PHIL& 101, Introduction to Philosophy, Syllabus COURSE

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

PHIL& 101, Introduction to Philosophy, Syllabus COURSE PHIL& 101, Introduction to Philosophy, Syllabus Item number: 1905, Section: E, Winter 2017 Meets: DAILY at 12:30pm-1:20pm in R210 Instructor: Benjamin Hole E-mail: [email protected] Office location: B100 Office Hours: Daily, 10:20-10:35, and via email COURSE INFORMATION This course introduces some current and traditional problems in philosophy. Students examine diverse views and arguments and develop basic philosophy skills including critical reasoning and conceptual analysis. Specific questions include the following. What is Philosophy? What makes me the same person over time? Does God exist? How can we know? What is knowledge? Can we have knowledge of an external world? What is valuable? What makes an action morally permissible or impermissible? Do we have a duty to aid the less fortunate? Is abortion morally permissible? We will examine these questions and various answers to them through reading several philosophical texts, both historical and contemporary. We will pay particular attention to different methods of philosophical argumentation. Students will be encouraged not only to master the material itself but also to develop their own critical and philosophical skills. The format of this course will be a mixture of lecture and discussion. There are two main objectives: (1) to familiarize you with the ethical theory and controversies surrounding certain contemporary moral issues, thus helping you develop reasoned views on these (and related) issues, and (2) to help you sharpen your ability to think clearly and critically about such issues. BOOKS AND MATERIALS REQUIRED Required Philosophy: The Quest for Truth, Edited by Louis P. Pojman and Lewis Vaughn, Oxford University Press; 8th edition (2012). o PDFs of readings will be posted to accommodate earlier editions of the textbook; speak to me if you need help finding a reading. Turning Technologies Clicker There will be required PDF readings posted on the course website as well. Week Readings 1. 1/2-1/6 Syllabus Editors: “What is Philosophy?” (1-2; 33-52) Plato: “Socratic Wisdom” (1-18) 2. 1/9-1/13 Editors: “Knowledge” (185-188) Descartes: “Cartesian Doubt and the Search for Foundational Knowledge” (188-195) Editors: “Philosophy of Mind” (282-285) Descartes: “Substance Dualism” (285-292) 3. 1/16-1/20 Editors: “Philosophy of Religion” (53-58) Thomas Aquinas: “Five Ways” (58-61) St. Anselm and Gaunilo: “The Ontological Argument” (100-103) B.C. Johnson: “Why Doesn’t God Intervene to Prevent Evil?” (120-125) 4. 1/23-1/27 Editors: “Who am I? Do we have personal identity?” (360-364) John Locke: “Our Psychological Properties Define the Self” (365-368) In-class movie: The Singularity is Near Ray Kurzweil, Singularity Q&A (link) Nick Bostrom, Simulation Argument MP3 (15 minute podcast for philosophy bytes) 5. 1/30-2/3 Nick Bostrom and Rebecca Roache, “Ethical Issues in Human Enhancement” (Link) Editors: “Ethics” (474-477) Rachels: “Morality is Not Relative” (483-492) Rachels: “Divine Command Theory” (551-553) 6. 2/6-2/10 Jeremy Bentham (PDF) Robert Nozick, “The Experience Machine” (PDF) John Stuart Mill: “Utilitarianism” (537-543) 7. 2/13-2/17 Editors: “Do we have obligations to help the poor and hungry?” (712-714) Peter Singer, “Famine, Affluence, and Morality” (714-723) Garrett Hardin, “Living on a Lifeboat” (723-735) 8. 2/20-2/24 Immanuel Kant, “The Moral Law” (525-537) Thomas Mappes: “A Liberal View of Sexual Morality and the concept of Using Another Person” (PDF) 9. 2/27-3/3 Editors: “Contemporary Moral Problems” (645-647) Pope John Paul II, “The Unspeakable Crime of Abortion” (PDF) Mary Anne Warren, “On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion” (661-667) 10. 3/6-3/10 Don Marquis, “Why Abortion Is Immoral” (647-660) Judith Jarvis Thomson, “A Defense of Abortion” (667-679) 11. 3/13-3/17 Rosalind Hursthouse, “Virtue Ethics and Abortion” (PDF) Final review 12. Final Exam on Bellevue College Calendar Quarter Starts January 3, 2017 Holiday January 16, 2017 College issues day (no class) February 9, 2017 PD Day (no class) February 20, 2017 PD Day (no class) March 7, 2017 Final exams March 21-23, 2017 Quarter Ends March 23, 2017 COURSE OUTCOMES After completing this class, students should be able to: Distinguish and describe the major branches of philosophical inquiry Identify philosophical issues and explain them using basic philosophical vocabulary Discuss positions and arguments relevant to philosophical issues Formulate and evaluate philosophical arguments Motivate and explain their own philosophical views HOW OUTCOMES WILL BE MET “When students know the goals, are given opportunities to practice and get feedback, and are able to show their level of understanding— learning is supported.”1 STUDENTS ARE EXPECTED TO FAMILIARIZE THEMSELVES WITH THE GRADING MECHANICS AND TO TAKE RESPONSIBILITY FOR