Federico Barocci and the Science of Drawing in Early Modern Italy
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Hunting the White Elephant. When and How Did Galileo
MAX-PLANCK-INSTITUT FÜR WISSENSCHAFTSGESCHICHTE Max Planck Institute for the History of Science PREPRINT 97 (1998) Jürgen Renn, Peter Damerow, Simone Rieger, and Michele Camerota Hunting the White Elephant When and how did Galileo discover the law of fall? ISSN 0948-9444 1 HUNTING THE WHITE ELEPHANT WHEN AND HOW DID GALILEO DISCOVER THE LAW OF FALL? Jürgen Renn, Peter Damerow, Simone Rieger, and Michele Camerota Mark Twain tells the story of a white elephant, a present of the king of Siam to Queen Victoria of England, who got somehow lost in New York on its way to England. An impressive army of highly qualified detectives swarmed out over the whole country to search for the lost treasure. And after short time an abundance of optimistic reports with precise observations were returned from the detectives giving evidence that the elephant must have been shortly before at that very place each detective had chosen for his investigations. Although no elephant could ever have been strolling around at the same time at such different places of a vast area and in spite of the fact that the elephant, wounded by a bullet, was lying dead the whole time in the cellar of the police headquarters, the detectives were highly praised by the public for their professional and effective execution of the task. (The Stolen White Elephant, Boston 1882) THE ARGUMENT In spite of having been the subject of more than a century of historical research, the question of when and how Galileo made his major discoveries is still answered insufficiently only. It is mostly assumed that he must have found the law of fall around the year 1604 and that only sev- 1 This paper makes use of the work of research projects of the Max Planck Institute for the History of Science in Berlin, some pursued jointly with the Biblioteca Nazionale Centrale in Florence, the Istituto e Museo di Storia della Scienza, and the Istituto Nazionale die Fisica Nucleare in Florence. -
Bernardino Baldi's in Mechanica Aristotelis Problemata Exercitationes
Bernardino Baldi’s In mechanica Aristotelis problemata exercitationes ii Max Planck Research Library for the History and Development of Knowledge Series Editors Jürgen Renn, Robert Schlögl, Bernard F. Schutz. Edition Open Access Development Team Lindy Divarci, Beatrice Gabriel, Jörg Kantel, Matthias Schemmel, and Kai Surendorf, headed by Peter Damerow. Scientific Board Markus Antonietti, Ian Baldwin, Antonio Becchi, Fabio Bevilacqua, William G. Boltz, Jens Braarvik, Horst Bredekamp, Jed Z. Buchwald, Olivier Darrigol, Thomas Duve, Mike Edmunds, Yehuda Elkana, Fynn Ole Engler, Robert K. Englund, Mordechai Feingold, Rivka Feldhay, Gideon Freudenthal, Paolo Galluzzi, Kostas Gavroglu, Mark Geller, Domenico Giulini, Günther Görz, Gerd Graßhoff, James Hough, Manfred Laubich- ler, Glenn Most, Pier Daniele Napolitani, Alessandro Nova, Hermann Parzinger, Dan Potts, Circe Silva da Silva, Ana Simões, Richard Stephen- son, Mark Stitt, Noel M. Swerdlow, Liba Taub, Martin Vingron, Scott Walter, Norton Wise, Gerhard Wolf, Rüdiger Wolfrum, Zhang Baichun. Sources 3 Edition Open Access 2011 Bernardino Baldi’s In mechanica Aristotelis problemata exercitationes Elio Nenci Communicated by Jürgen Renn and Antonio Becchi Edition Open Access 2011 Max Planck Research Library for the History and Development of Knowledge Sources 3 Communicated by Jürgen Renn and Antonio Becchi Translated from Italian into English by Adriano Carugo Copyedited by Lindy Divarci ISBN 978-3-86931-961-2 First published 2011 Printed in Germany by epubli, Oranienstraße 183, 10999 Berlin http://www.epubli.de Edition Open Access http://www.edition-open-access.de Published under Creative Commons by-nc-sa 3.0 Germany Licence http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/3.0/de/ The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Na- tionalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at http://dnb.d-nb.de. -
Galileo, Ignoramus: Mathematics Versus Philosophy in the Scientific Revolution
Galileo, Ignoramus: Mathematics versus Philosophy in the Scientific Revolution Viktor Blåsjö Abstract I offer a revisionist interpretation of Galileo’s role in the history of science. My overarching thesis is that Galileo lacked technical ability in mathematics, and that this can be seen as directly explaining numerous aspects of his life’s work. I suggest that it is precisely because he was bad at mathematics that Galileo was keen on experiment and empiricism, and eagerly adopted the telescope. His reliance on these hands-on modes of research was not a pioneering contribution to scientific method, but a last resort of a mind ill equipped to make a contribution on mathematical grounds. Likewise, it is precisely because he was bad at mathematics that Galileo expounded at length about basic principles of scientific method. “Those who can’t do, teach.” The vision of science articulated by Galileo was less original than is commonly assumed. It had long been taken for granted by mathematicians, who, however, did not stop to pontificate about such things in philosophical prose because they were too busy doing advanced scientific work. Contents 4 Astronomy 38 4.1 Adoption of Copernicanism . 38 1 Introduction 2 4.2 Pre-telescopic heliocentrism . 40 4.3 Tycho Brahe’s system . 42 2 Mathematics 2 4.4 Against Tycho . 45 2.1 Cycloid . .2 4.5 The telescope . 46 2.2 Mathematicians versus philosophers . .4 4.6 Optics . 48 2.3 Professor . .7 4.7 Mountains on the moon . 49 2.4 Sector . .8 4.8 Double-star parallax . 50 2.5 Book of nature . -
