<<

Available online at www.sciencedirect.com

ScienceDirect

Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33

www.elsevier.com/locate/lingua

Sitcom as ventriloquism

Thomas C. Messerli

Department of English, University of Basel, Nadelberg 6, 4051 Basel, Switzerland

Received 8 February 2017; received in revised form 10 May 2017; accepted 11 May 2017

Available online 31 May 2017

Abstract

Ventriloquism has been used as a source domain to conceptualise a range of different aspects of discourse, meaning-making and

understanding, and in Cooren's (e.g., 2010) view on a communicative constitution of reality even as a model for communication at large. In

Telecinematic Discourse (TCD), the language of fictional film and television, the notion that characters onscreen speak on behalf of

someone or something else is a particularly tangible representation of the duality of communicative levels by which TCD is usually

characterised. Moreover, Goffman's (1986/1974) canonical understanding of ventriloquism, as well as the employment of the same term

in neuroscience, film studies and narrative theory point to additional understandings of ventriloquism that are relevant for the

understanding not just of TCD, but also for humour therein. This paper brings together such different views of ventriloquist effects

and uses examples from to demonstrate how ventriloquism can be used as an alternative to the traditional spatial understanding

of the communicative setting of TCD. These examples originate from Anger Management and Two and a Half Men, which are regarded

here as two connected acts of ventriloquism, staged by actor Charlie Sheen and producer Chuck Lorre as part of their public feud in 2011.

Analysing these scenes through the lens of ventriloquism provides a dynamic view of agency and an understanding of the television

audience as active viewers who infer ventriloquists based on the dummy actions encoded in the multimodal text surface.

© 2017 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.

Keywords: Anger Management; Communicative levels; Humour; ; Telecinematic discourse; Two and a Half Men; Ventriloquism

1. Introduction

Participation structures in Telecinematic Discourse (TCD), i.e., the communication in and of fictional film and television,

are typically conceptualised with either of two prevalent spatial metaphors: In the duality of simultaneous events that

characterise such communication, the actions and interactions within the fictional, or diegetic, world are either understood

as embedded within or as resting upon the communication between some form of authorship or sender and the actual

audience (see e.g., Bubel, 2006, 2008; Bednarek, 2010; Dynel, 2011; Piazza et al., 2011; Messerli, 2017a). In other

words, the real world of authors and viewers is a container in which the diegetic world is placed, or it is a foundation on

which a stage is constructed. The diegetic world, on the other hand, is either understood as that stage or as a second

container within the first. Humour in such settings may take place in a space that is separated from that of the audience.

Situated on that stage or in that second container, it may be a self-contained event that audiences observe by looking up to

or into the diegetic space. They are amused from a distance. Or, indeed, humour may transgress the walls of the second

container or the height of the stage, and depend upon the audience's ability to perceive not just humour in the diegetic

E-mail address: [email protected].

URL: http://www.thomasmesserli.com.

http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.lingua.2017.05.006

0024-3841/© 2017 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved.

T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33 17

world, but also the container or the stage in or on which it occurs. This second type of humour requires awareness of the

constructedness of the fictional artefact (but not necessarily the manner in which it is constructed).

These two spatial ontological metaphors function well to explain the participation structures of TCD and of humour

therein, if participant roles are understood as static and dependent upon the type of artefact and perhaps the particular

audience receiving it. I will argue here, however, that such a spatial understanding of the dual or even multiple

communication channels of TCD falls short when audiences and individual audience members are thought of in a more

dynamic sense, as participants that are positioned and repositioned by diegetic events. Such a dynamic conceptualisation

is however necessary especially when it comes to the understanding of and humour (see Brock, 2015; Messerli,

2016). I propose then to observe the communicative setting of humour in TCD through the lens of ventriloquism, which has

been a fruitful source domain for the concretisation of a vast array of different concepts in different disciplines -- many of

them relevant for the way in which communication in and of audiovisual artefacts can be theorised. By discussing the

relevant literature in Section 2 and applying the empirical findings and theoretical concepts to the domain of TCD in

Section 3, I will approach this particular setting from a new vantage point and demonstrate the usefulness of ventriloquism,

which puts the focus on the different agents that are involved in communication with the television viewers, for the

understanding of the dynamic audience. This discussion is done with the help of excerpts from two American sitcoms, Two

and Half Men (CBS, 2003--2015) and Anger Management (FX, 2012--2014). The central research question this article

asks is deceptively simple: How do we need to understand and how can we successfully model the participation structure

of telecinematic communication in general and humour therein in particular? Using research from a range of disciplines,

some of which are not typically considered when theorising humour and the pragmatics of humour, my conceptualisation

of telecinematic humour as ventriloquism offers an audience-centred and performance-based conceptualisation of

comedy that highlights the different agents from which the communication is ultimately perceived to emanate. The fictional

characters through which humour is performed are understood as endpoints of multiple chains of agencies, with these

chains being dependent both on the experiential and communal knowledge of the audience and on the context that is

being constructed within the particular artefact itself.

2. Ventriloquism in different strands of research

I follow the view here that humour can be understood in terms of incongruity and resolution in the sense of Suls (1972),

i.e., stimuli in a linear narrative activate a narrative frame that evokes certain expectations in readers or viewers, with each

new stimulus being measured against those existing expectations. As long as new stimuli are congruous with viewer

expectations, no humour will ensue -- if, however, a narrative element occurs that does not fit expectations but whose

presence in the narrative is nonetheless plausible, the readers or viewers will find the resulting resolvable incongruity

humorous. In the case of sitcoms and more generally TCD, these stimuli occur as part of staged and mediated

performances, and as a result telecinematic humour is multimodal and generally multifaceted both with regard to its

production and reception. While I will return to the exact setup of sitcom humour in the discussion of examples in Section 3,

I want to first propose here an understanding of the communicative setting of telecinematic humour that serves as a useful

alternative to the extant spatial models. This understanding of communication and humour in film and television as a form

of ventriloquism will be outlined in the following sections. I will start by discussing various ways in which ventriloquism and

ventriloquism effects have been adapted in different disciplines to explain a range of different phenomena -- all of them will

be shown to be relevant for the understanding of telecinematic humour and thus inform the view I propose in Section 3.

2.1. Perceptual ventriloquism

A first understanding of ventriloquism that needs to be taken into account here stems from research in cognitive

psychology on multi- and cross-modal perception. Interested in cross-modal effects on perception, i.e., whether co-

occurring visual and auditory stimuli affect the perception of each of the two modalities, Vroomen and de Gelder (2004:

142) describe the well-documented phenomenon of the ventriloquism effect as follows: ‘‘[W]hen auditory and visual

stimuli occur in close temporal and spatial proximity, the perceptual system assumes that a single event has occurred.’’ A

prime example is indeed the performance of a ventriloquist. It depends upon the illusion that the voice the audience hears

when the 's mouth opens and closes emanates from the puppet itself rather than the who moves it with

her hand: Because of the visual stimulus provided by the visibly articulating puppet (and in the absence of a competing

visual stimulus in the form of lip movements by the puppeteer), the audience's perception of the sound shifts enough into

the direction of the puppet to make puppet action and voice appear to be a single event. In a range of experimental

settings, Vroomen and de Gelder (2004) showed that this effect is very robust even when participants were trained to

ignore the visual stimulus, and that ‘‘[a]ttention towards the visual distracter is not needed to obtain a ventriloquism effect’’

(Vroomen and de Gelder, 2004: 144).

18 T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33

2.2. Technological-ideological ventriloquism

That this effect is central to the reception of film by audiences was also taken up in film studies by Altman (1980: 76--77):

Indeed, the ventriloquist's art depends on the very fact which we have found at the heart of sound film: we are so

disconcerted by a sourceless sound that we would rather attribute the sound to a dummy or a shadow than face the

mystery of its sourcelessness or the scandal of its production by a non-vocal (technological or ‘‘ventral’’) apparatus.

In what is at least partially a defence of the importance of sound in film, Altman's interest goes beyond the perceptual

basis for the unification of sound and image. He finds in ventriloquism the answer for the roles each of the two modes have

in cinematic meaning-making. For Altman, the purpose of the ventriloquised dummy is to utter that which the ventriloquist

dare not speak in his or her normal voice. Mapping this idea to the target domain of cinema, he finds a similar mechanism

for sound and image: Whereas the sound functions as the head voice of the ventriloquist, the image is the dummy that is

being ventriloquised. Associated with the belly, it is the ventral voice that ‘‘speaks a more sincere, personal, and

unguarded language, a language no longer watched over by the censorship of the conscious mind’’ (Altman, 1980: 78).

This is to say that sound ventriloquises the image and meets those conditions that Altman finds in manuals for

ventriloquists, viz., (1) that it disguises the true source of the sound; and (2) that it makes all motion of its dummy consistent

with the sound (Altman, 1980: 77). Thus, the cinematic act of ventriloquism serves first of all as a means to disguise the

technology required to produce it and to create a fiction that the audience is able and willing to believe; secondly, it ‘‘permit

[s] the film's production personnel to speak their sub-conscious mind -- their belly -- without fear of discovery’’ (79). The

former describes the specific technological counterpart to perceptual ventriloquism that is paid heed to in (sound) film-

making. The latter is an attempt to explain the goal of film-making as speaking in images what cannot be said in words.

2.3. Narratological ventriloquism

Whereas films can be said to be divided between their auditory and visual modes, narrative theory has long established

that narrative fiction more generally can be rendered in terms of a multiplicity of voices. As O’Neill (1994: 58, his emphasis)

puts it, ‘‘[n]o narrative voice, however apparently objective or unbiased, is ever undivided, for all narrative discourse,

implicitly or explicitly, is compound discourse.’’ Novels as a form of mediated discourse between authors and their

readers, for instance, are communicated through a number of different agents that range from the implied author to the

narrator and on the side of the reception from the narratee to the implied reader. Even at the centre of this communicative

setting, in which a narrator talks to his direct audience, i.e., the narratee, that narrator's voice may not be undivided and

may instead speak through the different characters that populate the novel. This multiplicity of voices has been addressed

from a range of different angles and focusing on different agents within this narrative chain. Booth's (1961) introduction of

the notion of the implied author was met consequently by Iser's (1972) discussion of their counterpart, the implied reader.