REGULATING THEIR OWN LEARNING PROCESS. This involves reading the syllabus carefully, thinking strategically about your performance in class, and being communicative with your instructor. Think metacognitively about your learning. Metacognition is the process of reflecting on and adjusting your own thinking. These thought processes help monitor and control your learning when you, for example: assess the task at hand, assess your own skills and knowledge, plan an approach to a task, apply strategies and monitor progress, reflect on whether approach is working, and/or make adjustments to your approach. Keep the final paper and exam in mind and continually think about ways to do well in the areas where you will be assessed. Discussion Participation 10% Clicker Quizzes 15% Midterm Exam 15% Outline of Final Paper 5% Peer Review of Final Paper 5% Final Paper 25% Final Exam 25% Total 100% GRADING Discussion Participation (10%): All students are expected to play an active role. Such participation presupposes regular attendance. Credit will be given for active engagement with the material, and for helpful interactions with others. We aim to establish an environment where mutual respect is accompanied by serious reflective engagement with the material. There is a grading rubric for your participation grade, also posted on the course website, which clarifies expectations and defines the elements of quality class participation. Active involvement in your learning increases what you remember, how well it is assimilated, and how you apply what you have learned in new contexts. You must, for example, articulate your thoughts about the topics discussed in class and submit them for critical examination by your peers. In listening to peers, you hear many different ways of interpreting and applying class material and therefore are better able to integrate and apply ideas to many examples. Clicker Quizzes (15%): Graded multiple choice and discussion questions will take place via Turning Technologies Clickers. These “quizzes” will be given randomly during most class sessions throughout the quarter. Some questions will be based on the readings to make sure you’re reading carefully and following along. Many questions will have no right or wrong answer and will just ask for your opinion about something we are discussing. Each student’s lowest five quiz grades will be dropped. This means that students can miss up to five quizzes without negatively impacting their overall grade. Each full day of Clicker questions will count as one “quiz”. This policy is designed to allow for unexpected technical problems (i.e., malfunctioning clicker) and absences (i.e., due to illness). Because of this, students will not be allowed to take make-up quizzes. The point of the daily quizzes 1 Ambrose, et al., How Learning Works: Seven Research-Based Principles for Smart Teaching (Jossey-Bass, 2010), 85. is to serve as low-stakes opportunities for assessment and to make sure that you are following the course material. Midterm Examination (15%): There will be an online midterm examination on 2/7. It will consist of multiple choice and short essay questions. The point of the exam is for you to show that you are familiar with a broad range of concepts and skills used in the class. Although the exam will be scheduled during class (with some leeway), since it is online, you will not be expected to attend in person. There is no in-person class the day of the midterm. Outline of Final Paper (5%). There will be an outline of your final paper due on 2/24, 11:59pm. The point of this assignment is to give you an opportunity to receive feedback on your argumentative structure before you submit your final paper. A prompt will be posted on the course website. Peer Review for Final Paper (5%). There will be a peer review for the final paper on 3/6. The point of this assignment is for you to collaborate with a peer to improve your final paper by reviewing the grading criteria and discussing how well your paper meets those standards. Participation in the review requires a full draft of the paper. You will be graded on the basis of participation and good faith effort. Final Examination (25%): There will be an online final examination, as scheduled by the College (https://www.bellevuecollege.edu/courses/exams/). It will consist of multiple choice and short essay questions. The point of the exam is for you to show that you are familiar with a broad range of concepts and skills used in the class. Although the exam will be scheduled during class (with some leeway), since it is online, you will not be expected to attend in person. There is no in-person class the day of the final. Final Paper (30%): The point of the paper is for you to demonstrate that you are familiar with a philosophical issue and are able to critically evaluate that view with philosophical rigor. Your critical evaluation is an opportunity for you to demonstrate the philosophical skills you have practiced throughout the term.
