Philosophy & Social Criticism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophy & Social Criticism Philosophy & Social Criticism http://psc.sagepub.com ‘The black, scabby Brazilian’: Some thoughts on race and early modern philosophy Michael A. Rosenthal Philosophy Social Criticism 2005; 31; 211 DOI: 10.1177/0191453705050608 The online version of this article can be found at: http://psc.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/31/2/211 Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com Additional services and information for Philosophy & Social Criticism can be found at: Email Alerts: http://psc.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://psc.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav Downloaded from http://psc.sagepub.com at CAPES on December 11, 2009 04 Rosenthal (bc/s) 4/3/05 3:18 pm Page 211 Michael A. Rosenthal ‘The black, scabby Brazilian’ Some thoughts on race and early modern philosophy Abstract When Spinoza described his dream of a ‘black, scabby Brazilian’, was the image indicative of a larger pattern of racial discrimination? Should today’s readers regard racist comments and theories in the texts of 17th- and 18th-century philosophers as reflecting the prejudices of their time or as symptomatic of philosophical discourse? This article discusses whether a critical discussion of race is itself a form of racism and whether supposedly minor prejudices are evidence of a deeper social pathology. Given historical hindsight, we may read such discussion of race in early modern philosophy as a sign of the incipient struggle against prejudice, a sign that we can recognize and use in the struggles of our own time. Key words colonialism · the concept of haunting · essentialism · David Hume · Immanuel Kant · racism · Benedict Spinoza Introduction In 1664 Benedict Spinoza received a letter from his friend Pieter Balling, in which the latter, who was grieving from the recent loss of his child, reported that he had experienced strange premonitions of the little boy’s death, such as hearing ‘groans such as he uttered when he was ill and just before he died’, when the boy was still healthy (p. 125).1 Spinoza replied that he doubted the groans were real and that it was possible to imagine the groans ‘more effectively and vividly’ than to hear them in fact. To illustrate the phenomenon, Spinoza recalls a dream he himself had the previous winter: When one morning just at dawn I awoke from a very deep dream, the images which had come to me in the dream were present before my eyes as vividly PHILOSOPHY & SOCIAL CRITICISM • vol 31 no 2 • pp. 211–221 PSC Copyright © 2005 SAGE Publications (London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi) www.sagepublications.com DOI: 10.1177/0191453705050608 Downloaded from http://psc.sagepub.com at CAPES on December 11, 2009 04 Rosenthal (bc/s) 4/3/05 3:18 pm Page 212 212 Philosophy & Social Criticism 31 (2) as if they had been real things, in particular the image of a black, scabby Brazilian [cujusdam nigri, & scabiosi Brasiliani] whom I had never seen before. This image disappeared for the most part when, to make a diver- sion, I fixed my gaze on a book or some other object; but as soon as I again turned my eyes away from such an object while gazing at nothing in particular, the same image of the same Ethiopian [Æthiopis]2 kept appear- ing with the same vividness again and again until it gradually disappeared from sight. (Letters, pp. 125–6) Spinoza goes on to explain the differences between these two incidents. While his friend’s image arose out of mental causes, specifically the intense emotional identification with his son, Spinoza’s dream image had corporeal causes, more specifically some sort of delirium. In the friend’s case, then, it could be an omen, while his case it could not. While I will return later to Spinoza’s explanation of the mechanism of his dream, and dispute his interpretation of it, right now I want to use it to highlight something of which apparently he was not aware: the obvious racial aspect of the dream. He makes a point of adding the adjective ‘black’ to his description of the man and, lest the reader think he was indicating nationality with the term ‘Brazilian’, the second refer- ence to ‘Ethiopian’ makes it clear that he is not. Moreover, the use of ‘scabby’ emphasizes the ugliness and sickness of the being that appears to frighten him. Just as his friend’s auditory hallucinations of his now dead child’s groans are obviously distressing so also is Spinoza’s visual image of this diseased, black man. Not much has been said of this image in the literature on Spinoza. And that is perhaps not surprising. There does not seem to be much of philosophical significance that