Returning the Radiant Gaze: Visual Art and Embodiment in a World of Subjects Beth Carruthers Emily Carr University of Art + Design

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Returning the Radiant Gaze: Visual Art and Embodiment in a World of Subjects Beth Carruthers Emily Carr University of Art + Design The Goose Volume 17 | No. 1 Article 32 9-14-2018 Returning the Radiant Gaze: Visual art and embodiment in a world of subjects Beth Carruthers Emily Carr University of Art + Design Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, Environmental Studies Commons, Fine Arts Commons, Metaphysics Commons, Other Philosophy Commons, Social and Cultural Anthropology Commons, and the Theory and Criticism Commons Follow this and additional works at / Suivez-nous ainsi que d’autres travaux et œuvres: https://scholars.wlu.ca/thegoose Recommended Citation / Citation recommandée Carruthers, Beth. "Returning the Radiant Gaze: Visual art and embodiment in a world of subjects." The Goose, vol. 17 , no. 1 , article 32, 2018, https://scholars.wlu.ca/thegoose/vol17/iss1/32. This article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholars Commons @ Laurier. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Goose by an authorized editor of Scholars Commons @ Laurier. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Cet article vous est accessible gratuitement et en libre accès grâce à Scholars Commons @ Laurier. Le texte a été approuvé pour faire partie intégrante de la revue The Goose par un rédacteur autorisé de Scholars Commons @ Laurier. Pour de plus amples informations, contactez [email protected]. Carruthers: Returning the Radiant Gaze BETH CARRUTHERS Returning the Radiant Gaze: Visual art and embodiment in a world of subjects Published by / Publié par Scholars Commons @ Laurier, 2018 1 The Goose, Vol. 17, No. 1 [2018], Art. 32 There is a place on earth where stillness and motion meet where a pool of water or the petal from a single stem catches the eye expressing through its rarified being-in-time perfection and the seeing of this apprehension seeks not to impede nor master this moment allowing it instead to be where it ought most to be – this reverential care this fragile power shared this delicate body-in–the-mind this two way mirror where the seen looks back mysteriously acknowledging in mutual respect this radiance of the gaze Nelson Gray, Gifted (for Beth Carruthers) (unpublished, 1999) https://scholars.wlu.ca/thegoose/vol17/iss1/32 2 Carruthers: Returning the Radiant Gaze It is only through the senses that we experience what it means to be fully human. It is only through the engaged senses that we are able to feel desire and intimacy, the great longing to be fully, wholly, and utterly in the world. But it is only through the honest and engaged senses that we will come to appreciate the living world as it truly is, both wildly beautiful and endangered. Cultivating our perceptual capacity is fundamentally related to both the quality of our personal lives and restoring the quality of life on the planet. Laura Sewall, Sight and Sensibility (14) But what is Nature? From the Latin Natura, it is my birth, my characteristics, my condition. It is my nativity, my astrology, my biology, my physiognomy, my geography, my cartography, my spirituality, my sexuality, my mentality, my corporeal, intellectual, emotional, imaginative self. And it is not just myself, every self and the Self of the world. There is no mirror I know that can show me all of these singularities, unless it is the strange, distorting looking glass of art, where I will not find my reflection nor my representation but a nearer proof than I prefer. Natura is the whole that I am. The multiple reality of my existence. Jeanette Winterson, Art Objects (149-150) Why is it important to re-embody vision—and what does art have to do with it? An introduction to the enquiry. Vision is, many say, our most dominant sense. Our eyes move constantly, adapting, monitoring, locating us in relationship with the world. Through them we experience sunsets and gardens, disasters and conflicts, a single red poppy in the sun, the terrifying sight of a runaway truck on a crowded road. Yet, in Western cultural tradition, vision is also suspect and denigrated. From Plato, through the Middle Ages, to the twentieth-century backlash against a so-called ocularcentric Western culture, debates on vision have figured large in our cultural landscape. Vision, as they say in marketing, has an image problem. In the mid to late twentieth century, ocularcentrism and vision itself came to be heavily criticised within cultural practices, particularly the visual arts. As David Abram writes in his forward to Laura Sewall’s Sight and Sensibility, “the objectifying gaze has become a cliché of contemporary criticism” (xiv). Visual art was easily targeted as problematic, and within art institutions, artists