Chapter Nine

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Chapter Nine Chapter Nine Is There Immediate Justification? You have immediate justification for believing that p if, and only if, your justification for believing that p does not depend on any justification you have for believing some other proposition, q. James Pryor defends the claim that such justification exists. According to him, the best argument in its support is not the regress argument, according to which unacceptable alternatives – justification coming from an infinite regress of reasons, from a circular chain of reasons, or from initial beliefs that are not themselves justified – lend support to the conclusion that there must be immediate justification. Rather, Pryor argues, the best way to defend the existence of immediately justified beliefs is to cite examples of such beliefs, such as “I am tired” or “I have a headache.” Pryor provides additional support for immediate justification by criticizing what he calls the “Master Argument for Coherentism.” In his essay, Juan Comesaña raises a serious problem for the view that there are immediately justified beliefs. He argues that a view like Pryor’s is committed to four principles each of which is, by itself, exceedingly plausible. Unfortunately, the four principles are inconsistent. In response to Comesaña, Pryor singles out and rejects what Comesaña calls the Entailment Principle. Comesaña, in turn, defends the principle in his reply to Pryor. There Is Immediate Justification James Pryor 1 Justification I want to talk about a certain epistemic quality that I call “justification,” and inquire whether that quality can ever be had “immediately” or “non-inferentially.” Before we Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, Second Edition. Edited by Matthias Steup, John Turri, and Ernest Sosa. © 2014 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. Published 2014 by John Wiley & Sons, Inc. get into substantive issues, we need first to agree about what epistemic quality it is we’ll be talking about, and then we need to clarify what it is to have that quality imme- diately or non-inferentially. When I say I call this epistemic quality “justification,” you are liable to think, “Oh I know what that is.” You may. But experience has taught me that different philosophers use and understand the term “justification” differently, even before they start spinning substantive theories about what “justification” amounts to. So we should proceed cautiously. You may use the term “justification” to describe the same epistemic quality as I do; or you may use it to describe some different status or quality. You may use some other term, or no term at all, to describe the quality I call “justification.” I say that you have justification to believe P iff you are in a position where it would be epistemically appropriate for you to believe P, a position where P is episte- mically likely for you to be true. I intend this to be a very inclusive epistemic status.1 Some philosophers say you can know P without “having any justification” for your belief. We can assume that whenever a subject knows P, she will be in a position where it would be epistemically appropriate to believe P. So on my usage, whoever knows P has justification to believe P. (Perhaps she has that justification because she knows.) The philosophers who say otherwise are using “having justification” to mean something different, or more specific, than the epistemic status I am using it to mean. The same goes for philosophers who say a belief can be epistemically appro- priate, and so play a role in justifying other beliefs, though you do not “have any justification” for it. On my usage, all it means to have justification to believe something is that it is appropriate for you to believe it, and to rely on that belief in forming other beliefs. Some philosophers call this epistemic status “entitlement” or “warrant,” rather than “justification.” For the sake of a shared discussion, though, we need to fix on a single terminology. If there is some state or condition you are in in virtue of which you have justifica- tion to believe P, I’ll call it a “justification-making condition,” or a justification maker for short. This is a condition that makes it epistemically appropriate (or more appro- priate) for you to believe P, rather than disbelieve P or suspend judgment. It is a truth maker for your having justification to believe P. (Firth, 1964, called these conditions “warrant-increasing properties.”) We can say that conditions of this sort justify you in believing P. They are justifiers. (We will encounter a different way to understand talk of “justifiers” in section 6 below.) In what follows, it will be useful for us to distinguish between having justification to believe P, and actually appropriately holding a belief in P. To have justification to believe P, it is not important whether you actually do believe P (nor, if you do, why you do); there just have to be things that make believing P an appropriate attitude for you to have. To appropriately believe P more is required. You need to believe P; you need to have justification to believe P; and you also need to believe P on the right grounds. You need to believe it for reasons that make you have justification to believe it; you can’t believe it for other, bad reasons, or on a whim.2 There are further conditions as well: for instance, you need to be taking proper account of any evidence you have that tells against or undercuts your grounds for believing P. I describe another further condition in Pryor (2004). Only when all such conditions are met will your belief in P be appropriately held. There Is Immediate Justification 203 2 Immediate Justification Now that we have a grip on the notion of “justification,” let’s clarify what