rides on the content of the example itself.3 However, recently there has developed a literature that is critical of early modern philosophers and their ideas of race. These critics argue that such apparently ad hoc examples are really symptomatic of a larger pattern of racial discrimination. Some, such as Charles W. Mills in his recent book The Racial Contract, go farther and claim that these texts help produce the racial discrimination that they exemplify. So we arrive at the question of this article: How do (and how ought) modern readers make sense of racist comments and theories in the texts of 17th- and 18th-century philosophers? Some view them as reflecting prejudices of the age, which are not central to the philosophical projects of the thinkers in question. Others argue that they are symptomatic of a funda- mental malady of philosophical discourse. I shall focus on the latter claim and consider two related varieties of it, one that argues that the absence of a critical discussion of race is itself a form of racism, and the other that argues that supposedly minor prejudices are in fact evidence of a racist theory. I shall evaluate these criticisms in light of their historical and philosophical claims and suggest that another approach to the texts is possible. Downloaded from http://psc.sagepub.com at CAPES on December 11, 2009 04 Rosenthal (bc/s) 4/3/05 3:18 pm Page 213 213 Rosenthal: ‘The black, scabby Brazilian’ Part 1 Until now the dominant way of dealing with what we would now term as racist views has been essentially to excuse them. They are minor and do not impact on the philosophically significant works; they reflect assumptions of the time to which everyone was subject. Moreover, the work of the same philosophers has resources that would address these very defects. This certainly could be (and has been) said about Spinoza, but let me give two further examples to illustrate this point. First, the philosopher David Hume added a note to his essay ‘Of National Character’, which appeared in the second edition of his Essays: Moral, Political and Literary (1754), which begins as follows: ‘I am apt to suspect the Negroes to be naturally inferior to the whites. There scarcely ever was a civilized nation of that complexion, nor even any individual eminent either in action or speculation’ (p. 208).4 Those willing to excuse Hume’s racism might point to the following consider- ations. This essay, although Hume worked on it and revised it more than once, seems to be the only place in Hume’s considerable work in which he makes such a statement. And in the essay itself the racism that Hume espouses is not based on a modern theory of inherent biological inferiority but rather exclusively on environmental factors, which he uses to denigrate the morals of many other (mostly southern) nations as well. Perhaps surprisingly, the inferiority of the Negroes does not justify systematic discrimination against them, for elsewhere in the same volume Hume condemns slavery in no uncertain terms.5 Moreover, Hume’s moral philosophy, which is based on a sympathy for others, recognizes that we tend to favor those who are closest to us, and that we must constantly revise our conceptions and expand our circle of concern to those whom we previously did not know or care about. So, while Hume, like many of this time, makes racist comments, the modern reader must balance them against his progressive philosophical and moral system. The work of Immanuel Kant is even more clearly riven by this con- tradiction. On the one hand, Kant’s moral philosophy is characterized by the defense of individual autonomy based on the principle of the categorical imperative, in which an action is judged to be right only if its motive can become a universal law of nature.6 For example, it is wrong to break a promise because, if the motive of doing so (e.g. to benefit oneself or someone else) were to become a law of nature, then the very institution of promising would become meaningless. Kant’s second formulation of the categorical imperative is even clearer: act so that you treat yourself or others always as an end never merely as a means (p. 38). Slavery, for instance, is immoral according to this formu- lation because the masters are not respecting the autonomous goals of the individual slaves but are treating these people merely as means to Downloaded from http://psc.sagepub.com at CAPES on December 11, 2009 04 Rosenthal (bc/s) 4/3/05 3:18 pm Page 214 214 Philosophy & Social Criticism 31 (2) their own ends. It hardly seems possible that Kant could be accused of racism. However, Kant, far more than Hume, develops and defends racist ideas in his writings, particularly in those devoted to anthropology and physical geography.