They both shed light on the fact that within a literary text, it is not just narrators and characters that are constructed, but also

the fictional personae of an author and a reader that author is speaking to. Moreover, Genette's (1980/1972) well-known

classification of narrators highlights their position in relation to the narrated events and makes clear that within the frame of

implied authors speaking to implied readers, there is a range of different vantage points from which the embedded story is

told. That novels are thus multi-voiced in many different ways has been aptly captured by O’Neill (1994) in what he calls

ventriloquism effect, which will be renamed to narratological ventriloquism effect here in order not to confuse it with the

perceptual ventriloquism effect discussed in Section 2.1.

Ventriloquism in this narratological sense first of all refers to the narrator's voice, or indeed voices: Apart from using her

own, primary voice, the narrator can also ventriloquise the fictional characters, as the ventriloquist's dummies, in order to

speak with additional, secondary voices. As O’Neill (1994: 59) points out, this happens in different ways, which range from

the clear separation of voices in the mimetic case of a narrator that lets her characters utter direct speech, to more diegetic

cases, in which the narrator reports the characters’ dialogue rather than to include their voices. Between those endpoints

of the scale, a narrator using free indirect discourse creates ‘‘an example of an overtly mixed or compound discourse’’

(O’Neill, 1994: 59), which makes the borders between primary and secondary voices more fuzzy. The diegetic case, on

the other hand, at first appears to be resting on an undivided voice, at least on the level of the narrator speaking to his

narratee. However, O’Neill points to a second type of ventriloquism, which -- as will become clear in Section 2.4 -- is

reminiscent of yet another, socio-pragmatic, understanding of ventriloquism that Goffman (1986/1974) has termed say-

foring. Explicitly or implicitly, the narrator may utter what she assumes would be the response of the narratee at that

particular point in the narration. Finally, O’Neill discovers ventriloquism in a third sense by approaching literary

communication through Greimas's semiotics. I will refer the reader to O’Neill (1994: 76--82) for the discussion and

exemplification of how abstract narrative slots such as actants and narratants are realised on two different levels, that of

the story and that of the text. What is important here, however, is that as a result of this distinction, the narrator needs to be

T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33 19

understood in a more abstract sense as a position rather than as a person, and thus as ‘‘identifying the point of utterance of

the narrative voice’’ (O’Neill, 1994: 77). While there may be a typical position for the narrator between the implied author

and the character, O’Neill (1994: 78) emphasises that the narrator's voice ‘‘can be ‘thrown’ so that it appears to come

either from position C (character) or position A’ (implied author).’’ The different points on the scale of narrative positions

(author--implied author--narrator--character--narratee--implied reader--reader) are constructs of the text, and the reader

infers the respective positions based on her understanding of that text. Thus, the reader interacts with the text-as-dummy

and infers from this interaction what ventriloquist or what ventriloquists may animate it.

2.4. Ventriloquism as a discourse strategy

The multi-voicedness of authors and literary texts in narratological understandings of ventriloquism, which is particular

to the communicative setting of narrative fiction, finds its more general equivalent in sociological and pragmatic research.

For instance, as has been mentioned in the previous section, a narrator assuming the voice of a narratee can be seen as a

literary exemplification of say-foring as it is used by Goffman (1986/1974). Indeed, in order to characterise how ordinary

talk is framed, Goffman goes back and forth between staged, theatrical performance and ordinary conversation. He starts

from the generally accepted assumption that speakers can act out characters not their own on stage and finds that in non-

staged interaction, speakers also speak not as individual actors, but are split into principals, who are responsible for what

is being said, and animators who make the utterance (Goffman, 1986/1974: 516ff.). This separation of roles is of course

later expanded to the canonical distinction author--principal--animator (Goffman, 1979). The notion that a speaker can be

regarded as someone that animates the message she utters is clearly already akin to the ventriloquist animating her

dummy. More specifically, however, Goffman (1986/1974) speaks of forms of ventriloquism in his categorisation of the

figures through which we can speak in ordinary talk. This speaking through figures includes the use of natural, staged,

printed and cited figures as well as say-foring, which occurs when a speaker ‘‘puts words in another's mouth’’ (Goffman,

1986/1974: 534), of which speaking on behalf of a child or a pet are examples. As Lorenzo-Dus (2009: 33) puts it in her

adaptation of say-foring to television discourse, ‘‘[t]he ventriloquiser allegedly gets inside the ventriloquisee and speaks

for the latter, making public his/her personal intentions, feelings and views.’’

This understanding of ventriloquism is also taken up in the discourse analytic work of Tannen (2004, 2010) who uses

the term ventriloquising to describe ‘‘instances in which speakers frame their utterances as representing others’ voices’’

(Tannen, 2010: 310) and regards it as a form of borrowing others’ identities. Importantly, Tannen notes that what formally

resembles reported speech is in fact not a representation of what others have previously said, but functions as ‘‘a way for

speakers to represent their own meaning’’ (Tannen, 2010: 310). In her analyses of interactions between family members

who ventriloquise each other (Tannen, 2010) as well as their pets (Tannen, 2004), Tannen explicitly builds on work by

Schiffrin (1993) and Scollon (2001) who have termed similar conversational strategies ‘‘speaking for another’’ and

‘‘through baby talk’’ respectively (Tannen, 2004: 403). As she notes, the term itself is often attributed to Bakhtin (1981),

who in fact never used it but did speak of language that ‘‘would appear to be at a certain distance from [the author's] lips’’

(Bubnova and Malcuzynski, 2001: 299, quoted in Tannen, 2004: 404). This distancing effect is also found by Tannen in the

family interactions she examines. She finds that the family members achieve a range of conversational functions when

they speak through their dogs or through other family members. These functions include giving instructions (Tannen,

2010) as well as shifting away from an argument or into a humorous frame (Tannen, 2004). More generally, Tannen (2010:

308--310) links the instances of ventriloquism in her data to existing work on indirectness in language, which includes

among others Bateson's (1979) abduction and Bakhtin's (1986/1952--53) dialogicality. The two notions are similar in that

they find language use to be not so much performance based on a language system, as a form of interaction with previous

utterances, which are appropriated and related indirectly in the act of speaking. Tannen (2010: 310) complements this

dialogical view of utterances with the finding ‘‘that meaning in interaction comes not only from associations with others’

words but also from associations with others’ identities, as suggested not only by those words but also by the voices those

words create.’’ In other words, by ventriloquising others, speakers find a way of putting distance between themselves and

their utterances and of appropriating certain traits of the dummies they animate.

2.5. Constitutive ventriloquism

A final theoretical framework that needs to be included here is the all-encompassing view of ventriloquism offered by

Cooren (2010, 2012, 2013) and Cooren et al. (2013). He uses ventriloquism as a metaphor not just for a particular

discourse strategy used when a speaker pretends to speak through someone or something else, but for communication at

large. Following Derrida (1988), Cooren (2010: 28) first of all regards any communication as telecommunication in the

sense that any act of speaking necessarily has a material dimension and that even when speakers interact face-to-face

they do so through the signs and texts they produce and thus from a distance. These material products of communication

20 T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33

are not simply described as distant extensions of the speaking agent by Cooren, however -- they are understood as

entities that can be animated and that can have agency themselves in communication. One key example Cooren (2010:

29) provides is a note stuck to a wall in a hospital in the Congo, which states -- among other things -- that medical staff must

wear protective gear when decontaminating instruments. Anyone interested in the analysis of discourse would agree of

course that something is communicated through this note. Cooren, however, is adamant that this note is not just a tool of

communication, i.e., that the case is not simply that of an agent communicating through the note as a tool. While, as he

states, ‘‘the note does not do anything in and of itself’’ (Cooren, 2010: 30, his emphasis), he considers its communicative

actions to be those of an agent for whatever author wrote it and whatever principal that author represents.

First of all, this note in the hospital serves as an example for the understanding of textual agency that Cooren discussed

in earlier work (Cooren, 2004, 2008). In this view, stating that the medical staff member that put up the note on behalf of

Médecins Sans Frontières was simply communicating to other staff members through that note would mean ignoring the

role of nonhuman agency. Instead, Cooren (2004: 378--379) states that the person putting up the note appropriated the

note and with it its powers that include communicating across time and space. While texts and other objects are seen as

active participants in communication, which do ‘‘things that humans alone could not do’’ (Cooren, 2004: 388), the actions

they perform can at the same time be attributed to the human and nonhuman agents that have appropriated them for their

purposes. This is to say that the importance given to nonhuman and in this case textual agency is not meant to reduce

human agency.

This negotiation between human and nonhuman agents is where ventriloquism comes into play. The material signs

and texts we produce are examples at a basic level of communication of how we animate other things into speaking on our

behalf. In other words, to interact means to create ‘‘textual, gestural, or kinesic agents that speak and act on [one's]

behalf’’ (Cooren, 2010: 90) and thus to communicate through ‘‘beings’’ that have at least some autonomy. The metaphor

of ventriloquism seems abundantly clear at first sight, with a speaker/ventriloquist animating such nonhuman agents/

dummies. However, an important notion that Cooren (2010: 170) adds is ‘‘that interactants are ventriloquised as much as

they ventriloquise.’’ In the context of organisational communication, which Cooren is mainly interested in, this means for

instance that when someone speaks in the name of justice, she first of all animates justice into becoming an active agent

within that interaction. At the same time, however, justice in this case also ‘‘ventriloquises the ventriloquist’’ (Cooren et al.,

2013: 263), i.e., it animates her into performing in a specific manner.