it means to talk about “immediate justification.” For some propositions, you have justification to believe them because other propositions you have justification to believe epistemically support them. For instance, suppose you look at the gas gauge of your car, and it appears to read “E.” So you have justification to believe: (Gauge) The gas gauge reads “E.” That, together with other things you justifiedly believe about your car, gives you justification to believe: (Gas) Your car is out of gas. (It is not important for our purposes whether you actually do believe (Gauge) or (Gas). Given your evidence, you ought to believe them.) In this example, your justi- fication to believe (Gas) comes in part from the fact that you have justification to believe (Gauge). That is, having justification to believe the latter is part of what makes you have justification to believe the former. The justification you have in this example to believe (Gauge) does not in the same way come from your having justification to believe (Gas). (One mark of this is that evidence that undercut your justification to believe (Gauge) would ipso facto undercut your justification to believe (Gas); but not vice versa.) When your justification to believe P comes in part from your having justification to believe other, supporting propositions, I will say that those latter propositions mediate your justification to believe P. (This kind of justification is sometimes called “inferential” justification. We will encounter a second way in which justification can be “inferential” later.) When your justification to believe P does not come from your justification to believe other propositions, I will call it immediate. Some clarifications.3 First, the question whether your justification to believe P is mediate or immediate is a question about what kind of epistemic support you have for P. It is not a question about how much support you have: nothing in our definition requires immediately justified beliefs to be infallible or indefeasible. Nor is it a question about what psychological processes you have undergone. The support you have to believe P can be mediate (or “inferential”) even if you didn’t arrive at P by deriving or inferring it from other beliefs. Second, in order for you to have immediate justification to believe P, it is not required that your justification comes from nowhere, that there is nothing that makes you so justi- fied. It is only required that what makes you justified doesn’t include having justification for other beliefs.4 There are various proposals about what can make one have immediate justification. For example, perhaps you are immediately justified in believing you feel tired because you do feel tired. Perhaps you are immediately justified in believing that tiredness is a mental state because you understand what tiredness is. And so on. It may be 204 James Pryor that there is no single correct account. Different propositions may be justified by different kinds of things. Third, the fact that you have immediate justification to believe P does not entail that no other beliefs are required for you to be able to form or entertain the belief that P. Having the concepts involved in the belief that P may require believing certain other propositions; it does not follow that any justification you have to believe P must be mediated by those other propositions.5 Fourth, justification is usually defeasible. What a justification maker for P gives you is provisional or prima facie justification to believe P; and that is what I am saying can be mediate or immediate. Whether it is all things considered appropriate for you to believe P will depend on what other evidence you possess, and whether it defeats the prima facie justification you have to believe P. Fifth, beliefs can be epistemically overdetermined. You can have immediate justifi- cation and independent mediate justification to believe the same thing.
Recommended publications
  • GAGE-DISSERTATION-2014.Pdf (1.774Mb)
    ABSTRACT Objectivity and Subjectivity in Epistemology: A Defense of the Phenomenal Conception of Evidence Logan Paul Gage, Ph.D. Committee Chairperson: Trent Dougherty, Ph.D. We all have an intuitive grasp of the concept of evidence. Evidence makes beliefs reasonable, justifies jury verdicts, and helps resolve our disagreements. Yet getting clear about what evidence is is surprisingly difficult. Among other possibilities, evidence might consist in physical objects like a candlestick found at the crime scene, propositions like ‘a candlestick was found at the crime scene,’ or experiences like the experience of witnessing a candlestick at the crime scene. This dissertation is a defense of the latter view. Evidence, we will argue, consists in experiences or mental states called ‘seeming states.’ We begin with a look at why the logical positivists came to abandon the experiential or “phenomenal” conception of evidence and adopted what I call “the courtroom conception.” Despite its appeal, we argue that this latter view is too objective; it has trouble playing the role of subjective reasons-provider. Being more subjective, the phenomenal conception deserves another look. However, many have thought that the phenomenal conception itself is unable to fulfill other important roles of evidence. In Chapter Two we dispute this, arguing that the phenomenal conception can play all four of the chief roles of evidence. Examining the religious epistemology of Alvin Plantinga in Chapter Three we come to see that the phenomenal conception, while attractive, is in danger of being too subjective. If the phenomenal conception of evidence is to be tenable, it must be offered in conjunction with a conservative epistemic principle which tethers together experiences with the beliefs they evidence in an epistemically appropriate manner.