Recommended publications
  • Phil102: Intro to Philosophy: Knowledge & Reality
    PHIL102: INTRO TO PHILOSOPHY: KNOWLEDGE & REALITY section 3, schedule #22716 MW 4:00-5:15 pm in EBA 343 Dr. Robert Francescotti Office Hours (Arts & Letters, 438): Monday 5:45–7 pm, Wednesday 12:30–1:30 pm, & Thursday 2–4 pm Office phone & e-mail: 619-594-6585, [email protected] COURSE DESCRIPTION This course satisfies the Philosophy & Religious Studies section of the Humanities requirement of the Foundations of Learning component of the General Education requirements. - description in SDSU’s General Catalog: Introduction to philosophical inquiry with emphasis on problems of knowledge and reality. Students are encouraged to think independently and formulate their own tentative conclusions. - a fuller description of my section: You will learn about the philosophical method by exploring some main areas of philosophical interest. The first issue we will discuss is whether God exists. We will consider a few arguments designed to show that God exists along with an argument that aims to show that God does not exist. This first section of the course is a good introduction to the structure of argumentation (an essential tool of the philosophical method). Then we will investigate the Free Will debate. Science has shown that much of our behavior is the result of factors beyond our control. The environment in which we were raised obviously greatly affects our behavior. Non-conscious mental activity and genetic factors are also thought to play a major role. Of course, the state of one’s brain is a major culprit as well. However, if our actions are the result of these factors, which seem largely out of our control, then in what sense can we be considered “free”? And if we do not act in a truly free manner, then can we be held responsible for our actions? Many people believe that in addition to the body, there is some immaterial aspect to our being.
    [Show full text]
  • Aquinas and the Question of God's Existence: Exploring the Five Ways
    International Journal of Philosophy and Theology June 2018, Vol. 6, No. 1, pp. 19-32 ISSN: 2333-5750 (Print), 2333-5769 (Online) Copyright © The Author(s). All Rights Reserved. Published by American Research Institute for Policy Development DOI: 10.15640/ijpt.v6n1a3 URL: https://doi.org/10.15640/ijpt.v6n1a3 Aquinas and the Question of God’s Existence: Exploring the Five Ways Dr. Damian Ilodigwe1 Abstract Without doubt, St Thomas Aquinas was the greatest of the medieval philosophers. Aquinas was a prolific writer and he made contributions to virtually every area of Philosophy and Theology. His account of the existence of God is perhaps the best known aspect of his work. This is especially true of the celebrated five arguments he adduced in demonstration of the existence of God. In exploring Aquinas‟ Five ways, which some commentators regard as Aquinas‟ substantive contribution to Philosophy of religion, our contention is that they demonstrate the possibilities as well as the limits of natural theology, so far as while Aquinas does not deny that natural reason can establish the existence of God he nonetheless maintains that there are aspects of God‟s nature that can be known only through the means of divine revelation. Consequently unless we take into account the double emphasis on the possibilities and limits of natural theology, we are sure to underestimate the contemporary relevance of Aquinas‟ Five ways. Keywords: Aquinas, God’s Existence, Cosmological Arguments, Ontological Arguments, Anselm 1. Preamble Without doubt, St Thomas Aquinas was the greatest of the medieval philosophers. Aquinas was a prolific writer and he made contributions to virtually every area of Philosophy and Theology.