responded by scrambling to achieve the desired distance from visual pleasure, or to critique the gaze within their work. Artworks metamorphosed into configurations of signs and text. As a visual artist, I found myself split. Taking up the stance expected of a successful artist at that time involved a disconnection from the lived experience of art-making—an experience joyful, engaged, intimately and ultimately sensual. How to reconcile the Published by / Publié par Scholars Commons @ Laurier, 2018 3 The Goose, Vol. 17, No. 1 [2018], Art. 32 intimate touching of visual contact with a discourse which, intent on its desire to critique objectification, in fact promoted further removal from world, self, and other? While it could be argued that much has changed since the late twentieth century—for example, the re-embracing of the sensuous by way of “affect” and “new materialism”— vision and the visual remain troubled, reflecting the much discussed human disconnect from the body, as well as from places and other beings within the dominant, persistent, and reductive ontological frame of Modernity. Does such a disconnection in fact exist, or is it merely a stance taken—an ideal of disconnection constructed to support cultural beliefs and habits? I suggest the latter is the case and that this stance is continually reinforced by a number of behaviours within the culture. It occurred to me that the internal splitting I was experiencing as an artist was mirrored in myriad cultural ways, and that the splitting of vision has a long history—one that has everything to do with our way of Being-in-the-world. This essay is a response to the anti-ocular from inside the practice of visual art, through the lens of philosophy. It also constitutes an enquiry into a theory of visual embodiment and what I will call visual Being in the world. I believe that art has a vitally important role in cultures. By drawing us into a relational and sensual world, art denies dualisms while affirming difference. To quote writer and critic Jeanette Winterson, “art, by its nature, objects” (139). My intention here is to unravel some prevailing cultural beliefs about art and the visual by way of a personal journey through visual art and arts practice. I also intend to show how art is embodied in the world, engaged with myriad others. To do this I consider the relationship between the lived and the visual through the practice and experience of art-making. I then follow with an enquiry into the nature of the artwork in the world and the relationship between the work and the viewer. There is no intention on my part to engage with an in-depth analysis of anti-visual discourse, but as much as possible to locate my enquiry within an exploration of lived experience. As an enquiry, this essay promises no final truths, but a process, a journey through the contested territory of the sensual world of art and vision. This essay is primarily indebted to Maurice Merleau-Ponty’s reflections on art and the visual in Eye and Mind, as well as to Martin Jay’s thorough study and critique of anti- ocular discourse in the twentieth century, Downcast Eyes. Other valuable resources include the writings and ideas of philosopher Glen Mazis and philosopher/cultural ecologist David Abram, the work of psychologists James Gibson and Laura Sewall on vision, and writer Jeanette Winterson’s essays on art. While I cannot speak for all visual artists when I make the observations and assertions that I do within this essay, I am aware that observations that I make on the art-making process reflect the lived experiences of others, as well as my own. https://scholars.wlu.ca/thegoose/vol17/iss1/32 4 Carruthers: Returning the Radiant Gaze Visual Being in a world of subjects What do I mean by visual Being? What do I mean by subject? For the purposes of this essay a subject is a being with agency. This subject may be considered animate, inanimate, seen, or unseen. A subject may be an object, an other, a differently bodied force. Visual Being is the embodied visual. Vision is of the eyes, of the body, of the mind, of our entire selves. We are present in our vision, embodied within vision as vision is in us, so that when we extend ourselves into the world visually, we really are extending our selves, embodied. As we encounter others, and others encounter us, we may engage, and converse, through vision. We do not have to be within physical proximity to touch, to converse. Through vision we may be, as Merleau-Ponty points out, “everywhere at once” (187). Vision itself has a mixed reputation in Western culture. We love it, vilify it, attempt to master it, pin it down for deconstruction, and use it as a tool for the deconstruction. Vision is culturally problematic because it ties us to the body as sensual beings. On the other hand, vision is also a problem by virtue of our insisting on its being disembodied and located in the mind.