Recommended publications
  • Visibility of Invisible Africans
    Vol. 18. 2006 ISSN 0794-8670 BULLETINI OF ECUMENICAL ·THEOLOGY· MIGRATION AND RELEVANCE OF CHRISTIAN MISSION Visibility of Invisible Africans PUBLISHED BY The Ecumenical Association of Nigerian Theologians BULLETIN OF ECUMENICAL THEOLOGY ISSN 0794-8670 Vol.18 2006 MIGRATION AND RELEVANCE OF CHRISTIAN MISSION VISIBILITY OF INVISIBLE AFRICANS PUBLISHED BY The Ecumenical Association of Nigerian Theologians Editor Elochukwu E. Uzukwu, C.S.Sp. - Milltown Institute of Theology and Philosophy, Dublin 6, Ireland Deputy Editor Nicholas Ibeawuchi Omenka - Abia State University, Uturu Editorial Board J.P.c. Nzomiwu, - Nnamdi Azikiwe University, Awka Chris I. Ejizu - University of Port Harcourt Chris U. Manus, - Obafemi Awolowo University, Ife Ibrahim Musa Ahmadu, - University of Jos Obiora Ike - Catholic Institute for Development, Justice and Peace, Enugu Emmanuel N. Onwu - University of Nigeria, Nsukka SUBSCRIPTION RATES Nigeria - 400.00 per issue Foreign - US$ 20 ( €20) per annum US$ 20 (€20) per combined issue (air mail postage included) Payments overseas: Congregazione dello Spirito Santo Casa Generalizia Clivo di Cinna, 195 00136, Roma, Italia Bulletin of Ecumenical Theology is published by the Ecumenical Association of Nigerian Theologians (EANT), and printed in Nigeria by SNAAP Press Ltd, Enugu. EANT acknowledges its indebtedness to SIST for affording it facilities to continue publishing the Bulletin. All Correspondence should be addressed to the Editor, B.E.Th. Spiritan International School of Theology (SIST), P.O. Box 9696, Enugu, Nigeria, Tel. (042) 250865; 450445; Fax: 253781; E-mail: [email protected] BULLETIN OF ECUMENICAL THEOLOGY Volume 18 (2006) CONTENTS Editorial 1 Bernard Ukwuegbu . The Judeo-Christian Redemptive History: an Alternative Framework for the Migration Debate 6 Patrick Roe C.S.Sp.
    [Show full text]
  • Reading Reason with Emmanuel Eze Formations
    Africana philosophy through his founding and editorship of the journal Philosophia Africana. The journal under Eze’s Symposia on Gender, Race and editorial leadership was committed to promoting “scholarly Philosophy exchanges across [the] historical and cultural boundaries” represented by African, African-American, and Afro- Volume 4, Special Issue on Emmanuel Eze, Spring 2008 Caribbean philosophical traditions. He also edited two http://web.mit.edu/sgrp important anthologies, Postcolonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader (1997) and African Philosophy: An Anthology (1998), in which he took pains to draw contributions from writers working in all of these three subdisciplinary Reading Reason with Emmanuel Eze formations. Eze is perhaps best known for his critical reading of Kant’s JOHN PITTMAN anthropological writings and the philosophical ‘raciology’ Department of Art, Music, and Philosophy they contain, in his important article, “The Color of Reason: John Jay College of Criminal Justice The City University of New York The Idea of ‘Race’ in Kant’s Anthropology.” He extended that 899 Tenth Ave. critique to include Hume as well in his edited volume on Race New York, NY 10019 and the Enlightenment. Indeed, Emmanuel Eze was the USA contemporary writer who most consistently explored the [email protected] issue of the racial logic of the founding thinkers of the European enlightenment. In Achieving our Humanity: The Idea of a Postracial Future (2001), Eze extended that inquiry, Emmanuel Eze’s last and, terribly, posthumous book is On discussing at length the history of race conceptions in Reason: Rationality in a World of Cultural Conflict and Racism European thought, arguing that the modern origins of (2008).
