­ Jacobi's disclosure of Lessing's Spinozism-and whose effects were so great. The pantheism controversy completely changed the intellectual map of eigh­ teenth-century Germany; and it continued to preoccupy thinkers well into the nineteenth century. The main problem raised by the controversy-the dilemma of a rational nihilism or an irrational fideism-became a central issue for Fichte, Schelling, Hegel, Kierkegaard, and Nietzsche. It is indeed no exaggeration to say that the pantheism controversy had as great an impact upon nineteenth-century philosophy as Kant's first Kritik. 3 The first and most visible effect of the controversy was the remarkable rise in the fortunes of Spinozism in Germany. Nearly all the major figures of the classical Goethezeit-Goethe, Novalis, Holderlin, Herder, F.
    [Show full text]
  • „Oh, Was Ein Langsamer Deutscher Nicht Alles Fragt!”*
    Eötvös Loránd Tudományegyetem Bölcsészettudományi Kar DOKTORI DISSZERTÁCIÓ UTASI KRISZTINA ÉSZ ÉS KINYILATKOZTATÁS KÖZÖTT. A FRAGMENTENSTREIT ESZTÉTIKATÖRTÉNETI JELENTŐSÉGÉRŐL Filozófiatudományi Doktori Iskola Doktori Iskola vezetője: Dr. Kelemen János egyetemi tanár Esztétika Doktori Iskola Esztétika Doktori Iskola vezetője: Dr. Radnóti Sándor egyetemi tanár A bizottság tagjai és tudományos fokozatuk: A bizottság elnöke: Dr. Bacsó Béla, az MTA doktora Hivatalosan felkért bírálók: Dr. Radnóti Sándor, az MTA doktora Dr. Horváth károly, PhD A bizottság titkára: Dr. Szécsényi Endre, PhD A bizottság további tagjai: Dr. Weiss János, az MTA doktora Dr. Papp Zoltán, PhD Dr. Pintér Tibor, PhD Témavezető: Dr. Balassa Péter, az MTA doktora Dr. Fodor Géza, az MTA doktora 2 „Oh, was ein langsamer Deutscher nicht alles fragt!”* „Azt mondja a rest: ordító oroszlán van az úton! Oroszlán van az utcákon!”** 3 Tartalom Bevezetés 4 1. A ’lassú német’: Gotthold Ephraim Lessing 12 2. Taktika és vívótudomány: Schmidt és Goeze 42 3. A ’névtelen’ és töredékei 58 4. Tudós háborúk 82 5. Szünet a teológiai harcban 105 Exkurzus: Mendelssohn ’élő írás’ fogalma 132 6. Gyűrűk és ékkövek: az igaz vallás mibenlétének kérdése 150 7. A költői nyelv alkalmazásának elméleti háttere 171 8. Válasz egy felesleges kérdésre: Nathan der Weise 194 9. A Nathan der Weise mint Anti-Candide 218 Appendix 239 Bibliográfia 242 4 Bevezetés „Endlich fiel man darauf, selbst das, was mich zu einem so langsamen oder wie es meinen wüstigen Freunden scheint, so faulen Arbeiter macht, selbst das man mir nutzen zu wollen: Die Kritik.”1 A lessingi életművet vagy annak egyes szegmenseit szisztematikus szempontok alapján feldolgozni kívánó kutató nincs irigylésre méltó helyzetben, hisz munkája többszörösen is akadályokba ütközik.
    [Show full text]
  • TLH 23 April 2017 MASTER-FIN.Vp
    THE COLLECTED WORKS OF HERMAN DOOYEWEERD Series B, Volume 14 GENERAL EDITOR: D.F.M. Strauss Time, Law, and History SELECTED ESSAYS Herman Dooyeweerd Paideia Press Grand Rapids 2017 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Dooyeweerd, H. (Herman), 1894-1977. Time, Law, and History Herman Dooyeweerd. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and indexes ISBN 978-0-88815-202-2 (so!) This is Series B, Volume 14 in the continuing series The Collected Works of Herman Dooyeweerd (Paideia Press) ISBN 978-0-88815-202-2 The Collected Works comprise a Series A, a Series B, a Series C and a Series D Series A contains multi-volume works by Dooyeweerd, Series B contains smaller works and collections of essays, Series C contains reflections on Dooyeweerd's philosophy designated as: Dooyeweerd’s Living Legacy, and Series D contains thematic selections from Series A and B A CIP catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Copyright © 2017 The Dooyeweerd Centre for Christian Philosophy Redeemer University College, Ancaster, Ontario CANADA L9K 1J4 All rights reserved. For information contact: PAIDEIA PRESS Grand Rapids, MI 49507 www.reformationalpublishingproject.com Printed in the United States of America Time, Law, and History Herman Dooyeweerd SELECTED ESSAYS All articles in this volume are translated by Daniël Strauss Edited by Harry Van Dyke, Roy Clouser and David Hanson General Editor Daniël Strauss Foreword From a systematic and genetic point of view this Volume of Se- lected Essays is exceptional in various respects. The problem of time dealt with in the first part of this Volume could be seen as the fourth Volume of his magnum opus, De Wijsbegeerte der Wetsidee (1935-1936 – see page 1, footnote 1).
    [Show full text]