Recommended publications
  • Depopulation: on the Logic of Heidegger's Volk
    Research research in phenomenology 47 (2017) 297–330 in Phenomenology brill.com/rp Depopulation: On the Logic of Heidegger’s Volk Nicolai Krejberg Knudsen Aarhus University [email protected] Abstract This article provides a detailed analysis of the function of the notion of Volk in Martin Heidegger’s philosophy. At first glance, this term is an appeal to the revolutionary mass- es of the National Socialist revolution in a way that demarcates a distinction between the rootedness of the German People (capital “P”) and the rootlessness of the modern rabble (or people). But this distinction is not a sufficient explanation of Heidegger’s position, because Heidegger simultaneously seems to hold that even the Germans are characterized by a lack of identity. What is required is a further appropriation of the proper. My suggestion is that this logic of the Volk is not only useful for understanding Heidegger’s thought during the war, but also an indication of what happened after he lost faith in the National Socialist movement and thus had to make the lack of the People the basis of his thought. Keywords Heidegger – Nazism – Schwarze Hefte – Black Notebooks – Volk – people Introduction In § 74 of Sein und Zeit, Heidegger introduces the notorious term “the People” [das Volk]. For Heidegger, this term functions as the intersection between phi- losophy and politics and, consequently, it preoccupies him throughout the turbulent years from the National Socialist revolution in 1933 to the end of WWII in 1945. The shift from individual Dasein to the Dasein of the German People has often been noted as the very point at which Heidegger’s fundamen- tal ontology intersects with his disastrous political views.
    [Show full text]
  • The Male Gaze Interpretive Guide
    Interpretive Guide & Hands-on Activities The Alberta Foundation for the Arts Travelling Exhibition Program The Male Gaze The Alberta Foundation for the Arts Travelling Exhibition Program The Interpretive Guide The Art Gallery of Alberta is pleased to present your community with a selection from its Travelling Exhibition Program. This is one of several exhibitions distributed by The Art Gallery of Alberta as part of the Alberta Foundation for the Arts Travelling Exhibition Program. This Interpretive Guide has been specifically designed to complement the exhibition you are now hosting. The suggested topics for discussion and accompanying activities can act as a guide to increase your viewers’ enjoyment and to assist you in developing programs to complement the exhibition. Questions and activities have been included at both elementary and advanced levels for younger and older visitors. At the Elementary School Level the Alberta Art Curriculum includes four components to provide students with a variety of experiences. These are: Reflection: Responses to visual forms in nature, designed objects and artworks Depiction: Development of imagery based on notions of realism Composition: Organization of images and their qualities in the creation of visual art Expression: Use of art materials as a vehicle for expressing statements The Secondary Level focuses on three major components of visual learning. These are: Drawings: Examining the ways we record visual information and discoveries Encounters: Meeting and responding to visual imagery Composition: Analyzing the ways images are put together to create meaning The activities in the Interpretive Guide address one or more of the above components and are generally suited for adaptation to a range of grade levels.
    [Show full text]
  • Can We All Really Have It? Loving Gaze As an Anti-Oppressive Beauty
    The Perfect Bikini Body: Can We All Really Have It? Loving Gaze as an Anti-Oppressive Beauty Ideal Forthcoming in Thought: A Journal of Philosophy (please cite the final version) Abstract In this paper I ask whether there is a defensible philosophical view according to which every body is beautiful. I review two purely aesthetical versions of this claim. The No Standards View claims that every body is maximally and equally beautiful. The Multiple Standards View encourages us to widen our standards of beauty. I argue that both approaches are problematic. The former fails to be aspirational and empowering, while the latter fails to be sufficiently inclusive. I conclude by presenting a hybrid ethical-aesthetical view according to which everybody is beautiful in the sense that every body can be perceived through a loving gaze (with the exception of evil individuals who are wholly unworthy of love). I show that this view is inclusive, aspirational and empowering, and authentically aesthetical. As soon as the summer season approaches, the internet is inundated with articles and slideshows with such titles as: “37 Totally Perfect Bikini Bodies. Rule No.1: there are no rules”1 or “9 Stunning Bodies That Shatter Society’s Stereotypes About the ‘Perfect’ Body”.2 These popular articles are ultimately grounded in the feminist imperative of dismantling sexist and oppressive aesthetic norms that harm women3 in a myriad of ways, among which: damaging their self-esteem and affecting their psychological and physical health, exposing 1 https://www.buzzfeed.com/kirstenking/all-your-perfect- imperfections?utm_term=.aoxkvwvz2#.qwJzDJD9G Last accessed on 02/16/2017.