    [Show full text]
  • PGR Faculty List 2021 ALL Departments 24August2021 Draft
    Faculty Lists fall 2021 Email: [email protected] for corrections. Current update: 8/24/2021 #=75 or older in 2021 (* was over 70 in 2017 list) Part-time faculty are half-time, unless otherwise noted. UNITED STATES (the top 50 will be ranked) FACULTY # Arizona Faculty: Sara Aronowitz, Thomas Christiano, Stewart Cohen, Juan Comesaña, Reza Hadisi, RiChard Healey, Laura, Howard, J. Christopher Maloney, MiChael McKenna, Bill OberdiCK, Guido PinCione, Marga Reimer, Daniel Russell, Carolina Sartorio, David SChmidtz, Houston Smit, MarK Timmons, Joseph Tolliver, Jason Turner, Steven Wall, Jonathan Weinberg. Part-time faculty: *Allen Buchanan (.25 time) Cognate faculty and philosophers in other units: Martin FriCKe, Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini, Christopher Robertson, Simone Sepe. FACULTY # Arizona State Faculty: RiChard Amesbury, Brad Armendt, Thomas BlaCKson, Cheshire Calhoun, Peter de Marneffe, Typer DesRoChes, MarCello Di Bello, Peter Kung, Joan MCGregor, Shyam Nair, Ben Phillips, Nestor Ángel Pinillos, Douglas W. Portmore, Maura Priest, Steven Reynolds. Part-time faculty: Cognate faculty and philosophers in other units: RiChard Creath, Tyler DesRoChes, ZaChary Horne, Ted Humphrey, PatriCia J. Huntingon, Manfred LaubiChler, Jane MainesChein, Martin BeCK MatuštíK, Ben A. Minteer, *Jeffrie G. Murphy, BeCKett Sterner, Jason Robert, Hava Tirosh-Samuelson, Norbert Samuelson, BeCKett Sterner. FACULTY # BerKeley Faculty: Olivia Bailey, John Campbell, Timothy ClarKe, Shamik Dasgupta, Johann FriCK, Hannah Ginsborg, Florian Grosser, Wesley H. Holliday, NiKo Kolodny, Geoffrey Lee, John MaCFarlane, Paolo ManCosu, Alva Noë, Andreja NovaKoviC, Kristin Primus, R. Jay WallaCe, Daniel Warren, Seth Yalcin, Xueyin (Snow) Zhang. Part-time Faculty: Joshua Cohen (.25 time), MiChael (M.G.F.) Martin, Veronique Munoz Darde, Kwong-Loi Shun. Cognate Faculty and Philosophers in Other Units: Asad Q.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Phil. 4400 Notes #1: the Problem of Induction I. Basic Concepts
    Phil. 4400 Notes #1: The problem of induction I. Basic concepts: The problem of induction: • Philosophical problem concerning the justification of induction. • Due to David Hume (1748). Induction: A form of reasoning in which a) the premises say something about a certain group of objects (typically, observed objects) b) the conclusion generalizes from the premises: says the same thing about a wider class of objects, or about further objects of the same kind (typically, the unobserved objects of the same kind). • Examples: All observed ravens so far have been The sun has risen every day for the last 300 black. years. So (probably) all ravens are black. So (probably) the sun will rise tomorrow. Non-demonstrative (non-deductive) reasoning: • Reasoning that is not deductive. • A form of reasoning in which the premises are supposed to render the conclusion more probable (but not to entail the conclusion). Cogent vs. Valid & Confirm vs. Entail : ‘Cogent’ arguments have premises that confirm (render probable) their conclusions. ‘Valid’ arguments have premises that entail their conclusions. The importance of induction: • All scientific knowledge, and almost all knowledge depends on induction. • The problem had a great influence on Popper and other philosophers of science. Inductive skepticism: Philosophical thesis that induction provides no justification for ( no reason to believe) its conclusions. II. An argument for inductive skepticism 1. There are (at most) 3 kinds of knowledge/justified belief: a. Observations b. A priori knowledge c. Conclusions based on induction 2. All inductive reasoning presupposes the “Inductive Principle” (a.k.a. the “uniformity principle”): “The course of nature is uniform”, “The future will resemble the past”, “Unobserved objects will probably be similar to observed objects” 3.