Before I turn to the application of ventriloquism to telecinematic humour, I need to add that this constitutive

understanding of ventriloquism can in many ways be regarded as the flipside of the interpersonal pragmatic

understanding of identity construction, as it is described in the seminal article by Bucholtz and Hall (2005). Identity is

understood there as an emergent product of interaction, as a quality that interactants construct by positioning themselves

in a particular fashion. One aspect of this discursive process of identity construction is what Bucholtz and Hall (2005: 598)

call the relationality principle, which states that in interaction, we use intersubjective strategies to put ourselves in a

particular relation to other groups and entities, e.g., we position ourselves as similar or different, as authentic or as having

authority (Bucholtz and Hall, 2005: 598--605). Thus, when a spokesperson of a company speaks, Bucholtz and Hall would

point to processes of authorisation and authentication to explain how the particular person can successfully position

herself as someone who has the legitimate right to represent the company. What Cooren's understanding of ventriloquism

emphasises is that in doing so, the spokesperson and the company she represents both construct each other's identities

and animate each other into being agents within that particular interaction.

2.6. Ventriloquism effects and chains of agencies: terminology used in this paper

The previous sections have discussed the use of ventriloquism as an ontological metaphor in various disciplines.

Applied to the domain of telecinematic discourse, they are understood here as complementary in the sense that they can

shed light on different ventriloquist effects that are at play during the reception of films and television, and will all be shown

to be valid concepts for the understanding of sitcom humour in Section 3. However, before progressing to applying the

concept of ventriloquism empirically, some terminological clarification is necessary at this point. In accordance with the

subsections in this section, I will distinguish the following levels of ventriloquism effects in television reception: (a)

perceptual ventriloquism effects, which refer to the perceptual system assuming a single event based on co-occurring

auditory and visual stimuli; (b) technological ventriloquism effects, which refer to the facilitating of (a) through the

technological affordances employed for televisual meaning-making; (c) narratological ventriloquism effects, which refer to

the chain of narrative voices that are inferred by the viewers; (d) say-foring effects, which refer to the act of speaking for

another agent; (e) constitutive ventriloquism effects, which refers to different agents within the chain of agency reciprocally

animating each other into being.

That notion of chain of agency (Cooren, 2010) or chain of agencies (Cooren, 2008) refers to the assumption that any

communicative action cannot be pinpointed to one particular locus or agent. Instead it always entails a stream of different

T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33 21

communicators, from the gestures a speaker uses to communicate, to the speaker, to the author of the spoken utterance

to more abstract entities on behalf of which the communicative act may take place. In many ways, this chain of agency can

thus be seen as an elaboration of Goffman's understanding of participation roles and of Levinson's (1987) further

development of what he terms production roles in particular. Even though Levinson (1987) deems reception to be the

analytically more difficult side of communication, he already points out that the different production roles he distinguishes

are not always clearly separable. For instance, as he mentions, transmitters may or may not play a part in the origin of the

message (Levinson, 1987: 177). Within Cooren's more dynamic framework of chains of agency, the individual roles

involved in the production of communicative acts are not only difficult to separate, but are also necessarily fragmentary.

Since ultimately ‘‘there is no origin of action’’ (Cooren, 2008: 13), it follows that the Goffmanian principal and Levinsonian

categories like ultimate source or author are not fixable to any particular agent. Put differently, it is true for any agent that

‘‘their very action can always be attributed to other agents, whether upstream (the entities of whom or which they are

positioned as acting on behalf or incarnating) or downstream (the entity they are mobilising to interact)’’ (Cooren, 2008:

14). Having acknowledged that communicative agency is a fuzzy concept, it nonetheless needs to be added here that

conceptualising telecinematic humour as ventriloquism does not render useless the canonical classifications of

participants or production roles. Concepts like the simple model of animator, author and principal have value as

prototypes of particular loci on the chain of agency, and they will be retained here as anchors for the ventriloquism-based

analysis of telecinematic disourse.

3. Telecinematic humour as ventriloquism

3.1. The production context of Anger Management and Two and a Half Men

Having outlined the relevant theoretical background that informs the view of telecinematic humour as ventriloquism I

propose here, I will move on in this section to adapting the key notions discussed in the literature to the particular domain of

humour in telecinematic discourse (TCD), which I will also refer to as telecinematic humour. I will do so by focussing on

examples from two American sitcoms whose production histories are connected in a particular way: Two and a Half Men

(CBS, 2003--2015) and Anger Management (FX, 2012--2014). While being in many ways typical representatives of how

humour is constructed in sitcoms, they are also good examples of what could be termed paratextual humour, i.e., humour

that goes beyond the fictional story in which it is embedded and thus requires its receivers to be familiar with current affairs

in the broadest sense and more specifically with events in the public lives of those involved in the production of the

particular sitcom episode they are watching. The two sitcoms at hand are connected through the actor Charlie Sheen, who

played the lead role for eight seasons of Two and a Half Men (TAAHM) and for the entire run of Anger Management (AM).

To contextualise the example from AM I introduce in the next section, and the examples from TAAHM that follow later

(Sections 3.5 and 3.7), I will briefly address the circumstances that led to Sheen's dismissal from TAAHM and to his role as

the main character on AM. My summary here is informed by an article in the Washington Post, which was published on the

occasion of the TAAHM finale (Yahr, 2015), and I refer the reader to that article for a more detailed chronology of the

individual events.

After a range of drug-related incidents that led to Sheen being sentenced to rehab several times, CBS put TAAHM on

hiatus in the middle of its eighth season in 2011. In a month of tabloid stories, Sheen after that gave several interviews in

1

which he repeatedly attacked producer Chuck Lorre and the quality of TAAHM. Chuck Lorre responded in a vanity card in

his other sitcom Mike & Molly (CBS, 2010--2016). Sheen continued to attack TAAHM, in sometimes incoherent manner

and full of self-aggrandizement, until CBS finally decided to let him go. While CBS described Sheen's behaviour as self-

destructive (Yahr, 2015), he nonetheless managed to capitalise on the publicity, first by starting a live tour and gaining a

million Twitter followers in record time, then with a contract for a new sitcom, Anger Management, with the television

network FX. Meanwhile, TAAHM continued, with Sheen's onscreen character, Charlie Harper, written out of the sitcom.

Instead, a new lead character was introduced (played by Ashton Kutcher).

3.2. An example of multimodal humour in Anger Management

As a starting point, example 1 presents the very first scene of the first episode of AM, which marks actor Charlie

Sheen's return to the television screen:

1

A vanity card is a written text displayed at the end of the episode, comparable to a blog post, which Chuck Lorre regularly includes in episodes

of his sitcoms to comment on the production and a wide range of other current events.

22 T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33

Example 1: Anger Management, Season 1, Episode 1, 00:00:00–00:00:16 Charlie is shown in a close-up facing the camera directly. The background only reveals that he is indoors, no further

details about the room are visible.

1 Charlie: you can’t fire me, I quit. (.) + -----makes a punching movement with the right arm----+ {thump sound} Charlie: think you can replace me with some other guy? go ahead, it won't be the same.

+-----makes a punching movement with the right arm----+

{thump sound}

LT: hahahaha

2 Charlie: you may think I'm losing, but I'm not. I'm- +---turns around----+ {Cut to long shot of the room, which reveals that it is a large living room with several armchairs and a sofa, on which there are three men looking at

Charlie}

Charlie: =anyway, you get the idea. LT: hahahahahahahahahahahaha

+ Charlie

As I have done elsewhere (Messerli, 2016), I will use the audience laughter that is broadcast as part of the sitcom as a

marker of humorous intentions by the collective sender of the sitcom. This leads to the identification of two instances of

intended humour in excerpt 1, HI 1 (humorous instance 1) and HI 2, as is indicated in the numbering in the leftmost column.

Following an incongruity-resolution approach to humour as it is presented in Suls (1972), I regard the intended humour in

these and all other instances as the result of something unexpected that disrupts the narrative frame that had been evoked

up to that point. The incongruity surprises the viewer and at the same time permits the finding of a satisfactory explanation

as to why this incongruous element is nonetheless plausibly present within the narrative. In an abstract sense, theorising

these or any other HIs is thus a fairly straightforward affair. However, in the case of example 1, at least the reader

unfamiliar with the sitcoms I refer to here will have noticed that it is not necessarily easy to explain either the narrative

frame or the way it is disrupted here.

Of course, contrary to a , humour in sitcoms is multimodal -- both in the sense that character actions, gestures and

facial expressions are meaningful and that so is camera work and the mise-en-scène at large (see Bednarek, 2010) --, and

it makes sense then to also include the auditory and visual stimuli that the viewer processes in the first twelve seconds of

this episode. Apart from hearing the dialogue, we also see a close-up of a middle-aged man, who we may recognise as

Charlie Sheen. He stands in front of a non-descript, slightly out of focus interior background and looks straight into the

camera and therefore at us, the viewers. While speaking, he thrusts his chin upwards in an aggressive gesture, and

afterwards clenches his teeth, leans forward and punches something that is below the camera frame and thus invisible to

the viewer. While we cannot see this punch, there is an audible thump we need to assume is the result of it. Similar

gestures, including a head tilt and another chin thrust, accompany the continuation of the dialogue, there is another punch.

Finally, the third time, Charlie stops after ‘‘I’m’’ and turns to his right; there is a cut to a long shot that shows not only the full

body of the actor/character, but also reveals that he is standing in a huge living room, left of him a sofa with three men that

look at him and to his right an inflatable doll, which we infer to be the target of the punches we had just seen him throw. He

shrugs his shoulders and puts his hands together while saying, as a punchline, ‘‘anyway, you get the idea.’’