    [Show full text]
  • Children of Genius: Affirmation of Will in Schopenhauer's Aesthetics
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 5-9-2019 Children Of Genius: Affirmation Of Will In Schopenhauer's Aesthetics Clare Mauney Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Recommended Citation Mauney, Clare, "Children Of Genius: Affirmation Of Will In Schopenhauer's Aesthetics." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2019. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/249 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. CHILDREN OF GENIUS: AFFIRMATION OF WILL IN SCHOPENHAUER’S AESTHETICS by CLARE MAUNEY Under the Direction of Jessica Berry, PhD ABSTRACT While Schopenhauer is well-known for his pessimistic outlook on life, I argue that not all aspects of his philosophical project support this outlook. Specifically, I argue that Schopenhauer’s aesthetic genius must necessarily affirm life through artistic creation. To show that this is the case, I contend that the aesthetic genius’ engagement with the world of representation precludes him from engaging in the denial of the will-to-live, and that his desire to communicate his knowledge of the world entails an affirmation of the will-to-live. I furthermore outline and explore significant parallels between artistic creation
    [Show full text]
  • SPECULUM MENTIS Or the Map of Knowledge
    Questions de recherche, 5 octobre 2017: « Aber ist das eine Antwort? » (Heine) : On Questioning in, by, and about Literature Christine Weder, Département de langue et de littérature allemandes Heinrich Heine: Gedichte 1853 und 1854: Traduction (Saint-René Taillandier):H. Heine: Le Livre de Lazare (1854): Heinrich Heine: Historisch-kritische Gesamtausgabe der Werke, hg. v. Manfred Windfuhr, Band 3/1, S. 198 (dt.), S. 294 (franz.) SPECULUM MENTIS or The Map of Knowledge by R. G. COLLINGWOOD- OXFORD AT THE CLARENDON PRESS [1924] Reprint London et al. 1946 CONTENTS PAGE PREFACE 9 I. PROLOGUE 15 -11. SPECULUM MENTIS 39 Ill. ART I. Art as pure Imagination 58 2. The Work of Art 63 3. The Monadism of Art 68 4. Meaning in Art 13 5. Knowledge as Question and Answer 76 6. Art as a form of Error 80 7. The Dialectic of Art . 91 8. Play 102 IV. RELIGION I. The Transition from Art to Religion 108 2. The Growth of Religion Il2 3. Religion and its Object Il7 4. Symbol and Meaning in Religion 122 5. Convention 134 6. The Task of Religion 138 7. The Transition from Religion to the Life of Thought 146 V. SCIENCE I. The Life of Thought._ 154 2. Science as the assertion of the Abstract Concept 158 3. A priori or Deductive Science 163 4. Utility or Abstract Ethics . 169 5. Empirical or Inductive Science 176 6. Science as Supposal 180 7. Science as the Intuitive Form of Thought 188 8. Understanding and Reason 195 8 CONTENTS VI. HISTORY PAGE I. History as the Assertion of Fact .
    [Show full text]
  • The Disjunctive Aesthetics Af Myth and Empathy in Thea Angelopaulas' Ulysses Gaze Vrasldas Karalls
    The Disjunctive Aesthetics af Myth and Empathy in Thea Angelopaulas' Ulysses Gaze Vrasldas Karalls 77ze true is inimitable, the false un transformable. Robert Bresson j) As a Prelude In his insightful study on Theo Angelopoulos' cinema, Andrew Horton posits an extremely crucial question about the director's visual strategies in order to establish creative empathy between his audience and his epic cinema of 'contemplation': "while Angelopoulos often refers to Brecht and the need for an audience to think as well as feel in theater and cinema, we do not experience anything close to what could be called an 'alienation effect' in Brechtian terms. To the contrary, the mixture of theatricality and reality in his films often leads us into a deeper, fuller emotional bond with the film - one that, we could say, embraces our thinking mind as well".1 In our opinion, this premise needs qualifications and some further discussion in order to better appreciate the formal and visual techniques employed by Angelopoulos to transport his viewer through imaginative empathy into the levels of meaning that themselves establish and denote. For this purpose we will attempt a close look at one of his most 'epic' films, Ulysses' Gaze (1995), in order to examine the creative dilemmas of the artist in an era of intense commercialisation of cinema and of the absence of political projects for artistic renewal. 1 I lorton. Andrew, (1997: 14-15) The Films ofTheo Angelopoulos. A Cinema ofContemplation. Princeton University Press. Princeton New Jersey. Vrasidas Karalis,
    [Show full text]
  • Computational Aesthetics Based on Gaze Patterns
    ISAMA BRIDGES The International Society of the Mathematical Connections Arts, Mathematics, and Architecture in Art, Music, and Science Computational Aesthetics Based On Gaze Patterns Gary R. Greenfield Department of Mathematics & Computer Science University of Richmond Richmond, VA 23173, U.S.A. [email protected] Abstract Generative art systems usually rely on the technique of user-guided evolution to enable "artists" to interactively search through populations of images in order to breed those images which show aesthetic promise. We consider algorithmic criteria for automating the aesthetic evaluation step. Our criteria are inspired by a recent description of techniques used for controlling the aesthetic reorganization of photorealistic imagery. Surprisingly, our approach seems to impose a rigid style on the images we evolve. A drawback to our method is that eventually it fails to clearly differentiate between non-degenerate and degenerate images. We consider how improvements might be made. 1. Introduction It is difficult to formulate general purpose aesthetic metrics for visual imagery. The human visual system is both complex and sophisticated. Moreover, human aesthetic decision making is subject to cognitive and cultural biases. To date, there appear to be a limited number of examples where aesthetic evaluation of images by computational means has been wholly successful. At one extreme lie simple generative systems whose underlying objective is to color the squares within a relatively small rectangular grid using only a limited number of colors. In this caSe reasonable metrics for identifying aesthetic qualities such as balance, symmetry, and pattern have been studied [9] [16]. At the other extreme lie specialized generative systems supporting the narrowly defined "styles" of individual artists.