    [Show full text]
  • MID-TWENTIETH CENTURY NEO-THOMIST APPROACHES to MODERN PSYCHOLOGY Dissertation Submitted to the College of Arts and Sciences Of
    MID-TWENTIETH CENTURY NEO-THOMIST APPROACHES TO MODERN PSYCHOLOGY Dissertation Submitted to The College of Arts and Sciences of the UNIVERSITY OF DAYTON In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for The Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Theology By Matthew Glen Minix UNIVERSITY OF DAYTON Dayton, Ohio December 2016 MID-TWENTIETH CENTURY NEO-THOMIST APPROACHES TO MODERN PSYCHOLOGY Name: Minix, Matthew G. APPROVED BY: _____________________________________ Sandra A. Yocum, Ph.D. Dissertation Director _____________________________________ William L. Portier, Ph.D. Dissertation Reader. _____________________________________ Anthony Burke Smith, Ph.D. Dissertation Reader _____________________________________ John A. Inglis, Ph.D. Dissertation Reader _____________________________________ Jack J. Bauer, Ph.D. _____________________________________ Daniel Speed Thompson, Ph.D. Chair, Department of Religious Studies ii © Copyright by Matthew Glen Minix All rights reserved 2016 iii ABSTRACT MID-TWENTIETH CENTURY NEO-THOMIST APPROACHES TO MODERN PSYCHOLOGY Name: Minix, Matthew Glen University of Dayton Advisor: Dr. Sandra A. Yocum This dissertation considers a spectrum of five distinct approaches that mid-twentieth century neo-Thomist Catholic thinkers utilized when engaging with the tradition of modern scientific psychology: a critical approach, a reformulation approach, a synthetic approach, a particular [Jungian] approach, and a personalist approach. This work argues that mid-twentieth century neo-Thomists were essentially united in their concerns about the metaphysical principles of many modern psychologists as well as in their worries that these same modern psychologists had a tendency to overlook the transcendent dimension of human existence. This work shows that the first four neo-Thomist thinkers failed to bring the traditions of neo-Thomism and modern psychology together to the extent that they suggested purely theoretical ways of reconciling them.
    [Show full text]
  • The Five Ways from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Question 2) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) Translated by Brian Shanley (2006)
    The Five Ways from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Question 2) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) Question 2. Does God Exist? Article 1. Is the existence of God self-evident? It seems that the existence of God is self-evident: 1. Things are said to be self-evident to us when knowledge of them is naturally present in us, as is clear in the case of first principles. But, as Damascene says at the beginning of his book, “knowledge of the existence of God is naturally implanted in everyone.” Hence the existence of God is self-evident. 2. Things are said to be self-evident that are grasped as soon as the terms are grasped … ; for if I know what a whole is and what a part is, then I immediately know that every whole is greater than any of its parts. But if I understand what the name ‘God’ signifies, then it follows immediately that God exists. For by the name is signified “that than which a greater cannot be signified.” Now something is greater when it exists both in reality and in the intellect, rather than only in the intellect. Therefore, since when I understand this name ‘God,’ he immediately exists in the intellect, it follows that God must also exist in reality. Hence the existence of God is self- evident. 3. The existence of truth is self-evident, since someone who denies that there is truth concedes its existence: for if there is no truth, then it is true that there is no truth.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Evil
    3 The Problem of Evil For what is that which we call evil but the absence of good?1 espite being conceived in secular terms in much contemporary Dthought, the “problem of evil” has traditionally been a theological one concerned with the question of how to reconcile the existence of suf- fering, and hence evil, in the world, with the characterization of the Judeo-Christian God as benevolent, omniscient, and omnipotent. Formally articulated by Epicurus (341–270 BCE) and originally quoted in the work of Lactantius (c. 260–340 CE), the “problem of evil” is tradi- tionally presented as follows: God either wishes to take away evils, and is unable; or He is able, and is unwilling; or He is neither willing nor able, or He is both willing and able. If He is willing and is unable, He is feeble, which is not in accordance with the character of God; if He is able and willing, He is envious, which is equally at variance with God; if He is neither willing nor able, He is both envious and feeble and, therefore not God; if He is both willing and able, which alone is suitable to God, from what source then are evils? Or why does He not remove them?2 Presented syllogistically, the problem is this: God is benevolent. God is omnipotent (which should be taken to include omniscience). There is evil in the world. If the first two propositions are true, the third cannot be. R. Jeffery, Evil and International Relations © Renée Jeffery 2008 34 EVIL AND INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS Now the third is true as a matter of observable fact.