Much of the multimodality of this scene serves the establishment of a pattern and its surprising disruption: The two

completed intonation units are telecinematically framed as close-ups, and are followed by punches; the third intonation

unit is interrupted, does not end with a punch and cuts to a long shot. The repetitive nature of this setup that leads to the

humorous instance in the example triggers viewer expectations that are reinforced multimodally, with repetition occurring

in gesture, in the size of camera shot, in intonation patterns, and in the dialogue Charlie engages in with an off-screen

2

interactant -- manifest in the vacillation between direct address to a ‘‘you’’ and clauses in the first-person. These

expectations are followed by surprise in the form of a new camera perspective, the character/actor turning sideways, and

a sudden interruption in the utterance. Thus, the formal structure of the audiovisual text is at the same time prototypical for

2

For a discussion of the functions of repetition in sitcom humour, see Messerli (2017b).

T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33 23

humour -- setup in two steps, punchline in the third -- and specific to the meaning-making of telecinematic discourse, with

the different modes working together to create expectations and surprise.

While the construction of this humorous instance is transparent on the text surface, it is less so in terms of the meaning

that is thus encoded. In other words, the mechanism by which the incongruity is realised is comparatively simple, but the

essence of that same incongruity is not as easy to pinpoint. Based on the context of this episode and generic knowledge

about sitcoms, the viewers gather that what they see is an actor portraying a character who is currently expressing his

anger by verbalising his frustration and punching an as of yet undefined item. Given the lack of information about his

surrounding space due to the close-up, there may be surprise when it is revealed that this character is in fact not alone, but

in presence of three other people. As the majority of the contemporary American audience will have known, however, the

key to this humorous instance lies in recognising that the interrupted intonation unit is an allusion to a particular quote that

is in turn indexical of the meltdown of actor Charlie Sheen. The antonymous pairs, firing and quitting, as well as

successfully or unsuccessfully replacing someone, lead to the expectation that ‘‘you may think I’m losing, but I’m not’’ will

be completed by ‘‘I’m winning,’’ which can be said to be the catchphrase of actor Charlie Sheen's public meltdown in 2011.

Instead of fulfilling this expectation, Charlie stops and turns around and thus surprises the knowledgeable viewers.

3.3. Sitcom humour as a chain of ventriloquism effects

Taking into account this additional, meta-textual information, it becomes clear that the humorous instances discussed

in Section 3.2 are a case of what might be referred to as humour across communicative levels. This is to say that humour

transgresses the borders of the fictional communicative level in which the main character holds his dialogical monologue,

and has him allude to the communicative level between collective sender and television audience, of which knowledge

about well-publicised real-life events concerning the actors is part. To put it in Brock's (2015: 33) terms, the viewers are ‘‘in

two different communicative roles and on two communicative levels all at once.’’ I have previously shown how different

humour constellations dynamically reposition viewers on different communicative levels (Messerli, 2016). However, the

spatial representation of what occurs in this type of humour constellation is not satisfactory, for it is quite clear that both

communicative levels remain fully intact (no walls are broken), and the viewers’ position is dynamic, but also stable in that

they remain a real-life audience that is both aware that what they receive is fiction and that they need to suspend their

disbelief to enjoy it. It seems unnecessary to imagine this dynamic positioning as one of constant oscillation between

levels, or as a form of paradoxical co-presence on two planes: What we see is always some type of dummy that is

animated by some type of ventriloquist.

To begin with, willing suspension of disbelief is dependent on perceptual and technological ventriloquism effects (see

Sections 2.1, 2.2 and 2.6). The viewers perceive of the visible articulation by the actor and the sound they hear through the

speakers as a single event, with the ventriloquised image thus disguising the technological nature of the television

broadcast at hand. In the case of fictional film and television, this disguise goes beyond the technological, however, and

the viewers are aware of course that the character Charlie Goodson they hear speak in this excerpt does not simply do so

on his own behalf, but as part of a chain of agency (to use the terminology of Cooren, 2010) which includes other agents.

These other agents are always present, but may make themselves manifest in different ways on the surface of the

audiovisual text. Thanks to the metacommunicative cues that they receive when watching Anger Management, viewers

may note that the character Charlie Goodson is played by the actor Charlie Sheen and that the shared first names of both

figures may indicate other commonalities. They will also be aware that there is a particular television network that is

responsible for the production and broadcast of the sitcom, and that there are other agents that serve as the authors of the

artefact and formulate what the actors will voice -- a responsibility usually shared by scriptwriters, directors and producers.

It is important to note here that telecinematic discourse as a particular form of ventriloquism does only present the

dummy, i.e., the visible screen including the characters and their surroundings, to its audience, while the ventriloquist,

which in this case is in fact a conglomerate of different agents, remains hidden, carefully concealing their figurative lip-

movements in order to allow the audience to believe that the dummy is animated in and of itself. The open secret that

actors speak not as themselves but through the characters they represent is kept by adhering to a number of conventions

of film-making, which includes the passive denial of the presence of a camera -- i.e., that the actors/characters will not

point at or directly look into the camera --, as well as constraining the characters’ knowledge, manifest in their utterances

and actions, to what the characters could know based on their fictional experiences rather than the real-life experiences of

the actors that portray them.

Based on the different notions of ventriloquism discussed in Section 2, the interaction as well as the humour in example

1 can be conceptualised as the result of the interplay of different types of ventriloquism. I have already mentioned the

perceptual ventriloquism effects that are required to perceive sound and image as co-constructing audiovisual events and

that at the same time partially mask the constructedness of the audiovisual artefact (i.e., a technological ventriloquism

effect). Following Cooren's view, the gestures -- both in a narrow sense (1) as the character/actor gestures and actions

captured by the camera and in a broader sense (2) as the telecinematic gestures the camera itself together with all other

24 T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33

aspects of television making performs -- can be regarded as agents produced and animated into communicating with the

television audience. The importance of this assumption is particularly clear in the case of telecinematic discourse,

because the willing suspension of disbelief that is required to enjoy the engagement with fiction entails that the audience

assumes the ventriloquist behind the gestures in the first sense to be the character, when they actually know it is the actor

who produces them. The more analytic viewer may also be aware that these character gestures are only visible to the

viewership because they are captured on camera -- in this case, suspension of disbelief allows denying any agency to the

telecinematic apparatus and perceive the capturing as automatic, when it could in fact be identified as the sum of gestures

in sense (2), performed by the director (among others), who is in turn informed by the script.

It follows that the fictional sitcom characters and more generally the diegetic world that is constructed through these

gestures constitute a telecinematic trick that could be called a fictional ventriloquism effect in the constitutive sense: The

manifest gestures or signals that are present at the surface of the audiovisual text are produced by actors, directors and

the like when filming and post-producing the sitcom. The audience, however, is meant to construe them as indices of the

characters and their fictional surroundings. Thus, hiding the means by which the artefact is produced and adhering to the

conventional realism of televisual storytelling amounts to offering a valid visual stimulus to the television audience while

hiding the actual source of the onscreen events: It presents the fictional characters and events as ventriloquists to mask

the actual ventriloquising taking place by actors and the collective sender more generally. As Bednarek (2010: 19) already

points out, one crucial element of this fictional ventriloquism is the fact that characters and actors inhabit the same body:

Any character action is necessarily also an actor's action at the same time. Because of this, any produced signal is

necessarily always ambiguous in the sense that it can be attributed to either character or actor. Assuming an ideal viewer,

who is willing to suspend her disbelief, it seems plausible that by default telecinematic conventions steer audiences

towards inferring the signals to be animated from within the diegetic world. At the same time, however, audiences are

aware that this is ventriloquism. They know that characters do not act in and of themselves, just like gestures do not act on

their own. The character actions, designed for the audience, implicate that some form of ventriloquist who is external to the

diegetic world, animates them. That ventriloquist or those ventriloquists remain hidden, but their identities may emerge at

certain points of the sitcom, as anticipated results for the collective sender, but as surprising, emergent products for the

viewers.

Example 1 demonstrates that this ventriloquist can be located at any number of positions. For instance, the actions

transcribed can be said to be ventriloquised by the genre of the television sitcom. Charlie is framed by the camera in

certain ways and speaks in a particular way because that is how sitcoms are made and that is how characters in sitcoms

talk. Similarly, Anger Management ventriloquises the genre of the sitcom and is ventriloquised by it, and this particular

episode ventriloquises the sitcom Anger Management and is ventriloquised by it. Thus, when Charlie speaks, he may

speak on behalf of the actor Charlie Sheen, of the writers that wrote his lines, of the director that determines the

telecinematic framing of his actions, of the producers that have creative control over the television series, of the narrative

of this particular episode, of the sitcom Anger Management more generally, of the genre of the sitcom, etc.; and

simultaneously, all these ventriloquists speak through Charlie.

3.4. Ventriloquism and the epitext

The distribution of agency to many different loci of television sitcom production is not just a different way of theorising

screen-to-face interaction (to use Bubel's 2008 term), it is also directly relevant to the humour that occurs in example 1.

Whereas the first line is generic and can be assumed to be understood by the audience as a cliché sentence often used in

popular media to redistribute agency from the employer to the employee when employment is terminated, the second line

is more specific: It allows the reading that Charlie Goodson, about whom the audience knows almost nothing at this point,

is not talking about his fictional environment, to which the viewers are now being gradually introduced, but also about the

actor Charlie Sheen who had by then been replaced by another actor, Ashton Kutcher, on Two and a Half Men. To the

knowledgeable viewer, the utterance is thus a clear cue that the onscreen events are not just animated by the character,

but that they or indeed the character itself, are ventriloquised by the actor Charlie Sheen who speaks through them to

address the fact that he was let go in the aftermath of his public meltdown. By reacting in this fashion, by ventriloquising

Charlie Goodson into making a statement through what is, after all, only a part of a fictional sitcom, the agency behind

these utterances can at least partially be moved away from the actor and instead be ascribed to the character Goodson,

and perhaps even to all other potential ventriloquists aside from Sheen that may animate him.