    [Show full text]
  • The Male Gaze and the (In)Visible Bodies of Muslim Women—A Response Article
    Journal of International Women's Studies Volume 19 | Issue 2 Article 14 Jan-2018 Lost in Translation: The aleM Gaze and The (In)visible Bodies of Muslim Women - A Response Article Ewa Glapka Follow this and additional works at: http://vc.bridgew.edu/jiws Part of the Women's Studies Commons Recommended Citation Glapka, Ewa (2018). Lost in Translation: The aleM Gaze and The I( n)visible Bodies of Muslim Women - A Response Article. Journal of International Women's Studies, 19(2), 215-229. Available at: http://vc.bridgew.edu/jiws/vol19/iss2/14 This item is available as part of Virtual Commons, the open-access institutional repository of Bridgewater State University, Bridgewater, Massachusetts. This journal and its contents may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. ©2018 Journal of International Women’s Studies. Lost in Translation: The Male Gaze and The (In)visible Bodies of Muslim Women—A Response Article By Ewa Glapka1 Abstract This article explores women’s relationship with the patriarchal surveillance of their bodies—‘the male gaze’. Going beyond the scholarly tradition of solely critiquing the patriarchal discourse of the female body, the study examines the processes in which individuals relate to the male gaze by means of socio-culturally available meaning-making resources. The analysis is based on interviews with Muslim women in South Africa who talk about their hijab practices and thus position themselves to the patriarchal discourses of Islam and West.
    [Show full text]
  • Heidegger, Metaphor, and the Essence of Language Joel Meservy Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected]
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Master's Theses Graduate School 2014 Heidegger, metaphor, and the essence of language Joel Meservy Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses Part of the Arts and Humanities Commons Recommended Citation Meservy, Joel, "Heidegger, metaphor, and the essence of language" (2014). LSU Master's Theses. 277. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_theses/277 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Master's Theses by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. HEIDEGGER, METAPHOR, AND THE ESSENCE OF LANGUAGE A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in The Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies by Joel Meservy B.A., University of Tennessee, 2009 May 2014 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This thesis was made possible only with the help and support of many people. I would first like to thank Anna Rose, who took care of me when I could not; Cliff and Deb Meservy, for their perennial encouragement and support; Anthony Chow, for stress management counseling; Thelonius, Bill, Penelope, and Quattro, for their comfort and calm; Eric Pannico and Jaideep Shah, for their feedback and comments; and the rest of my friends and family, for all the little things. Finally, I would like to thank the members of my committee, Greg Schufreider, François Raffoul, and Mary Sirridge, for committing time and resources to this project.