    [Show full text]
  • Race in Early Modern Philosophy
    Introduction I.1. Nature In 1782, in the journal of an obscure Dutch scientific society, we find a relation of the voyage of a European seafarer to the Gold Coast of Africa some decades earlier. In the town of Axim in present- day Ghana, we learn, at some point in the late 1750s, David Henri Gallandat met a man he describes as a “hermit” and a “soothsayer.” “His father and a sister were still alive,” Gallandat relates, “and lived a four- days’ journey inland. He had a brother who was a slave in the colony of Suriname.”1 So far, there is nothing exceptional in this relation: countless families were broken up by the slave trade in just this way. But we also learn that the hermit’s soothsaying practice was deeply informed by “philosophy.” Gal- landat is not using this term in a loose sense, either. The man he meets, we are told, “spoke various languages— Hebrew, Greek, Latin, French, High and Low German; he was very knowledgeable in astrology and as- tronomy, and a great philosopher.”2 In fact, this man, we learn, “had been sent to study at Halle and in Wittenberg, where in 1727 he was promoted to Doctor of Philosophy and Master of Liberal Arts.”3 On a certain understanding, there have been countless philosophers in Africa, whose status as such required no recognition by European institu- tions, no conferral of rank.4 On a narrower understanding, however, Anton Wilhelm Amo may rightly be held up as the first African philosopher in modern history. Gallandat tells us that after the death of Amo’s “master,” Duke August Wilhelm of Braunschweig- Wolfenbüttel, the philosopher- slave grew “melancholy,” and “decided to return to his home country.” 1 Verhandelingen uitgegeven door het Zeeuwsch Genootschap der Wetenschappen te Vlissingen, Negende Deel, Middelburg: Pieter Gillissen, 1782, 19– 20.
    [Show full text]
  • Political and Cultural Identity in the Global Postcolony: Postcolonial Thinkers on the Racist Enlightenment and the Struggle for Humanity
    www.acpo.cz recenzovaný časopis | peer-reviewed journal 2017 | vol. 9 | no. 1 | issn 1803–8220 ROOTHAAN, Angela (2017). Political and Cultural Identity in the Global Postcolony: Postcolonial Thinkers on the Racist Enlightenment and the Struggle for Humanity. Acta Politologica. Vol. 9, no. 1, pp. 31-44. Tento článek podléhá autorským právům, kopírování a využívání jeho obsahu bez řádného odkazování na něj je považováno za plagiátorství a podléhá sankcím dle platné legislativy. This article is protected by copyright. Copying and use of its content and presenting it as original research without proper citation is plagiarism, which is subject to legal sanctions. Katedra politologie Institutu politologických studií DepartmentFakulta of Political sociálních Science, věd u Instituteniverzity of Karlovy Political Studies Faculty of social sciences, charles university Political and Cultural Identity in the Global Postcolony: Postcolonial Thinkers on the Racist Enlightenment and the Struggle for Humanity Angela Roothaan1 Abstract: This paper investigates how, in the condition of postcolonialism, claims of political and cultural identity depend on the understanding of humanity, and how this understanding ultimately relates to historical agency. I understand postcolonialism as the condition that aims at the decolonization of thought of formerly colonized and former colonizers together – a condition that is global. I will construe my argument by discussing the following au- thors: Frantz Fanon, Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze, Amilcar Cabral, Achille Mbembe and Michael Onyebuchi Eze. Fanon for his criticism of modern Western philosophy as dehumanizing the other; Emmanuel Eze for his in-depth critique of Kant and Hegel’s ideas of humanity and the racialised and racist frames of thought they left behind and both Fanon and Eze for their proposals to understand humanity as a project under construction; Amilcar Cabral for his views on the interrelatedness of political and cultural identity in a situation of the building of new nations.