    [Show full text]
  • PHI230 Philosophy of Science
    Department of Philosophy Level 2 Module PHI230 Philosophy of Science LECTURER: George Botterill Office Hours Wed 12-1, Fri 1-2; external tel: (0114)2220580; email: [email protected] Lectures: Monday 2-3 in Hicks Building LT6 Friday 11-12 in Hicks Building LT5 Seminars: See MOLE unit to join: Monday 4-5 Jessop Building 215, Friday 12-1 Jessop Building 215 GENERAL OUTLINE This course will deal with major issues in the philosophy of science, with particular emphasis on the rationality of theory-change, explanation, the status of scientific laws, observation, and the structure of scientific theories. Most of the course will be devoted to the methodology of natural science, though we may also discuss some issues in the philosophy of the social sciences. Most of the issues presented revolve around two major debates in the philosophy of science: (1) the dispute between Kuhn and Popper about theory change (2) disagreements between positivist (or instrumentalist) and realist conceptions of science. Modern philosophy of science has become closely linked with the history of science. The course will reflect this by considering how well major developments in the history of science fit proposed methodological rules about how science ought to proceed. The Copernican Revolution in astronomy will be used as a case-study. 1 AIMS AND OBJECTIVES The main aims of this module are: • to introduce students to the debate about theory-change in science, deriving from the work of Popper, Kuhn, Feyerabend and Lakatos • to help students acquire an understanding of some important problems in the philosophy of science (concerning the topics of: explanation, observation, scientific realism, and the nature of laws) • to encourage students to enter into serious engagement with some of the major problems in the philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • Barnett CV January 2016
    David James Barnett Department of Philosophy • 807 Union Street • Schenectady, NY 12308 917 657 5326 • [email protected] • www.davidjamesbar.net AREAS OF Epistemology, Philosophy of Mind SPECIALIZATION AREAS OF Early Modern Philosophy, Logic, Philosophy of Language, Bioethics COMPETENCE ACADEMIC Union College. 2012-present, Assistant Professor, Philosophy Department APPOINTMENTS Union College. 2012-present, Affiliated Professor, Neuroscience Program New York University. 2015-2016, Visiting Scholar, Philosophy Department University of Edinburgh. Summer 2013, Visiting Fellow, Eidyn research center EDUCATION New York University. 2003-2012, PhD New College of Florida. 1998-2003, BA (Honors) in Philosophy and Cognitive Science DISSERTATION Self-Knowledge and the Boundaries of the Mind Committee: Paul Boghossian (chair), Don Garrett, James Pryor PUBLICATIONS “Perceptual Justification and the Cartesian Theater”, forthcoming Oxford Studies in Epistemology. Runner-up, 2015 Marc Sanders Prize in Epistemology “Inferential Justification and the Transparency of Belief ”, 2016 Noûs 50(1): 184-212. “Is Memory Merely Testimony from One’s Former Self?”, 2015 Philosophical Review 124(3): 353-392. “What’s the Matter With Epistemic Circularity?”, 2014 Philosophical Studies 171(2): 177-205. WORKS IN “Moore’s Paradox and Self-Knowledge” draft available PROGRESS “Epistemic Autonomy and the Cartesian Circle” draft available “A Note on Egan’s Counterexamples to Causal Decision Theory” draft available “Higher-Order Evidence is the Wrong Kind of Reason” outline
    [Show full text]
  • Seminar in Epistemology: Fallibilism (PHIL 468)
    Seminar in Epistemology: Fallibilism (PHIL 468) Professor Baron Reed Spring Quarter, 2012 office: 3-225 Kresge Hall 2-345 Kresge Hall email: [email protected] T 4:00-6:50 office hours: T/Th 12:30-1:30 and by appointment Course Description: “We are all fallibilists nowadays,” says Michael Williams. This is almost entirely true. But, despite its near-universal acceptance, fallibilism remains poorly understood. There are significant problems that follow in its wake—e.g,. the Gettier problem and the Lottery Paradox. Moreover, some philosophers claim more for knowledge than fallibilism can deliver, tying knowledge to assertion, practical rationality, and epistemic possibility. Finally, some philosophers think that the very idea of fallibilism is suspect; if the view is correct, it means “the world must do us a favor,” as John McDowell puts it. But the whole point of knowledge, one might have thought, is that it puts one in such a position that favors are not needed. In this seminar, we will investigate whether fallibilism has the resources to meet some or all of these concerns. Required Texts: Readings to be posted on Blackboard. Required Work: Work for the course will include a short paper, a presentation, a commentary on a classmate’s paper, and a final paper: 20% Short paper (4-5 pages) 20% Presentation (4-5 pages) 10% Comments (2 pages) 50% Final Paper (10 pages) Excellent class participation may also factor into the final grade. Course Policies: (1) Regular contributions to discussion will be expected. (2) Extensions must be requested before the due date.