The same instance of ventriloquism that thus reduces the accountability of Charlie Sheen for what could otherwise be

said to be a direct attack on producer Chuck Lorre is also the essence of both humorous instances in example 1. There is

no semantic incongruity proper here, in the sense that two clashing scripts would be evoked by the diegetic events, and as

would be the case in a prototypical joke. Instead, the viewer expectations triggered by the actions in context lead precisely

to the acceptance of the fictional ventriloquism effect, i.e., they reinforce the viewers’ belief that character actions and

utterances are informed by fictional character experiences. The resulting incongruity can be explained by a clash between

T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33 25

the text and what Genette (1997) called the paratext, and more precisely the epitext. The more general term, paratext,

refers to those ‘‘verbal or other productions’’ that ‘‘surround it [the text] and extend it, precisely in order to present it’’

(Genette, 1997: 1, his emphasis). It includes both peritextual elements, which are part of the artefact itself, and distanced

elements that Genette calls epitext:

The distanced elements are all those messages that, at least originally, are located outside the book, generally with

the help of the media (interviews, conversations) or under cover of private communications (letters, diaries, and

3

others). (Genette 1997: 5)

One way of putting simply the mechanism behind the humorous instances in example 1 is thus to say that it creates a

clash between text and epitext. Contrary to the expected constraint that fictional characters are conventionally bound to

only have access to aspects on the hierarchically subordinate fictional communicative level, Charlie makes reference

here to the epitext and thus creates an incongruity between stimuli that results in a humorous effect on the audience. Since

only actors, as representatives of the collective sender, have access to epitextual and more generally paratextual

information, whereas characters do not, the epitextual reference in example 1 amounts to a momentary repositioning of

the dummy Charlie Goodson as the ventriloquist Charlie Sheen. This in turn means that the viewers’ position must follow

that repositioning and look past the dummy to focus on the ventriloquist.

3.5. References to text and epitext in Two and a Half Men

In order to broaden the range of humorous phenomena that can be captured by this view of telecinematic humour as

ventriloquism, I will include two examples from Two and Half Men (TAAHM) at this point, which highlight different

relationships between ventriloquist and dummy and soften what would be considered the boundaries between different

layers in a spatial understanding of participation in telecinematic humour. To introduce these examples, I will briefly explain

their production context here, while bearing in mind the larger context that was described in Section 3.1. The excerpts I will

include are from the first episode of the ninth season and the sitcom finale, i.e., the final episode of the twelfth season. These

two episodes mark the beginning and ending of the four-season run of TAAHM after Charlie Sheen had left the sitcom. On

the fictional level, it starts with the funeral of Charlie Harper, the main character that was played by Sheen in its first eight

seasons, and its final episode then begins with the surprise revelation that Charlie Harper had in fact not died, but is now out

to take revenge on all of those who profited from his disappearance. Many of the scenes in the finale make clear reference to

aspects of its epitext, similar to what has been shown in example 1, and they serve as implicit or explicit attacks on Charlie

Sheen by the producer of TAAHM, Chuck Lorre. The very final scene of the sitcom shows Charlie Harper being killed by a

grand piano that falls on him, and then, as its final movement, shows producer Chuck Lorre sitting in a director's chair and

turning around to the camera to say ‘‘winning,’’ before he, too, is killed by yet another falling grand piano.

Example 2 is a transcription of the very first scene of the first episode of season 9, which starts off the post-Sheen part

of TAAHM:

Example 2: Two and a Half Men, Season 9, Episode 1 “Nice to meet you, Walden Schmidt”, 00:00:00–00:02:27

Alan is speaking at his brother Charlie’s funeral. A pan reveals Charlie’s typical clothes (a short-sleeved blue shirt with

stripes and a pair of shorts) hanging on a coat hanger behind Alan.

(Introductory is a version of Chopin’s Funeral March sung by repeating the word “Men”, which makes it a

blend of that march with the usual credit music of Two and Half Men.)

1 {Camera pans left past a coffin and reveals Charlie’s clothes and then Alan}

LT: hahahahahahahahahahah[hahaha]

2 Alan: [hello. ](.) I’m Charlie’s brother

Alan. (.) I wanna thank you all for coming. (.) I know this is a- a very sad day for all of us.

Woman 1 speak for yourself!

LT: hahahahahaha[hahaha ]

3 Alan: [o- okay.] uh. (.) I understand that, ah, some of you have-ff

“mixed feeli ngs.”

*---air quotes---* LT: hahahahahaha[hahahaha]

3

While Genette (1997) refers to books in his work on paratexts, there is no reason why an audiovisual artefact could not be conceptualised

using the same terms.

26 T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33

4 Alan: [um. (.) but] I-I-I think we can all agree that Charlie lived life to its fullest and-and

gave it everything he had.

Woman 2: gave me herpes.

LT: hahahahahahahaha

5 Woman 3: &---raises hand---&

chlamydia

LT: hahahahahahahaha

6 Woman 4: %---raises hand---%

vaginal warts

LT: hahahahahahahaha

7 Evelyn: excuse me, this is my dead son we're talking about. (.) I loved him and I'm devastated

that he's gone, leaving me with nothing but my memories (.) and my regrets (.) and the listing for

his beaut iful beachfront [Malibu getaway with three bedrooms and three and a half baths (.) and ] a

LT: [hahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahahah]

8 Evelyn: =beautiful panoramic ocean view. (.)

LT: hahahahahaha[haha]

9 Evelyn: [Help ]yourselves to brochures out by the coffee urn.

LT: hahahahahahahaha

10 Alan: Thank you, (.) Mom. [um, any][[way.]]

LT: [hahaha ]

11 Evelyn: [[uh, ]] Open house is Sunday, one to five.

LT: hahahahahahahaha

12 Alan: Okay, uhm, I’d- I'd like to: take a moment to: talk about my brother, um, and his incredible love

for life.

Woman 4: he also loved being spanked.

LT: hahahaha[hahahahahahaha]

13 Woman 5: [while wearing my]panties.

LT: hahahahahaha[[ha]]

14 Woman 6: [[he]] used my panties to make tea.

LT: hahahahahahahahahahahaha[hahahahahahahahahahahaha]

15 Alan: [my- my- my point i:s, um, that-] (.) Charlie lived life on his own

terms and-and never apologized for who he was.

Woman 7: yeah, blah, blah, blah. Why can't we see the body?

LT: hahahahahahahaha

16 Woman 1: yeah, I didn't come all this way to spit on a closed coffin.

LT: hahahaha[hahahahahahahaha]

17 Alan: [o- okay, I understand] how you feel, but, uh, unfortunately due to the circumstances of

his passing, the remains aren't exactly (.) spit-able.

LT: hahahahahahahaha[[hahaha]]

18 Man 1: [[I have a]]question.

LT: hahahahaha[hahaha]

19 Alan: [o- okay. ]u:h, I wasn't planning on doing a Q and A, [[u:h, but go ahead.]] LT: [[hahahahahahaha ]]

20 Man 1: thank you. Charlie owes me 38,000 Dollars for some, let's say, pharmaceuticals.

LT: hahahahahahahaha

21 Man 1: who do I talk to about that?

LT: hahahahahahahaha

22 Alan: uh, we- uh, I think that's something you'll have to discuss with the lawyers. Man 1: yeah. (.) I'd rather not involve [the law.]

LT: [hahahaha]hahahaha

* Alan

& Woman 3 % Woman 4

T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33 27

The excerpt in example 2 includes 22 humorous instances. Rather than discussing the processes of incongruity and

resolution that create humour in all 22 cases in detail, I will focus here on larger patterns and demonstrate their explicability

through ventriloquism.

Given the setting in this example as well as the plot of the preceding episode, in which Charlie Harper is reported to

have been fatally hit by a subway train in Paris, the obvious theme of most of the HI in example 2 is Charlie as a character.

The narrative frame evoked by the mise-en-scène is that of a funeral. The communicative setting, including the positioning

of the characters, e.g., as speakers in front of a crowd sitting in church benches, and the characters’ clothing further

reinforce that frame. The characters that are part of the main cast of the sitcom, Charlie's brother, Alan, and their mother,

Evelyn, also pay heed to the same frame, and adapt to it at least initially -- Alan by holding a eulogy, Evelyn by expressing

that she is mourning for her son (HI 7). The prevalent pattern for humour construction in this scene exploits this narrative

frame of the funeral and mourning for Charlie, which is enacted multimodally, and juxtaposes it with aspects that do

decidedly not fit that frame. The surprising elements that trigger the humour-evoking incongruities for the most part fall into

the detailed description of Charlie Harper's actions in life, which -- if this excerpt is taken as a measure -- have affected

many people negatively. Other characters who have featured in previous episodes of TAAHM refer to Charlie's drug

abuse (HIs 20--22) as well as his sexual behaviour (Hi 4--6; 12--14), the excessive promiscuousness of which is evaluated

4

as negative here. More generally, the humorous instances here all include facts about Charlie's life that are less than

flattering and thus create a contrast with the focus on fond memories about the deceased that is expected at a funeral.