    [Show full text]
  • TWO ARGUMENTS of ST. ANSELM 1. in Proslogium II, St. Anselm
    APPENDIX TWO ARGUMENTS OF ST. ANSELM 1. In Proslogium II, St. Anselm argues as follows: And assuredly that than which no greater being can be conceived, cannot exist in the understanding alone. For suppose it exists in the understanding alone: then it can be conceived to exist in reality; which is greater. Therefore, if that than which nothing greater can be conceived exists in the understanding alone, the very being than which nothing greater can be conceived, is one, than which a greater can be conceived. But obviously this is impossible. Hence, there is no doubt that there exists a being, than which nothing greater can be conceived, and it exists both in the understanding and in reality. 1 I shall take "exists in the understanding alone" to mean "is logically possible but not actual", and I shall take "a being than which no greater can be conceived" to mean "a being than which no greater being is logically possible", i.e., "a maximally great being". Moreover, I shall take "[If X] exists in the understanding alone, [then] it can be conceived to exist in reality, which is greater" to mean "If X is merely logically possible, then it would be greater if it were actual"; and I shall take it that the bearer of the predicate "would be greater if it were actual" is, at least, a logically possible object. Given these interpretations, Anselm's argument can be restated as follows: (1) If there were a logically possible object which is a maximally great being and it were merely logically possible (rather than both logically possible and actual), then it would be greater if it were actual.
    [Show full text]
  • Why the Five Ways? Aquinas’S Avicennian Insight Into the Problem of Unity in the Aristotelian Metaphysics and Sacra Doctrina
    Why the Five Ways? Aquinas’s Avicennian Insight into the Problem of Unity in the Aristotelian Metaphysics and Sacra Doctrina Daniel D. De Haan Abstract: This paper will argue that the order and the unity of St. Thomas Aquinas’s five ways can be elucidated through a consideration of St. Thomas’s appropria- tion of an Avicennian insight that he used to order and unify the wisdom of the Aristotelian and Abrahamic philosophical traditions towards the existence of God. I will begin with a central aporia from Aristotle’s Metaphysics. Aristotle says that the science of first philosophy has three different theoretical vectors: ontology, aitiology, and theology. But how can all three be united into a single Aristotelian science? In his Metaphysics of the Healing, Avicenna resolved the impasse by tak- ing the ontological vector as the subject of metaphysics. He then integrated the question of the four first causes into the penultimate stage of his demonstration for the existence of God, thereby placing aitiological and theological questions among the ultimate concerns of a unified Aristotelian metaphysics. In the five ways, St. Thomas integrated Avicenna’s Aristotelian search for the first four causes into the last four of his five ways, by showing that each of the four aitiological orders terminate in an ultimate first cause that we call God. Finally, by appending the proof from the Physics to the beginning of the five ways, St. Thomas was able to show that the ultimate aim of both natural philosophy and metaphysics is the divine first principle, which is the beginning and subject of sacra doctrina.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is the Summa? Who Is St Thomas Aquinas?