    [Show full text]
  • Against Parthood* in Karen Bennett and Dean W
    Against Parthood* In Karen Bennett and Dean W. Zimmerman, eds., Oxford Theodore Sider Studies in Metaphysics, volume 8 (Oxford: OUP, 2013): 237– 93 I will defend what Peter van Inwagen calls nihilism: composite entities (entities with proper parts) do not exist.1 This formulation will need to be rened, and, at the very end of the paper, softened a little. But let us stick to the simple, strong version for now. Nihilism may seem absurd. For the world of common sense and science consists primarily of composite entities: persons, animals, plants, planets, stars, galaxies, molecules, viruses, rocks, mountains, rivers, tables, chairs, telephones, skyscrapers, cities… According to nihilism, none of these entities exist. But it is not absurd to reject such entities if one accepts their noncomposite subatomic particles. Consider three subatomic particles, a, b, and c, arranged in a triangular pattern. According to some, there exists in addition a fourth thing, T , which contains a, b, and c as parts. According to me, this fourth thing does not exist. Picture the disagreement thus: *Thanks to Frank Arntzenius, Elizabeth Barnes, Karen Bennett, Jiri Benovsky, Mike Bergmann, Ben Caplan, Ross Cameron, John Collins, Earl Conee, Shamik Dasgupta, Janelle Derstine, Sinan Dogramaci, Cian Dorr, TomDougherty, Matti Eklund, Hartry Field, Kit Fine, Anthony Fisher, Pete Graham, Yu Guo, John Hawthorne, Allan Hazlett, Sophie Horowitz, Michael Huemer, TomKelly, Josh Knobe, Rob Koons, Martin Lin, Ned Markosian, Kris Mc- Daniel, Trenton Merricks, Jill North, Lewis Powell, Jim Pryor, Josh Schechter, Nico Silins, Steve Steward, Margot Strohminger, Sarah Stroud, Meghan Sullivan, Jason Turner, Bruno Whittle, Dean Zimmerman, to anonymous referees, and especially to Liz Harman for much wisdom and patience.
    [Show full text]
  • Induction, Deduction, and the Scientific Method
    INDUCTION, DEDUCTION, AND THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD AN ECLECTIC OVERVIEW OF THE PRACTICE OF SCIENCE IRVING ROTHCHILD Emeritus Professor of Reproductive Biology Case Western Reserve University School of Medicine Cleveland, Ohio © 2006 by the Society for the Study of Reproduction, Inc. CONTENTS ABSTRACT 1 INTRODUCTION 1 INDUCTION AND DEDUCTION 2 Etymology 2 Definitions 2 Induction 2 Deduction 3 THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD 3 BEING A SCIENTIST 4 Making Observations 4 Point of View 5 Asking the Right Question 6 Theorizing 6 The theory (or finding) that questions authority 7 Defending the controversial theory or finding 8 Eurekas 8 Experimentation 9 The failed experiment 9 Publishing 10 Statistics 10 Recognition 10 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS 10 REFERENCES 11 © 2006 by the Society for the Study of Reproduction, Inc. © 2006 by the Society for the Study of Reproduction, Inc. INDUCTION, DEDUCTION, AND THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD AN ECLECTIC OVERVIEW OF THE PRACTICE OF SCIENCE IRVING ROTHCHILD* Emeritus Professor of Reproductive Biology Case Western Reserve University School of Medicine Cleveland, Ohio ABSTRACT: Science is a never-ending, always changing process through which we learn to know the material nature of the universe. Science does not deal with nonmaterial entities such as gods, for there is no way their existence can be either proved or disproved. No single, identifiable method applies to all branches of science; the only method, in fact, is whatever the scientist can use to find the solution to a problem. This includes induction, a form of logic that identifies similarities within a group of particulars, and deduction, a form of logic that identifies a particular by its resemblance to a set of accepted facts.
    [Show full text]
  • A Companion to the Philosophy of Language
    A COMPANION TO THE PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE SECOND EDITION Volume I Edited by Bob Hale, Crispin Wright, and Alexander Miller This second edition first published 2017 © 2017 John Wiley & Sons Ltd Edition history: Blackwell Publishing Ltd. (1e, 1997) Registered Office John Wiley & Sons Ltd, The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK Editorial Offices 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148‐5020, USA 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK The Atrium, Southern Gate, Chichester, West Sussex, PO19 8SQ, UK For details of our global editorial offices, for customer services, and for information about how to apply for permission to reuse the copyright material in this book please see our website at www.wiley.com/wiley‐blackwell. The right of Bob Hale, Crispin Wright, and Alexander Miller to be identified as the authors of the editorial material in this work has been asserted in accordance with the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, except as permitted by the UK Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988, without the prior permission of the publisher. Wiley also publishes its books in a variety of electronic formats. Some content that appears in print may not be available in electronic books. Designations used by companies to distinguish their products are often claimed as trademarks. All brand names and product names used in this book are trade names, service marks, trademarks, or registered trademarks of their respective owners.