    [Show full text]
  • (Universals) in Aristotle
    Rethinking Universalism and Particularism in African Philosophy: Towards an Eclectic Approach by Mutshidzi Maraganedzha Supervisor: Prof Bernard Matolino This dissertation is submitted in fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy, in the School of Religion, Philosophy and Classics. College of Humanities, University of Kwa-Zulu Natal, Pietermaritzburg November 2019 Declaration The author declares that the content of this thesis is his work unless the contrary has been specifically indicated. This thesis has not been submitted in any form for any specific degree to any other university across the world. Citations, references and to a greater extend borrowed ideas are properly acknowledged within the text. Signed: __________________ _______________ Mutshidzi Maraganedzha Date Student No. 207505743 I declare that this work has been submitted with the approval of the University supervisor. Signed: __________________ _______________ Prof. Bernard Matolino Date School of Religion, Philosophy and Classics University of KwaZulu-Natal i Dedication I dedicate this thesis to my late father, Khamusi Samson Maraganedzha who passed-away at the beginning of my doctoral studies. ii Abstract The study focuses on the dispute between the universalists and particularists in the characterization of the nature of African philosophy. In African philosophy the debate is formulated as a dichotomy between the universalists and the particularists. At the center of this debate is the notion of ‘universal’ and its relationship to the particular. The universalists argue that the nature of (African) philosophy–its methodology and subject matter–has to be universal and should be the same when applied to Western and African thought systems.
    [Show full text]
  • An Appraisal of the Challenges Confronting the Nature of African Philosophy
    AN APPRAISAL OF THE CHALLENGES CONFRONTING THE NATURE OF AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY Williams O. ASO Introduction The place of adequate definition on any subject of discussion cannot be overemphasized. A proper definition of an idea is a true path way to better understanding and appreciation of its components, from the main topic to the minutest parts. Hence, a good definition of an academic subject tele-guides those who have interest in the subject to know what the subject holds, its concerns and what distinguishes it from other related subjects. A definition that involves all these concerns will help participants in the discussion at stake to avoid misconceptions and misgivings in one sense and overcome ambiguities and equivocations in another sense. As a matter of fact, a justified definition is necessary for African philosophy to determine its scope, to illustrate its characteristics, to identify its concerns and inherent problems. This attempt will make anybody in an academic environment to have a clearer picture of what is African philosophy. There is no doubt that countless definitions of 138 139 African philosophy may come up as a result of diverse impulses from the background, the school, the culture and appreciated methodology of each philosopher. However, a notable parameter is necessary to judge if a particular definition of African philosophy is credible and acceptable. What count most in the definition of African philosophy is not as important as the relationship that such definition must have with African worldview. Therefore, any definition of African philosophy that reflects on African perspective either by an African or non-African is relevant for the understanding of African philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • FEATURE Reviews an Apology for Postcolonial Reason
    FEATURE REVIEWS An Apology for Postcolonial Reason Paul Lyons Department of English, University of Hawai‘i On Reason: Rationality in a World of Cultural Conflict and Racism. By Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze. Durham and London: Duke University Press, 2008. Pp. xx + 327. Following his death in 2007, responses to Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze’s posthumously published On Reason: Rationality in a World of Cultural Conflict and Racism had a memorializing tone, and took place around spaces devoted to Africana Philosophy.1 This was appropriate, given Eze’s contributions through the establishment of the jour- nal Philosophia Africana; through editing the field-mapping Post-Colonial African Philosophy: A Critical Reader and On African Philosophy: An Anthology (collections whose Prefaces define Africana philosophy inclusively and extensively as including the diaspora and its engagements over time, in part because diasporic thought has returned to inform intellectual movements); and through a series of works that argued for the