What is interesting about this scene is the way in which its humour relates to various aspects of shared common ground

between the collective sender and the television audience and thus to different loci at which the audience will infer the

ventriloquist who animates and is animated by the gestures on the surface of the audiovisual text. First of all, insofar as the

individual HIs construct incongruities between the semantic frames of mourning and of sex, drugs and other frames that

are at odds with the traditional eulogy, humour only depends on the communal common ground (Clark, 1996) that the

collective sender will assume between themselves and their audience: The viewers have access to knowledge and

accordingly expectations about what is and what is not part of the proceedings of a funeral, and the descriptions of what

Charlie did in his life are clearly incongruous with those expectations. This is to say that the character interactions are

animated by the narrative frame of the funeral, which is visible in particular by their creation of those gestures -- e.g., Alan's

eulogy and Evelyn's sad voice -- that make it a representation of a funeral in the first place. Secondly, many of the HIs

function as call-backs to scenes that the regular viewer of TAAHM will remember, and they thus also build on experiential

common ground, i.e., they cater to those viewers that have seen Charlie Harper's incongruous behaviour in previous

seasons. In triggering such memories, they make incongruities more vivid and reinforce them, and they thus contribute to

humour. Finally, as in example 1, humour is also informed here by references to events outside the fictional world, insofar

as Charlie Harper's fate is connected to the then recent events in Charlie Sheen's public life. This connection depends on

a range of different factors, which includes the inherent connection between any actor and the character they portray (as

mentioned in Section 3.3). In this case, however, the connection between Harper and Sheen goes beyond the fact that

they inhabit the same onscreen body, and there are clear commonalities between Sheen's public persona and the way in

which Harper is characterised in TAAHM. These notably include drug abuse and sexual promiscuity, which are in turn the

semantic essence of the humorous instances in example 2. More than just serving as general references to shared

aspects between actor and character, they necessarily also activate knowledge about the scandal that led to Sheen's

dismissal, which also involved sex and drugs and at the same time served as an extradiegetic cause for the funeral scene

in the first place.

3.6. Inferring multiple agents

One way of interpreting the tripartite structure of humour in example 2 is in terms of audience design. The collective

sender rewards regular viewers and those that follow celebrity news by referring to the extra knowledge they have access

to due to their viewer experience and reading of news items, respectively. In order to broaden the target audience,

however, they make sure the sitcom's humorous incongruities also work for the less well informed television viewers.

While there are thus 22 humorous incongruities for informed and uninformed viewers alike in the example, the three

different audiences are not equal. It has been pointed out in the humour literature that often do not only rely on one

single incongruity, but may include background incongruities in addition to the main or focal incongruity (Attardo et al.,

2002; Dynel, 2012; Mayerhofer and Schacht, 2013), and Samson and Hempelmann (2011: 181) found in a study on jokes

4

Interestingly, however, the same behavioural pattern of sleeping with as many women as possible is presented in a much more positive light in

the previous eight seasons, as well as in subsequent episodes, when women are again presented as conquests for the newly introduced

character that replaces Charlie and the sitcom thus returns to its unashamed and stereotypical narrative focalisation through the perspective of a heterosexual white male.

28 T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33

and cartoons involving multiple incongruities that removing background incongruities resulted in reduced humour

appreciation and lower ratings of funniness. Similarly, in example 2, access to epitextual information can be regarded as a

basis for background incongruities, which in turn means that humour appreciation will be increased for those audiences

that are more informed. In other words, to get the most out of the opening scene of Season 9 of TAAHM, it is beneficial to

look beyond the current scene and include information from earlier seasons as well as from the news involving Charlie

Sheen.

That characters function as dummies that are ventriloquised not only by the actors that play them, but in this case more

importantly by the producer Chuck Lorre, is thus also directly relevant for humour appreciation. By being interested not

only in character utterances and actions, but also in the agencies that animate them, viewers gain access to background

incongruities, even if it is as simple as understanding that the loss of Harper in the sitcom is also the loss of Sheen, and the

humorous contrast is not only with Harper's but also with Sheen's transgressions. Crucially, then, the ideal viewer does not

decide between either character or collective sender, i.e., between either dummy or ventriloquist, but instead perceives of

every humorous instance as the result of a complex co-production of a dummy in plain sight and a hidden ventriloquist,

who is however manifest in dummy actions and utterances. Example 2 is full of traces of this seemingly paradoxical stance

of the viewers who both play along with the ventriloquist's act while also appreciating its constructedness. If it is beneficial

for the viewers to look beyond the fictional scene at hand, it is no surprise that the collective sender will do work in order to

steer them to those aspects of their previous knowledge whose activation is likely to increase their appreciation of the

humorous incongruities in the text. From a narratological perspective, the diegetic resurrection of the character Charlie

Harper in this scene, which happens through the collective reports about his life, serves as a set of analepses to earlier

episodes of TAAHM and puts the focus on the larger story of the sitcom, which is reinforced by the appearance of

characters that featured in what is now the pre-history to season 9. Epitextual information, on the other hand, is activated

through the references to those behavioural patterns that are common to the fictional and non-fictional lives of Harper and

Sheen, respectively.

From the perspective of the ventriloquised dummies, this means that in each of the HIs in example 2, they do not only

speak on behalf of their present selves, but also on behalf of their past selves, which they animate into being by referring to

this fictional past. This referring back also marks an important contribution to the characterisation of both themselves and

Charlie Harper. Moreover, they speak on behalf of producer Chuck Lorre as that member of the collective sender who has

creative control. Conversely, the two examples can be regarded as a form of interaction between Chuck Lorre and Charlie

Sheen who ventriloquise one or multiple characters in the sitcoms they are involved in to stage a humorous battle.

There are some noteworthy differences between the two examples, however. While the principles of ventriloquism

apply in both cases, i.e., the hidden ventriloquist is animated into being by the performing characters or more generally the

surfaces of the audiovisual texts, this ventriloquist is one collective sender in the case of AM and another in the case of

TAAHM. The ventriloquist could potentially be any subset of those involved in each of the two sitcoms. However, it makes

most sense in this case to simplify the ventriloquism setting to the assumption that AM ultimately speaks on behalf of

Charlie Sheen, whereas TAAHM speaks on behalf of Chuck Lorre.

Just as important for the understanding of the communicative setting of sitcom humour is another difference: Example

2 illustrates instances of humour that function with or without reference to the epitext, which is to say that they are

sufficiently grounded in the fictional story that they are understandable for the television audience even if one were to

assume fully immersed and -- in Clark's (1996) sense -- fully imaginative (and non-appreciative) viewers who are so caught

up in the fictional moment that they are incapable of looking to the larger text, let alone any epitextual information they

might have access to. The incongruities in example 1, on the other hand, are dependent on epitextual knowledge, which is

to say they necessitate a viewer that is willingly playing along while being aware of the constructedness of the performed

monologue. This difference in the positioning of the target audience does however not require a conceptualisation of two

different types of audiences on two different planes. The production, characters, the humour, etc. in both sitcoms are

similar enough that it can be safely assumed that there will have been a large overlap in their actual audiences.

Furthermore, the two examples are not characteristic of each of the two sitcoms in the sense that AM would usually

necessitate less immersed viewers than TAAHM: Either sitcom features HIs that are more or less grounded in the fictional

story and that are more or less dependent on epitextual knowledge (example 3 will illustrate this for TAAHM). First of all,

this serves to support the view that audiences are dynamic and can be repositioned by fictional events and notably by

instances of sitcom humour (Brock, 2015; Messerli, 2016). What the second example illustrates in addition, however, is

that these changes in audience focus cannot be attributed to discrete planes or layers, but need to be understood as

dynamic processes of inferring the ventriloquist at any of the available loci as they were discussed for example 1.

It is important to add here that this inference of the ventriloquist at a particular locus does not deny the existence of the

dummy or the ventriloquist act that is taking place. That the dummy can say what the ventriloquist cannot (Altman, 1980) or

that the dummy gives the ventriloquist power she would otherwise not have (Cooren, 2004) also applies in this case: All

characters possess agency and speak on their own fictional behalf, and all characters are also endpoints of chains of

agency and speak on behalf of a ventriloquist. What the different types of HIs in example 1 and 2 do then is to guide

T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33 29

audience attention to one particular locus and to provide them the opportunity to ascribe agency to a particular

ventriloquist. They do so, however, without denying the multiplicity of co-present agents, which means that alternative

readings remain possible. As a result, stating that Charlie Harper is a chauvinist or that TAAHM is a sexist sitcom are both

possible inferences from watching any episode from its first eight seasons.

3.7. (In-)visible ventriloquists

Example 1 and example 2 both make reference to and require knowledge about the paratatext, but are different in

terms of the way this epitextual information is grounded in the fictional story. Example 3 from the finale of TAAHM

illustrates another relationship between dummies and ventriloquists:

Example 3: Two and a Half Men, Season 12, Episode 15 “Of course he’s dead: Part 1 & 2”,00:29:07–00:29:58 Alan Harper and Walden are at Walden’s (formerly Charlie Harper’s) house, where they both live. Alan’s son Jake who had not appeared on the sitcom in two years surprisingly turns up in the doorway. Alan uses the moment to share with

his son the recent news that Charlie is alive.

1 Alan: here's the thing (.) i- i- it turns out that your uncle Charlie, might still be alive.

Jake: oh (.) that would explain why I got a check for 250,000 dollars and a note that said I'm alive.

LT: hahahaha[hahahaha]

2 Alan: [you have] 250,000 dollars?

Jake: not anymore. I stopped in in Vegas on the way here.

LT: hahahahaha[[ha]]

3 Alan: [[oh]] God. How much do you have le?

Jake: two and a half million.

LT: hahahahaha[haha]

4 Alan: [a::::h]

£---nearly faints---£

Walden: o:::h

ç---catches Alan---ç LT: Hahahahahaha[haha]

5 Walden: [you] won two and a half million dollars?

Jake: oh yeah (.)it's not that hard, I kept playing craps because (.) you know (.) crap.