    [Show full text]
  • Political Theory and the Problem of Explanation. James Wayne Lemke Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1978 Political Theory and the Problem of Explanation. James Wayne Lemke Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Lemke, James Wayne, "Political Theory and the Problem of Explanation." (1978). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 3249. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/3249 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 79031*4 LEMKE» JAMES WAYNE POLITICAL THEORY AND THE PROBLEM OF EXPLANATION. THE LOUISIANA STATE UNIVERSITY AND AGRICULTURAL AND MECHANICAL COL., P H .D ., 1978 University Microfilms International 3o o n , z e e s r o a d , a n n a r b o r , m i 4eioe 0 1978 JAMES WAYNE LEMKE ALL RIGHTS RESERVED Political Theory and the Problem of Explanation A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Political Science by James Wayne Lerrike B.A., Southeastern Louisiana University, 1969 August, 1978 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The writing of this dissertation, to say nothing of its completion, has been an enjoyable and rewarding enterprise. My good feelings about this experience are in large measure the result of the support and assistance of a number of people.
    [Show full text]
  • Science Without Inductivism ( Karl Popper’S View )
    Science without inductivism ( Karl Popper’s view ) Ningombam Bupenda Meitei (St.Stephen’s College), Department of Philosophy, University of Delhi Abstract The paper aims to expound on the issue of science being different from non science or pre- science in the form of the scientific methodology used. Popper’s method of falsifiability ensures the aim of science to be successful. The aim of science which also needs a critical attitude, can enable scientific progress by rejecting inductivism as its scientific methodology. Popper’s view on what the aim of science is and why and how inductivism fails in the case of science, along with examples from history of science besides its impact on philosophical foundations of science, has been stressed in the paper. Introduction Science and its significance grew rapidly due to Einstein’s theory of relativity and its difference from the nature of the works of Freud and Adler which made Popper to expound on the notion of allegedly scientific psychoanalysis of Freud and the revolutionary work on relativity of Einstein which was also experimentally proved by Eddington in 1919 showing the deflection of light by solid massive gravitational bodies. The debate of what science is and what non science could be, the notion of what science should do or can do or precisely ,the aim of science have made the 20th century a breeding moment of thoughts for philosophical foundations of science ,thereby influencing the development of philosophy of science. Popper who is also influenced by Hume’s skepticism on inductivism has made his notion of being scientific very strong in terms of being falsifiability through repeated tests.
    [Show full text]
  • Comments from Presentation
    Basic Justification and the Moorean Response to the Skeptic* Nico Silins [email protected] Introduction Suppose that, having concluded that there’s an external world, Moore forges on, and reasons along the following lines: BIV (HANDS): I have hands. (LINK): If I have hands, then it’s not the case that I’m a brain in a vat (BIV) who merely seems to have hands. So, (¬BIV): It’s not the case that I’m a BIV who merely seems to have hands. My focus will be on two questions about Moore’s justification to believe the premises and the conclusion of the argument above. At stake is what makes it possible for our experiences to justify our beliefs, and what makes it possible for us to be justified in disbelieving skeptical * For their helpful comments and questions, thanks to Richard Boyd, Stewart Cohen, Louis DeRosset, Ross Ford, John Hawthorne, Elizabeth Harman, David Jehle, Geoffrey Lee, Ram Neta, James Pryor, Stephen Schiffer, Declan Smithies, Scott Sturgeon, Adam Wager, Brian Weatherson, Ralph Wedgwood, Timothy Williamson, and Roger White. Special thanks to Matt Kotzen. I’m also grateful to audiences at the Universities of Calgary, Geneva, Kansas, Montana, Vermont, and North Carolina at Chapel Hill; Auburn, Columbia, Cornell, and Oxford Universities; and at MIT, SMU, and the ANU. 1 hypotheses about our experiences. The first question is (A) How is Moore justified in believing HANDS? Here my aim is to clarify and to defend the view that Moore’s experience gives him immediate or non-inferential justification to believe that he has hands (Pollock 1974; Pryor 2000, 2004, forthcominga; Peacocke 2004; Davies 2004).1 Doing so will be the task of sections 1 and 2.
    [Show full text]