ongoing need to mark and counter the racism that Eze identifies as “coloring thought” within Enlightenment philosophy and its legacies. It would be unfortunate, however, if On Reason were not engaged more widely within philosophical circles, for while the book claims to have “quite modest” intentions (p. xi), its implications for philosophy in the “Postcolonial Age” are potentially far-reaching. Eze makes a compelling if largely implicit case that the figure of “Africa” in his- tory as a multi-sourced crossroads of thought, and as a generative site of postcolonial philosophy, necessitates a rethinking of the often East-West coordinates of philoso- phy as a discipline. In the process, On Reason offers subtle reflections on Africana philosophy; on the question of how and where Africana philosophy’s difference among the family of philosophical traditions might be located (in what “nonacciden- tal” forms of kindred thought [p.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Newsletter on Indigenous Philosophy, Vol. 16, No. 2 (Spring 2017)
    NEWSLETTER | The American Philosophical Association Indigenous Philosophy SPRING 2017 VOLUME 16 | NUMBER 2 FROM THE EDITOR Agnes B. Curry SUBMISSION GUIDELINES ARTICLES Chike Jeffers On Listening to Ourselves Joseph Osei The Philosophical Significance of Listening to Ourselves Gail Presbey The Best of Both Worlds: Philosophy in African Languages and English Translation BOOK REVIEW Therapeutic Nations: Healing in an Age of Indigenous Human Rights Reviewed by Shelbi Nahwilet Meissner VOLUME 16 | NUMBER 2 SPRING 2017 © 2017 BY THE AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL ASSOCIATION ISSN 2155-9708 APA NEWSLETTER ON Indigenous Philosophy AGNES B. CURRY, EDITOR VOLUME 16 | NUMBER 2 | SPRING 2017 Bridging the gaps—conceptual and existential—between FROM THE EDITOR the language of one’s academic training and professional identity, and one’s “home” language, seems formidable. Starting Differently I don’t know this personally; rather, I speak as a Xicana who never adequately learned her mother’s tongue of Agnes Curry Spanish—but who was once told by one of my philosophy UNIVERSITY OF SAINT JOSEPH, CONNECTICUT professors that nothing of philosophical merit had been written in Spanish. I was told that the language itself, This edition of the APA Newsletter on Indigenous Philosophy while emotionally expressive, was not conducive to the features some of the papers presented at the special panel, articulation of rational thought. And that’s the European sponsored by the Committee on Indigenous Philosophers, language! Let’s not even broach considering the on Listening to Ourselves: A Multilingual Anthology of forgotten great-great-great grandmother’s tongue, buried African Philosophy, edited by Chike Jeffers, held January under a family history of baptism, shame, and a certain 6, 2017, at the APA Eastern Division meeting in Baltimore.
    [Show full text]
  • White Supremacy in Eurocentric Epistemologies: on the West’S Responsibility for Its Philosophical Heritage
    Preliminary communication UDC 165:141.74(045) doi: 10.21464/sp33115 Received: May 11, 2018 Björn Freter [email protected] White Supremacy in Eurocentric Epistemologies: On the West’s Responsibility for its Philosophical Heritage Abstract There is a largely overlooked fundamental flaw in the Eurocentric epistemological founda­ tion. Counter to the overwhelming ethos of the Enlightenment, this epistemological bedrock shockingly does not seem to be an epistemology of the human being, but only of the white human being. I, as a Western scholar, have to relativise my epistemological heritage, be­ cause it does not take into account the diversity of the human being. I will briefly explore the racist views of Voltaire, Hume, and Kant and I will argue that Western philosophy needs to (re)analyse its epistemological tradition with regards to the way the racist views of its pro­ tagonists corrupted their philosophical work. I suggest contextualization of the philosophi­ cal tradition and its desuperiorisation to foster ethical and broader philosophical dialogue amongst global scholars. Keywords white supremacy, racism, the Enlightenment, desuperiorisation, Voltaire, David Hume, Im- manuel Kant Introduction It is my critical evaluation that there is a largely overlooked fundamental flaw in the Western epistemological foundation, which no doubt has origins that can be traced back further, but is (re)introduced by the philosophers of the Enlightenment. Counter to the overwhelming ethos of the Enlightenment, this epistemological bedrock shockingly does not seem to be an epistemology of the human being, but only of the white human being. Indeed, I, as a Western scholar, have to relativise my epistemological heritage, because it does not take into account the diversity of the human being.