Geometry and Arithmetic in the Medieval Traditions of Euclid's
Geometry and Arithmetic in the Medieval Traditions of Euclid's Elements: a View from Book II Leo Corry – Tel Aviv University Dedicated to my dear friend Sabetai Unguru on his 82th birthday Contents 1. Abstract .......................................................................................................... 1 2. Introduction .................................................................................................... 2 3. Euclid’s Elements - Book II and Geometric Algebra ............................................... 7 3.1. Elements Book II – An Overview ........................................................................................... 7 3.2. Geometric Algebra – An Overview ..................................................................................... 14 3.3. Visible and Invisible Figures ............................................................................................... 18 4. Book II in Late Antiquity and in Islam Mathematics ............................................. 22 4.1. Heron’s Commentary of the Elements ................................................................................ 22 4.2. Al-Khwārizmī and Abū Kāmil .............................................................................................. 27 4.3. Thābit ibn Qurra ............................................................................................................... 35 4.4. Al-Nayrīzī ........................................................................................................................ -
Sciences Recent Acquisitions
BLACKWELL’S RARE BOOKS SCIENCES RECENT ACQUISITIONS 1 Blackwell’s Rare Books 48-51 Broad Street, Oxford, OX1 3BQ Direct Telephone: +44 (0) 1865 333555 Switchboard: +44 (0) 1865 792792 Email: [email protected] Fax: +44 (0) 1865 794143 www.blackwell.co.uk/rarebooks Our premises are in the main Blackwell bookstore at 48-51 Broad Street, one of the largest and best known in the world, housing over 200,000 new book titles, covering every subject, discipline and interest, as well as a large secondhand books department. There is lift access to each floor. The bookstore is in the centre of the city, opposite the Bodleian Library and Sheldonian Theatre, and close to several of the colleges and other university buildings, with on street parking close by. Oxford is at the centre of an excellent road and rail network, close to the London - Birmingham (M40) motorway and is served by a frequent train service from London (Paddington). Hours: Monday–Saturday 9am to 6pm. (Tuesday 9:30am to 6pm.) Purchases: We are always keen to purchase books, whether single works or in quantity, and will be pleased to make arrangements to view them. Auction commissions: We attend a number of auction sales and will be happy to execute commissions on your behalf. Blackwell’s online bookshop www.blackwell.co.uk Our extensive online catalogue of new books caters for every speciality, with the latest releases and editor’s recommendations. We have something for everyone. Select from our subject areas, reviews, highlights, promotions and more. Orders and correspondence should in every case be sent to our Broad Street address (all books subject to prior sale). -
Treatise on Land Surveying Methods Using the Surveyor's Cross
2019 IMEKO TC-4 International Conference on Metrology for Archaeology and Cultural Heritage Florence, Italy, December 4-6, 2019 The sixteenth-century find “Treatise On Land Surveying Methods Using the Surveyor’s Cross”, by Francesco Paciotti, military and civil architect to the Duchy of Urbino: the technical evolution of a surveying tool. Raffaella Marotti1 1 School of Conservation and Restoration of Cultural Heritage, Department of Pure and Applied Sciences (DiSPeA), Università degli Studi di Urbino "Carlo Bo", piazza della Repubblica, 13, 61029, Urbino, Italy, [email protected] Abstract - This paper focuses on the autograph Treatise Council Archive) at the Biblioteca Umanistica “On Land Surveying Methods Using the Surveyor’s dell’Università degli Studi di Urbino “Carlo Bo”, Cross” found at the Biblioteca Umanistica represents a primary source of information and data on the dell’Università degli Studi di Urbino “Carlo Bo” design and construction of this topographic tool, which (“Carlo Bo” Urbino University Humanistic Library). aimed to provide specific and precise measurements when The treatise was for many years erroneously included surveying land for the construction of fortifications. among the writings of the Urbino mathematician Furthermore, the treatise is of central importance as it Muzio Oddi (1569-1639), author of Dello Squadro (On bears witness to the wide and peculiar technical-scientific Land Surveying Methods Using the Surveyor’s Cross) of debate that characterised the Duchy of Urbino from the 1625, but through careful bibliographic research has second half of the 15th century to the first half of the 17th now been attributed to the civil and military architect century, making it culturally unique in Europe. -