    What is the Summa? The Summa Theologiae (written 1265–1274 and also known as the Summa Theologica or simply the Summa) is the best‐known work of Thomas Aquinas (c. 1225–1274). Although unfinished, the Summa is "one of the classics of the history of philosophy and one of the most influential works of Western literature."[1] It was intended as an instructional guide for moderate theologians and a compendium of all of the main theological teachings of the Catholic Church. It presents the reasoning for almost all points of Christian theology in the West. The Summa's topics follow a cycle: the existence of God; Creation, Man; Man's purpose; Christ; the Sacraments; and back to God. Among non‐scholars, the Summa is perhaps most famous for its five arguments for the existence of God known as the "five ways" .The five ways occupy one‐and‐a‐half pages of the Summa's approximately three thousand, five hundred pages. Throughout the Summa, Aquinas cites Christian, Muslim, Hebrew, and Pagan sources including but not limited to Christian Sacred Scripture, Aristotle, Augustine of Hippo, Avicenna, Averroes, Al‐Ghazali, Boethius, John of Damascus, Paul the Apostle, Dionysius the Areopagite, Maimonides, Anselm, Plato, Cicero, and Eriugena. The Summa is a more structured and expanded version of Aquinas's earlier Summa contra Gentiles, though these works were written for different purposes, the Summa Theologiae to explain the Christian faith to beginning theology students, and the Summa contra Gentiles to explain the Christian faith and defend it in hostile situations, with arguments adapted to the intended circumstances of its use, each article refuting a certain belief or a specific heresy.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Aquinas Stopped Commenting on Boethius's De Trinitate
    Studia Gilsoniana 9, no. 1 (January–March 2020): 167–188 ISSN 2300–0066 (print) ISSN 2577–0314 (online) DOI: 10.26385/SG.090106 Faustinus Ik. Ugwuanyi* Why Aquinas Stopped Commenting on Boethius’s De Trinitate Over the last decade, Aquinas’s commentaries on the two works of Boethius, De Trinitate and De Hebdomadibus, has prompted worries among scholars. The central question is why Aquinas had to comment upon these works of Boethius nearly seven hundred years after the death of Boethius. Having made my submission in the ongoing debate,1 I was yet confronted with another problem of why Aquinas did not con- tinue the commentary on Boethius’s De Trinitate. Note that Aquinas’s commentary stops at question six, article four without any explanation as to why, and this is before the point in the text where Boethius gets to the heart of the subject matter. This question sounds unlikely and, as such, I do not think it can be shown answered directly from the texts. Nevertheless, I believe that from the absence of a separate text on Aqui- nas’s reason for not continuing with the treatise of Boethius one may not conclude that such reasons do not exist. That such a conclusion would be premature can be clarified by comparison with the debate on the reasons behind his two commentaries on Boethius. Like the former, Aquinas produces no account for his reasons, but the intentions of changing the structural method of argument and the bid to establish the *Fr. Faustinus Ik. Ugwuanyi — John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin, Poland e-mail: [email protected] ▪ ORCID: 0000-0003-4755-2825 1 See Faustinus Ugwuanyi, “Aquinas’ Commentaries on Boethius’ Treatises: A Modi- fication or Interpretation?” Roczniki Kulturoznawcze 10, no.