LT: Hahahahahahaha[ha]

6 Jake: [oh,] and I kept beng on come, because hahaha you guys

LT: hahahaha[hahahaha]

7 Walden: [wow that's] amazing that you made so much money with such stupid jokes

LT: hahahahahahahahahahahahah

8 £---turns to the camera and smiles---£

ç---turns to the camera and smiles---ç

^---turns to the camera and shrugs his shoulders---^ LT: hahahahahahahaha £Alan ç Walden

^ Jake

While HIs 1--6 serve as context of example 3, I want to focus on HIs 7 and 8 here, which together constitute a two-part

joke targeting Chuck Lorre. As mentioned above, the finale is generally full of references to earlier moments in TAAHM as

well as to the epitext. In HI3, for instance, knowledge about the character Jake who was characterised as dim, goofy and

generally as a no-good is reactivated and serves to motivate and reinforce the incongruity: The regular viewers will share

Alan's assumption in HI 3 that Jake will have lost money in Las Vegas. In HI 4, the fact that Alan nearly faints will be

understood as coherent with his characterisation as penniless, stingy, yet greedy for money, and HIs 5 and 6 tie in with the

30 T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33

simple jokes that Jake was associated with when he appeared regularly on the sitcom. Thus, when Walden in HI 7 jokes

about making money with stupid jokes, Jake is a plausible target. This grounding in the fictional story of course only thinly

disguises that the joke is also targeting Chuck Lorre. The gesture in HI 8 serves as a recontextualisation of the same joke

and this time leaves no doubt that humour here goes beyond the world of the characters: all three characters turn towards

the camera and direct the viewers’ attention to the epitext and more precisely to Chuck Lorre, who is now being targeted as

the one responsible for the stupid jokes.

Even though HI 8 stands out because of the breaking with telecinematic conventions (characters looking straight into

the camera), which serves as a clear hint to the epitext, the humorous instance it constructs is admittedly simple. It is

interesting in terms of agency, however, because it involves the viewers, the characters, the actors and the producer of

TAAHM in one simple joke. The decisive move in this HI is of course the synchronised gesture that all three characters

perform together. They point to the camera and thus metonymically to the epitext, and we, the television audience can

then laugh about Chuck Lorre who might have written, but certainly oversaw those ‘‘stupid jokes’’, and perhaps as well

about ourselves, the accomplices who dutifully laugh about said jokes. But who is the ventriloquist that animates this

gesture? Initially, it is certainly the characters who just performed a series of jokes about each other and their past. In

turning to the camera, however, the characters reveal that they are ventriloquised by actors, since -- as pointed out in the

discussion of example 1 -- only actors have access to the epitext, whereas characters are contained within their fictional

surroundings. Thirdly, however, the fact that they all turn simultaneously points to the orchestration of the scene, to the

scriptedness of their behaviour and thus ultimately to Chuck Lorre as the ventriloquist who animates the scene.

It follows that the simple joke changes in its essence within only a few seconds. The audience at first plays along with

what I have called the fictional ventriloquism effect here and accepts the gesture to be animated by the characters. They

align with the speaker, Walden, and by laughing about the jab at Jake, disassociate themselves from the target. Then, the

viewers’ attention is steered towards the actors who laugh at Chuck Lorre. They witness how the characters seemingly

concede their agency and turn into the actors that animate them. At the same time, however, the viewers see that the

actors, too, are moved in synchrony by yet another ventriloquist, the producer, and they are amused by Chuck Lorre

sanctioning humour targeted at himself, while also appreciating their own complicity in the transgression of the narrative

conventions of TCD. Technically, the complexity of this simple joke is even further complicated by the fact that these

subsequent moves that take the viewers through different parts of the chain of agency behind the gesture in HI 8 are in fact

themselves yet another fiction. The production of the actors’ apparent concession of their character-roles is of course

identical to the production of any other scene in TAAHM. Put differently, the ostentatious revelation of ventriloquists in this

scene is in fact another ventriloquist's trick, which can only pretend to point to its own construction. As is the case with any

mise-en-abyme (see Prince, 1987: 53; Flückiger, 2008: 394--416), of which this scene here is an example, it can only point

from within the containment of the fiction, which means that any gesture reduplicates and fictionalises what it points to.

Irrespective of such meta-fictional considerations, the three moves emphasise (actually or fictionally) the different agents

that are involved in the production of any instance of sitcom humour and that are manifest to different degrees in the

audiovisual text. The television audience is thus guided to one locus or another at any given moment, and in sum is

perpetually reminded that being a recipient of a sitcom means witnessing an elaborate act of ventriloquism.

4. Conclusion

The three examples from the sitcoms Anger Management (AM) and Two and a Half Men (TAAHM) that were discussed

here serve to illustrate the way in which sitcom communication can be conceptualised as a form of ventriloquism. The

dynamic inferring of agencies by the viewers that I have shown to be instrumental for humour comprehension can only

partially be captured with existing spatial models of telecinematic communicative settings. It is this more dynamic

understanding of different roles or agencies as well as the emphasis on a range of coexisting processes (ventriloquism

effects on different levels) that the conceptual ventriloquism metaphor offers as an analytical tool. The examples highlight

in particular what different loci in the chain of agency are involved in sitcom production as communication, and thus point

to how the interacting dummies onscreen -- by which I mean not only the fictional characters, but the whole multimodal

surface of the audiovisual text -- reveal themselves to be speaking not only on their own behalf but also on behalf of the

actors that portray them and of the producer that has creative control over their actions, which includes the jokes they

perform. Any instance of humour in this domain involves the entire ventriloquist chain of agency, which is to say that the

dummies always speak for themselves as well as for all production events that lead to their performance at any time, and

also that within the space of the sitcom, producers and actors as ventriloquists are always communicating with the

television audience by animating these dummies. While in principle all scenes of the two sitcoms are thus identical when it

comes to the way in which they communicate, the different examples reveal that viewers need to be more, or less aware of

this multiplicity of agents depending on the way humour is constructed in any given scene. Example 1 displays humour

that depends on the audience's knowledge of what has here been referred to as the epitext, i.e., to aspects relevant for the

production that are however not part of the text itself. Example 2 also includes such epitextual references, but at the same

T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33 31

time invests more resources into the fictional ventriloquism effect by making sure that the humorous incongruities are not

only sufficiently motivated by fictional events, but are also based on incongruities that can exist in absence of any

epitextual knowledge. Nonetheless, this second example includes clear cues that animate the informed viewers to look

past the fiction and equate the fictional character with the actor Charlie Sheen, who thus becomes the target of most of the

humorous instances in the scene. Example 3, finally, demonstrates the dynamic change within a short humorous scene

from a focus on the fictional narrative frame and incongruities contained within it, to an emphasis on the ventriloquists that

animate that same scene.

Together, the three examples thus provide a partial view of a spectrum between those scenes that can be described as

maximally fictional and are essentially performed jokes independent of any other context than what is immediately

encoded in the scene and, at the other extreme, scenes that are maximally epitextual, as is the case when Chuck Lorre

appears before the sitcom stage and speaks to the audience in the final scene of TAAHM. Between those two extremes is

the range of more typical cases that were exemplified in section 3. They make clear that television viewers are positioned

as an audience that has the perceptual predisposition as well as the will to play along and interpret the dummies’ actions in

this ventriloquist act as animated by the dummies themselves, while at the same time being capable of appreciating the

ventriloquist's role in the act. Given the fact that viewers are used to such chains of agencies from other domains --

Cooren's (2004) example of the note through which an institution can speak to its employees being just one case in point --

the simultaneous recognition of dummy agency and ventriloquist agency in the processing of sitcom humour is not

different in principle from the reception of other acts of communication. However, the way in which audiences are made

aware of the different places from which humorous incongruities are animated, and the self-reflexive way in which the

communicative setting itself is exploited for humour (as was done in example 3) make sitcom humour and telecinematic

discourse more generally a uniquely illustrative example of communication as ventriloquism.

The feud between Charlie Sheen and Chuck Lorre, enacted in and mediated through different texts and practices, is

also carried out in the two sitcoms AM and TAAHM, in which each of the two television personalities create their own

ventriloquist act in order to engage in a sort of humorous battle that served the dual purpose of entertaining their audiences

while also attacking their opponent. In so doing, they make use of a complex form of say-foring and indeed make public

their own views through the sitcoms (Lorenzo-Dus, 2009), which is to say that the sitcoms serve as a way for Lorre and

Sheen ‘‘to represent their own meaning’’ (Tannen, 2010: 310). Whereas in interviews each of the two opponents speaks

on behalf of himself, which also means that these interviews animate into being the two public personae of Sheen and

Lorre, the sitcoms thus continued the interaction in a fictional form: through fictional events that allude directly to epitextual

events without clearly grounding them in the fiction (example 1); through fictional events that are ambiguously motivated

by both the fiction and by real-life events (example 2); or through fictional events that are initially motivated by the fiction,

but slowly turn into gestures that speak as agents on behalf of Lorre and Sheen (example 3).

This polyvalence is mirrored in the understanding of sitcom as ventriloquism, which assumes that all those involved in

the humorous sitcom performance are located at a particular place on the chain of agency, not unlike the narratological

distribution of voices between an author and a reader that was similarly conceptualised by O’Neill (1994). Instead of

envisioning the television audience as co-present on two different planes, the fictional one and the one between

themselves and the collective sender, they are thus understood as interpreters of dummy actions that are animated by

multiple agents at the same time. In the audiovisual text, different degrees of reference to textual and epitextual knowledge

are manifest and thus different agencies are foregrounded at different moments in each of the two sitcoms. This dynamic

understanding of inferring a particular ventriloquist based on textual cues is also mirrored in a dynamic understanding of

the television audience who processes the resulting incongruities that involve any one of the involved agents or several of them at once.

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the two anonymous reviewers for their comments on an earlier version of this paper. This research

did not receive any specific grant from funding agencies in the public, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.

Appendix A. Transcription conventions (based on Jefferson, 2004; Mondada, 2014)

[ ] overlapping speech (including laughter)

(.) gap between utterances

{} telecinematic events such as camera movements, cuts, etc.

< > description of voice quality

= latch

__ stress

: indicates lengthening of the previous sound

32 T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33

., ? ! punctuation indicates usual intonation

haha laughter

* Æ § ^ symbols to identify participants

*----* delimits action/facial expression by participant

*----> action continues on subsequent line(s)

----* action ends

34 number in left-hand column refers to humorous instance

References

Altman, R., 1980. Moving lips: cinema as ventriloquism. Yale French Stud. (60), 67--79.