The Development of Euclidean Axiomatics the Systems of Principles and the Foundations of Mathematics in Editions of the Elements in the Early Modern Age
Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. (2016) 70:591–676 DOI 10.1007/s00407-015-0173-9 The development of Euclidean axiomatics The systems of principles and the foundations of mathematics in editions of the Elements in the Early Modern Age Vincenzo De Risi1 Received: 4 August 2015 / Published online: 24 February 2016 © The Author(s) 2016. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract The paper lists several editions of Euclid’s Elements in the Early Modern Age, giving for each of them the axioms and postulates employed to ground elementary mathematics. Contents 1 Introduction ..................................593 1.1 The Euclidean tradition .........................593 1.2 Axioms and postulates .........................602 2 The principles .................................618 2.1 The principles of Euclid .........................618 2.2 Further principles in the Greek tradition ................619 2.3 Additional common notions and the foundations of the theory of magnitudes ...............................619 2.4 Principles on mereological composition and multiples of magnitudes . 620 2.5 The theory of ratios and proportions ..................622 2.6 The Axiom of Archimedes and the theory of indivisibles .......626 2.7 Principles of arithmetic and number theory ...............626 2.8 General principles of space, situation, and givenness ..........628 2.9 Principles of intersection, incidence and connection ..........629 2.10 Principles of continuity .........................631 2.11 Principles of congruence, motion, and transportation -
Annals of Science
This article was downloaded by:[Sidoli, Nathan] On: 11 October 2007 Access Details: [subscription number 782956906] Publisher: Taylor & Francis Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Annals of Science Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713692742 What We Can Learn from a Diagram: The Case of Aristarchus's On The Sizes and Distances of the Sun and Moon Nathan Sidoli a a Department of Mathematics, Simon Fraser University, Burnaby, British Columbia, Canada Online Publication Date: 01 October 2007 To cite this Article: Sidoli, Nathan (2007) 'What We Can Learn from a Diagram: The Case of Aristarchus's On The Sizes and Distances of the Sun and Moon', Annals of Science, 64:4, 525 - 547 To link to this article: DOI: 10.1080/00033790701336841 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00033790701336841 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf This article maybe used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. -
Euclid (In the Renaissance)
EUCLID (IN THE RENAISSANCE) Jens Høyrup Section for Philosophy and Science Studeis Roskilde University, Denmark Article written for Marco Sgarbi (ed.), Encyclopedia of Renaissance Philosophy Preprint 20 March 2017 Abstract Although the Latin Middle Ages received a number of versions of Euclid’s Elements and several other Euclidean works, by the 14th century only the Campanus redaction from c. 1259 was in circulation. In the 14th and 15th century, this redaction was encountered by students of Arts or Medical university faculties, even though we have scant evidence that Euclid impressed their minds. In the fifteenth century, other circles discovered him: Alberti took over the idea of elements, Regiomontanus used Euclid alongside Archimedes as an argument for the superiority of mathematics over philosophy, and one Florentine abbacus school tradition was able to give correct references to the Elements. A turn arrived with book printing. In 1482, the Campanus Elements were printed, and in 1498 and 1501 Giorgio Valla inserted pseudo-Euclidean and Euclidean material in two bulky volumes. A new though somewhat problematic Latin translation from the Greek (including also some minor works) was published by Zamberti in 1505, and until 1540 a number of reprints or re-editions of Campanus’s and Zamberti’s texts were published – at times in combination. From the 1540s onward, revisions, selections and vernacular translations began to appear, all based on the same two texts. In 1572, however, Commandino made a new Latin translation from Zamberti’s text and a sounder manuscript, and in 1574 Clavius produced a didactically oriented redaction. These two set the scene for the next two centuries. -
PAPPUS of ALEXANDRIA (About 320 AD) by HEINZ KLAUS STRICK, Germany