    [Show full text]
  • An African Existentialist Perspective on the Permissibility of Same Sex Marriage
    Nnamdi Azikiwe Journal of Philosophy. Volume 9, No 1 My Life, Our Right: An African Existentialist Perspective on the Permissibility of Same Sex Marriage 1Asia, Emmanuel & 2Odigie, Joseph Ndidi 1,2Department of Philosophy and Religions, Faculty of Arts, University of Benin, Benin City. Abstract Marriage is arguably a given in most societies but in recent years there has been a debate on the permissibility of same sex marriage. That is, whether it is possible for people of the same sex to be pronounced husband and wife. There have been several contradictory arguments for and against the permissibility of same sex marriage. Some of these arguments against same sex marriage include among others that it is anti-religious, that it destroys procreation which is a major reason why people get married in the first place, it leads to polygamy, it is incestuous, and bestial while on the other hand those in favour of same sex marriage argues along existentialist line that it is their life and their right to choose their sexual partner. However, this paper explores the African understanding of marriage and argues that the African understanding of marriage as exemplified among the Edo people should be used as an alternative solution to the controversial arguments on same sex marriage in western social philosophy. Thus, this paper argues that the question of marriage is a cultural phenomenon and given that the western culture had missed the true essence of marriage, that the Edo understanding of marriage should be use to correct the perverted notion of marriage in Western discourse. Keywords: Marriage, African, Same sex, Existentialism Last night I invented a new pleasure, and as I was giving it my first trial, an angel and a devil came rushing toward my house.
    [Show full text]
  • History of Race Theory Professor Peter K
    Course HUHI 6305.001: Ideas in Context: History of Race Theory Professor Peter K. J. Park Term Fall 2015 Class Meetings Wednesdays 4:00-6:45 p.m. Location: JO 4.708 Professor’s Contact Information Office Phone (972) 883-2152 Office Location JO 5.610 Office Hours Thursday afternoons. Please email me to let me know that you’re coming. Email Address [email protected] General Course Information Pre-requisites, Co- requisites, & other Open to M.A. and Ph.D. students restrictions This seminar is intended as a graduate-level historical and theoretical survey of both the history of race and racism and the scholarly field of critical race theory. This broad historical and theoretical survey is geographically centered on the West. It emphasizes the reading and criticism of classic works of critical race Course Description scholarship as well as important historical sources on race and racism in Western history. Among the ideas and practices falling under our purview are ancient and modern ethnography and ethnology, slavery, colonialism, natural history (or natural description or natural classification), natural rights, sociology of race, racialism, racial eliminativism, racial contract, and human development. Students will be able to (1) describe the major ideas and practices of race and racism in Western history, (2) describe major trends in the historiography of Learning Outcomes race and racism, (3) explain what critical race theory is, and (4) produce a work of historiography or a critical literature review. Bernasconi, Robert, and Tommy L. Lott, The Idea of Race. Indianapolis: Hackett, 2000. Cox, Oliver C. Caste, Class, and Race: A Study in Social Dynamics.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defence of Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze's
    SCHOOL OF RELIGION, PHILOSOPHY AND CLASSICS A Defence of Emmanuel Chukwudi Eze’s Conception of Reason. Mohammed Xolile Ntshangase This dissertation is submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy in the School of Religion, Philosophy and Classics. College of Humanities, University of KwaZulu- Natal, Pietermaritzburg November 2015 iii Declaration of originality The research reported in this thesis, except where otherwise indicated, is my original research, carried in the School of Religion, Philosophy and Classics, University of KwaZulu-Natal, Pietermaritzburg from February to November 2015. I hereby declare that the content of this thesis is my work, unless specifically indicated to the contrary. This thesis has not been submitted in any form for any degree or diploma to any other University. All citations, references and borrowed ideas have been duly acknowledged. Sign……………… Date……………… iv Acknowledgements I owe my deepest gratitude to my Supervisor Dr. Bernard Matolino for his professional guidance. Special thanks to Shulika L Stella and Marion Jordan for editing my thesis. I am also grateful to Mr Mutshidzi Maraganedzha who helped me to shape my thoughts towards the completion of this thesis. My sincere gratitude also goes to my Muslim brotherhood from Scottville society. v Table of Content: Declaration of originality ................................................................................................... iv Acknowledgements ............................................................................................................
    [Show full text]