Attardo, S., Hempelmann, C.F., Di Maio, S., 2002. Script oppositions and logical mechanisms: modeling incongruities and their resolutions.

Humor 15 (1), 3--46. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/humr.2002.004

Bakhtin, M.M., 1981. Discourse in the novel (C. Emerson, M. Holquist, Trans.) In: Holquist, M. (Ed.), The Dialogic Imagination: Four Essays by M.

M. Bakhtin. The University of Texas Press, Austin. pp. 259--422.

Bakhtin, M.M., 1986. The problem of speech genres (V.W. McGee, Trans.) In: Emerson, C., Holquist, M. (Eds.), Speech Genres and Other Late

Essays. The University of Texas Press, Austin. (Original work published 1952--1953), pp. 60--102. (Original work published 1952--1953).

Bateson, G., 1979. Mind and Nature: A Necessary Unity. Ballantine, New York.

Bednarek, M., 2010. The Language of Fictional Television: Drama and Identity. Continuum, .

Booth, W.C., 1961. The Rhetoric of Fiction. University of Chicago Press, Chicago.

Brock, A., 2015. Participation frameworks and participation in televised sitcom, candid camera and stand-up comedy. In: Dynel, M., Chovanec, J.

(Eds.), Participation in Public and Social Media Interactions. John Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp. 27--47. http://dx.doi.org/10.1075/

pbns.256.02bro

Bubel, C.M., 2006. The Linguistic Construction of Character Relations in TV Drama: Doing Friendship in Sex and the City. Universität des

Saarlandes Retrieved from http://scidok.sulb.uni-saarland.de/volltexte/2006/598/pdf/Diss_Bubel_publ.pdf

Bubel, C.M., 2008. Film audiences as overhearers. J. Pragmat. 40 (1), 55--71. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2007.10.001

Bubnova, T., Malcuzynski, M.-P., 2001, July The invention of Bakhtin (or the art of ventriloquism and other alien [counter]feits). In: Paper

presented at the Tenth International Conference on Bakhtin, .

Bucholtz, M., Hall, K., 2005. Identity and interaction: a sociocultural linguistic approach. Discourse Stud. 7 (4--5), 585--614. http://dx.doi.org/

10.1177/1461445605054407

Clark, H.H., 1996. Using Language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Cooren, F., 2004. Textual agency: How texts do things in organizational settings. Organization 11 (3), 373--393. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/

1350508404041998

Cooren, F., 2008. Between semiotics and pragmatics: Opening language studies to textual agency. J. Pragmat. 40 (1), 1--16. http://dx.doi.org/

10.1016/j.pragma.2006.11.018

Cooren, F., 2010. Action and Agency in Dialogue Passion, Incarnation and Ventriloquism. John Benjamins, Amsterdam. http://dx.doi.org/10.1075/

ps.4.3.07ita

Cooren, F., 2012. Communication Theory at the center: Ventriloquism and the Communicative Constitution of Reality. J. Commun. 62 (1), 1--20.

http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1460-2466.2011.01622.x

Cooren, F., 2013. Incarnation, sensation and ventriloquism: for a sensitive and constitutive view of pragmatics. J. Pragmat. 58, 42--45. http://dx.

doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2013.09.017

Cooren, F., Matte, F., Benoit-Barné, C., Brummans, B.H.J.M., 2013. Communication as Ventriloquism: A Grounded-in-Action Approach to the

Study of Organizational Tensions. Commun. Monogr. 80 (3), 255--277. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/03637751.2013.788255

Derrida, J., 1988. Limited Inc.. Northwestern University Press, Evanston, IL.

Dynel, M., 2011. ‘‘You talking to me?’’ The viewer as a ratified listener to film discourse. J. Pragmat. 43 (6), 1628--1644. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.

pragma.2010.11.016

Dynel, M., 2012. Garden-paths, red lights and crossroads: on finding our way to understanding the cognitive mechanisms underlying jokes. Isr. J.

Humor Res. 1 (1), 6--28.

Flückiger, B., 2008. Visual Effects: Filmblider aus dem Computer. Schüren, Marburg, Germany.

Genette, G., 1980. Narrative Discourse: An Essay in Method (J.E. Lewin, Trans.). Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY (Original work published

1972).

Genette, G., 1997. Paratexts: Thresholds of Interpretation. Literature, Culture. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/

CBO9780511549373

Goffman, E., 1979. Footing. Semiotica 25 (1--2), 1--29. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2075701

Goffman, E., 1986. Frame Analysis: An Essay on the Organization of Experience. Northeastern University Press, Boston, MA.

Iser, W., 1972. Der Implizite Leser, vol. 53. Wilhelm Fink Verlag, München.

Jefferson, G., 2004. Glossary of transcript symbols with an introduction. In: Lerner, G.H. (Ed.), Conversation Analysis: Studies from the First

Generation. John Benjamins, Amsterdam. pp. 13--31, Retrieved from http://www.liso.ucsb.edu/liso_archives/Jefferson/Transcript.pdf.

Levinson, S.C., 1987. Putting linguistics on a proper footing: explorations in Goffman's concepts of participation. In: Drew, P., Wootton, A. (Eds.),

Goffman: Exploring the Interaction Order. Polity Press, Oxford, pp. 161--227.

Lorenzo-Dus, N., 2009. Television Discourse: Analysing Language in the Media. Palgr, Basingstoke.

Mayerhofer, B., Schacht, A., 2013. Salience, accessibility, and humorous potential in the comprehension of garden path jokes: a probabilistic

approach. In: Dynel, M. (Ed.), Developments in Linguistic Humour Theory. John Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp. 341--366.

T.C. Messerli / Lingua 197 (2017) 16--33 33

Messerli, T.C., 2016. Extradiegetic and character laughter as markers of humorous intentions in the sitcom 2 Broke Girls. J. Pragmat. 95, 79--92.

http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.pragma.2015.12.009

Messerli, T.C., 2017a. Participation structure in fictional discourse: authors, scriptwriters, audiences and characters. In: Locher, M.A., Jucker, A.H.

(Eds.), Pragmatics of Fiction. Handbooks of Pragmatics, vol. 12. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp. 25--54.

Messerli, T.C., 2017b. Repetition in Sitcom Humour. Manuscript submitted for publication.

Mondada, L., 2014. Conventions for Multimodal Transcription. Retrieved from https://franz.unibas.ch/fileadmin/franz/user_upload/redaktion/

Mondada_conv_multimodality.pdf

O’Neill, P., 1994. Fictions of Discourse: Reading Narrative Theory. University of Toronto Press, Toronto, Canada.

Piazza, R., Bednarek, M., Rossi, F., 2011. Introduction: Analysing Telecinematic Discourse. In: Piazza, R., Bednarek, M., Rossi, F. (Eds.),

Telecinematic Discourse: Approaches to the Language of Films and Television Series. John Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp. 1--17.

Prince, G., 1987. A Dictionary of Narratology. University of Nebraska Press, Lincoln, NE.

Samson, A.C., Hempelmann, C.F., 2011. Humor with Backgrounded Incongruity: Does More Required Suspension of Disbelief Affect Humor

Perception? Humor 24 (2), 167--185. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/HUMR.2011.011

Schiffrin, D., 1993. ‘‘Speaking for another’’ in sociolinguistic interviews: alignments, identities, and frames. In: Tannen (Eds.), Framing in

Discourse. Oxford University Press, New York, pp. 231--255.

Scollon, R., 2001. Mediated Discourse: The Nexus of Practice. Routledge, London.

Suls, J.M., 1972. A two-stage model for the appreciation of jokes and cartoons: an information-processing analysis. In: Goldstein, J.H., McGhee,

P.E. (Eds.), The Psychology of Humor: Theoretical Perspectives and Empirical Issues. Academic Press, New York, NY, pp. 81--100.

Tannen, D., 2004. Talking the dog: framing pets as interactional resources in family discourse. Res. Lang. Soc. Interact. 37 (4), 399--420. http://dx.

doi.org/10.1207/s15327973rlsi3704

Tannen, D., 2010. Abduction and identity in family interaction: ventriloquizing as indirectness. J. Pragmat. 42 (2), 307--316. http://dx.doi.org/

10.1016/j.pragma.2009.06.002

Vroomen, J., de Gelder, B., 2004. Perceptual effects of cross-modal stimulation: ventriloquism and the freezing phenomenon. In: Calvert, G.A.,

Spence, C., Stein, B.E. (Eds.), The Handbook of Multisensory Purposes. MIT Press, Cambridge MA, pp. 141--150.

Yahr, E., 2015 February 19 Let’ s All Remember the Infamous Charlie Sheen ‘‘Two and a Half Men’’ Meltdown. The Washington Post, Washington, D.C.

Retrieved from https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/arts-and-entertainment/wp/2015/02/19/lets-all-remember-the-infamous-charlie- sheen-two-and-a-half-men-meltdown/

Television series:

Cadiff, A. (Director), Helford, B. (Writer), 2012. ‘‘Charlie goes back to therapy’’. In: B. Helford (Creator), Anger Management. FX, Los Angeles.

Roberts, M. (Creator), 2010--2016. Mike & Molly. CBS, Los Angeles.

Widdoes, J. (Director), Lorre, C. (Writer), Aronsohn, L. (Writer), 2011. ‘‘Nice to meet you, Walden Schmidt’’. In: L. Aronsohn, C. Lorre (Creators),

Two and a Half Men. CBS, Los Angeles.

Widdoes, J. (Director), Lorre, C. (Writer), Aronsohn, L. (Writer), 2015. ‘‘Of course he's dead: Part 1 & 2’’. In: L. Aronsohn, C. Lorre (Creators), Two

and a Half Men. CBS, Los Angeles.