    [Show full text]
  • Maimonides and Aquinas on Divine Attributes the Importance of Avicenna
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 8-2019 Maimonides and Aquinas on Divine Attributes the Importance of Avicenna Richard C. Taylor Follow this and additional works at: https://epublications.marquette.edu/phil_fac Part of the Philosophy Commons 12 Maimonides and Aquinas on Divine Attributes The Importance of Avicenna richard c. taylor It is well known that Shlomo Pines’s translation of Maimonides’ Guide of the Perplexed and Pines’s learned, stimulating introduction to the text have long influenced not only students of the rabbi’s work but also scholars of the Jew- ish, Christian, and Islamic Abrahamic traditions of medieval philosophical and religious thought. In scholarship on the Latin tradition, the use of the Guide by thinkers such as Alexander of Hales, William of Auvergne, Ro- land of Cremona, Giles of Rome, Albertus Magnus, Meister Eckhart, and other Christian Aristotelians of the thirteenth century has been duly noted. Nonetheless, major studies have focused mainly on the importance of Mai- monides for the teachings of Thomas Aquinas, the best- known Latin theo- logian and philosophical thinker of that period.1 With few exceptions,2 the research has also centered on the direct relation between Maimonides and Aquinas without consideration of their wider context, even though recent studies of Aquinas have repeatedly shown the invaluable importance of key 1. Some examples are the following: Dienstag 1975; Haberman 1979; Kluxen 1986; Copyright © 2019. University of Chicago Press. All rights reserved. of Chicago Press. © 2019. University Copyright Dobbs- Weinstein 1995; Hasselhoff 2001, 2002, 2004; Rubio 2006. 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Anselm's Ontological Argument for the Existence Of
    Anselm’s Ontological Argument for the Existence of God Anselm’s argument is an a priori argument; that is, it is an argument that is independent of experience and based solely on concepts and logical relations, like a mathematical proof. The form of the argument is that of a reductio ad absurdum argument. Such an argument works like this: Suppose P. If P, then Q. But Q is absurd (i.e. implies a contradiction). Therefore, P is false (or not the case). Anselm begins with a stipulative definition of “God” as “a being than which no greater being can be conceived.” The argument of Proslogium (Ch. II): (1) God exists in the understanding but not in reality. (Supposition) (2) Existence in reality is greater than existence in the understanding alone. (Premise) (3) God’s existence in reality is conceivable. (Premise) (4) If God did exist in reality, then he would be greater than he is (from (1) and (2)). (5) It is conceivable that there be a being greater than God is (from (3) and (4)). (6) It is conceivable that there be a being greater than the being than which nothing greater can be conceived ((5), by the definition of “God”). But surely (7) It is false that it is conceivable that there be a being greater than the being than which none greater can be conceived. Since (6) and (7) contradict each other, we may conclude that (8) It is false that God exists in the understanding but not in reality. Thus, if God exists in the understanding, he also exists in reality.
    [Show full text]
  • Between God and Society Divine Speech and Norm-Construction in Islamic Theology and Jurisprudence
    Between God and Society Divine Speech and Norm-Construction in Islamic Theology and Jurisprudence Omar Farahat Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2016 © 2016 Omar Farahat All rights reserved Abstract Between God and Society Divine Speech and Norm-Construction in Islamic Theology and Jurisprudence Omar Farahat The role of divine Revelation in the process of construction of normative judgments has long occupied scholars of religion in general, and Islam in particular. In the area of Islamic studies, numerous works were dedicated to the elucidation of various trends of thought on the question of the methods of formulation of norms and values. Many of those studies suppose a distinction between textualist and rationalist theories, and use this framework to explain the most influential Muslim views on this issue. In contemporary philosophical theology and the philosophy of religion, theorists of religious meta-ethics draw upon the medieval and early modern Christian debates almost exclusively. Reconstructing the philosophical foundations of classical Islamic models of norm-construction, which arise within both theological and jurisprudential works, has not received sufficient attention in either discipline. In this study, I explore eleventh century debates on the place of divine Revelation in the formulation of normative judgments in Islamic theology and jurisprudence, and bring this analysis in dialogue with current questions in philosophical theology. By reconstructing the epistemological, metaphysical and semantic foundations of those debates, I show that two general trends emerge on the question of the depth with which Revelation interferes in human moral reasoning, which generally correspond to recent debates between natural reason and divine command theorists in contemporary philosophical theology.
    [Show full text]