    [Show full text]
  • Woman As Object of Male Gaze in Some Works of Nigerian Artists
    WOMAN AS OBJECT OF MALE GAZE IN SOME WORKS OF NIGERIAN ARTISTS. Nkiruka Jane Nwafor Center for Excellence in the Arts and Humanities, Nnamdi Azikiwe University, Awka. [email protected] Abstract This essay interrogates visual representations of women in the fine arts especially paintings and drawings by Nigerian male artists. In it, I question how numerous issues pertaining to gender, sexuality and sexual differences are imagined and contested through artworks. I analyze some artworks by contemporary Nigerian male artists to see what layers of male gaze are in the Nigerian art scenario. I also take on the argument that some Nigerian male artists‟ perception of women in paintings reflects in most cases, the overriding traditional understanding of the woman as the differential, sexualized, and passive and equally subservient „other.‟ The essay raises questions about the stereotypical stance of women as inferior and irrational beings, unable to engage critically and often understood from their ascribed inert domestic or sexual roles. This is in opposition to representations of men in pictures as engaging, assertive and active. The essay shows how the artist‟s (usually male) narcissistic imaginative creations are imagined in the public space, as reality. The tendency to assume control over the „other,‟ is not only linked to questions of Eurocentric/colonial gaze and its mechanism of representation but, have also been applied to how the male perceives and understands its relationship with the female „other.‟ In the initial writings concerning the concept of gaze, it had been applied to how an audience viewed the people presented or depicted in visual culture.
    [Show full text]
  • Schopenhauer on Suicide and Negation of the Will Michal Masny Philosophy Department, Princeton University, Princeton, NJ, USA
    BRITISH JOURNAL FOR THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 2021, VOL. 29, NO. 3, 494–516 https://doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2020.1807909 ARTICLE Schopenhauer on suicide and negation of the will Michal Masny Philosophy Department, Princeton University, Princeton, NJ, USA ABSTRACT Schopenhauer’s argument against suicide has served as a punching bag for many modern-day commentators. Dale Jacquette, Sandra Shapshay, and David Hamlyn all argue that the premises of this argument or its conclusion are inconsistent with Schopenhauer’s wider metaphysical and ethical project. This paper defends Schopenhauer from these charges. Along the way, it examines the relations between suicide, death by voluntary starvation, negation of the will, compassion, and Schopenhauer’s critiques of cynicism and stoicism. The paper concludes that there may be gaps in Schopenhauer’s system, but not where the aforementioned commentators tried to locate them. ARTICLE HISTORY Received 28 January 2020; Revised 14 Juneand3August2020;Accepted6August2020 KEYWORDS Schopenhauer; suicide; salvation; stoicism; compassion 1. Introduction Schopenhauer’s argument against suicide has served as a punching bag for many modern-day commentators. It is often claimed that its premises or con- clusion are inconsistent with Schopenhauer’s wider metaphysical and ethical project. For instance, Dale Jacquette (“Schopenhauer on Death”; “The Ethics of Suicide”; The Philosophy of Schopenhauer) argues that even if Schopenhauer succeeds in showing that suicide is often objectionable, he has no effective objection to ‘philosophically enlightened suicide’. This claim is endorsed by Sandra Shapshay (“Review”) and supplemented by the worry that Schopen- hauer has no good answer to the question ‘why not annihilate all sentient creatures?’.
    [Show full text]
  • Measuring and Modeling the Perception of Natural and Unconstrained Gaze in Humans and Machines
    CBMM Memo No. 059 November 28, 2016 Measuring and modeling the perception of natural and unconstrained gaze in humans and machines Daniel Harari*, Tao Gao*, Nancy Kanwisher, Joshua Tenenbaum, Shimon Ullman Abstract Humans are remarkably adept at interpreting the gaze direction of other individuals in their surroundings. This skill is at the core of the ability to engage in joint visual attention, which is essential for establishing social interactions. How accurate are humans in determining the gaze direction of others in lifelike scenes, when they can move their heads and eyes freely, and what are the sources of information for the underlying perceptual processes? These questions pose a challenge from both empirical and computational perspectives, due to the complexity of the visual input in real-life situations. Here we measure empirically human accuracy in perceiving the gaze direction of others in lifelike scenes, and study computationally the sources of information and representations underlying this cognitive capacity. We show that humans perform better in face-to-face conditions compared with ‘recorded’ conditions, and that this advantage is not due to the availability of input dynamics. We further show that humans are still performing well when only the eyes-region is visible, rather than the whole face. We develop a computational model, which replicates the pattern of human performance, including the finding that the eyes-region contains on its own, the required information for estimating both head orientation and direction of gaze. Consistent with neurophysiological findings on task-specific “face” regions in the brain, the learned computational representations reproduce perceptual effects such as the ‘Wollaston illusion’, when trained to estimate direction of gaze, but not when trained to recognize objects or faces.
    [Show full text]