PAPPUS OF ALEXANDRIA (about 320 AD) by HEINZ KLAUS STRICK, Germany PAPPUS OF ALEXANDRIA is considered the last of the great Greek geometers. Almost nothing is known about his life - not even exactly when he lived. The only historical link is a commentary he wrote on a solar eclipse that he himself observed in Alexandria, which can be dated to October 320 by a modern calculation. It is known that he lived in Alexandria and led a "school" (or Academy) there. His main work was entitled Synagoge (Collection) and consisted of eight books. It represented a successful attempt to revive the classical geometry of the Greeks. PAPPUS was obviously not interested in replacing the books of the "ancients", but in bringing the meaning of these books (which probably all still existed at the time) back to consciousness and supplementing them with insights that had been added subsequently by other scholars. The collection also contained some references to writings by authors whose existence we might otherwise not have known about. The first translation of the Synagoge into Latin was by FEDERICO COMMANDINO in 1589, but it was then another few decades before RENÉ DESCARTES, PIERRE DE FERMAT and ISAAC NEWTON recognised the importance of the work and made it the basis of their own research. Book I on arithmetic has been completely lost, of Book II only a part exists (the fragment was discovered in 1688 by JOHN WALLIS in the Savillian Library in Oxford). It dealt with a problem of recreational mathematics: In ancient Greece, numerals were represented by letters, among others in the Milesian notation. -
DEFENDING HYPATIA Archimedes NEW STUDIES in the HISTORY and PHILOSOPHY of SCIENCE and TECHNOLOGY
DEFENDING HYPATIA Archimedes NEW STUDIES IN THE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY VOLUME 25 EDITOR Jed Z. Buchwald, Dreyfuss Professor of History, California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, CA, USA. ASSOCIATE EDITORS Jeremy Gray, The Faculty of Mathematics and Computing, The Open University, Buckinghamshire, UK. Sharon Kingsland, Department of History of Science and Technology, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, MD, USA. ADVISORY BOARD Henk Bos, University of Utrecht Mordechai Feingold, California Institute of Technology Allan D. Franklin, University of Colorado at Boulder Kostas Gavroglu, National Technical University of Athens Anthony Grafton, Princeton University Paul Hoyningen-Huene, Leibniz UniversitätHannover Trevor Levere, University of Toronto Jesper Lützen, Copenhagen University William Newman, Indian University, Bloomington Lawrence Principe, The Johns Hopkins University Jürgen Renn, Max-Planck-Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte Alex Roland, Duke University Alan Shapir , oUniversity of Minnesota Nancy Siraisi, Hunter College of the City University of New York Michael R. DietrichDartmouth, College Michel Morange , IHPST, Paris Hans-Jörg RheinbergerMax-Planck-Institut, für Wissenschaftsgeschichte Noel Swerdlow, University of Chicago Archimedes has three fundamental goals; to furtherintegration the of the histories of science and technology with one another: to investigate the technical, social and practical histories of specific developments in science andnology; tech and finally, where possible and desirable, to bring the histories of science and technology intocontact closer with the philosophy of science. To these ends, each volume will have its own themetitle and and will be planned by one or more members of the Advisory Board in consultation with the editor. Although the volumes have specific themes, the series itself will not be limited to one or even to a few particular areas. -
Max Planck Institute for the History of Science Archimedes
MAX-PLANCK-INSTITUT FÜR WISSENSCHAFTSGESCHICHTE Max Planck Institute for the History of Science 2017 PREPRINT 487 Jens Hµyrup Archimedes: Knowledge and Lore from Latin Antiquity to the Outgoing European Renaissance Abstract With only Apuleius and Augustine as partial exceptions, Latin Antiquity did not know Archimedes as a mathematician but only as an ingenious engineer and astronomer, serving his city and killed by fatal distraction when in the end it was taken by ruse. The Latin Middle Ages forgot even much of that, and when Archimedean mathematics was translated in the 12th and 13th centuries, almost no integration with the traditional image of the person took place. With the exception of Petrarca, who knew the civically useful engineer and the astrologer (!), fourteenth-century Humanists show no interest in Archimedes. In the 15th century, however, “higher artisans” with Humanist connections or education took interest in Archimedes the technician and started identifying with him. In mid-century, a new translation of most works from the Greek was made by Jacopo Cremonensis, and Regiomontanus and a few other mathematicians began resurrecting the image of the geometer, yet without emulating him in their own work. Giorgio Valla’s posthumous De expetendis et fugiendis rebus from 1501 marks a watershed. Valla drew knowledge of the person as well as his works from Proclus and Pappus, thus integrating the two. Over the century, a number of editions also appeared, the editio princeps in 1544, and mathematical work following in the footsteps of Archimedes was made by Maurolico, Commandino and others. The Northern Renaissance only discovered Archimedes in the 1530s, and for long only superficially.