Internalism Defended Author(S): Richard Feldman and Earl Conee Source: American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Internalism Defended Author(S): Richard Feldman and Earl Conee Source: American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol Internalism Defended Author(s): Richard Feldman and Earl Conee Source: American Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 38, No. 1 (Jan., 2001), pp. 1-18 Published by: University of Illinois Press on behalf of North American Philosophical Publications Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20010019 Accessed: 08/01/2009 17:48 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=illinois. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. University of Illinois Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to American Philosophical Quarterly. http://www.jstor.org American Philosophical Quarterly Volume 38, Number 1, January 2001 INTERNALISM DEFENDED Richard Feldman and Earl Conee Anternalism in epistemology has been get? the terms are routinely applied to theories ting bad press lately. Externalism is that predate their use. Thus, many propo? ascendant, partly because insurmountable nents of theories of justification have not problems for internalism are supposed to classified their views as internalist or have been identified.1 We oppose this trend. externalist. The recent literature is, there? In our view the purported problems pose fore, the best source of information about no serious threat, and a convincing argu? the nature of the distinction. Here are a few ment for internalism is untouched by the examples of how internalism has been recent criticism. identified. Laurence BonJour writes: Our main here is to refute goal objections most The generally accepted account... is to internalism. We what begin by offering that a theory of justification is internalist if we think is the best to understand the way and only if it requires that all of the factors distinction between exter? internalism and needed for a belief to be epistemically justi? nalism. We then present a new argument fied for a given person be cognitively for internalism. This frees internalism from accessible to that person, internal to his cog? nitive what we regard as suspect deontological perspective.2 underpinnings. Finally, we reply to what Robert Audi writes: we take to be the most significant objec? Some examples suggest that justification is tions to internalism. grounded entirely in what is internal to the mind, in a sense that it is acces? I.What is Internalism? implying sible to introspection or reflection by the we Internalism and externalism are views subject?a view might call internalism about about which states, events, and conditions justification.3 can contribute to epistemic justification? Alvin Plantinga writes: the sort of that, in sufficient justification The basic thrust of internalism in epistemol is a condition for strength, necessary ogy, therefore, is that the properties that Use of the terms "internalist" knowledge. confer warrant upon a belief are properties and "externalist" to classify theories of to which the believer has some special sort justification is a recent development, and of epistemic access.4 1 2 / AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICALQUARTERLY John Pollock writes that: the special kind of access on which many internalist theories can reach Internalism in epistemology is the view that rely only mental items, and all mental items, only internal states of the cognizer can be rel? perhaps or at least all that be counted as evant in determining which of the cognizer's might play? a beliefs are justified.5 ing role in justification. We think that simplicity and clarity are Finally, Ernest Sosa characterizes one ver? best served by understanding internalism sion of internalism this way: as mentalism. "Internalism" is a recent Justification requires only really proper technical term. It has been introduced to thought on the part of the subject: if a be? refer to a variety of theories in epistemol liever has obtained and sustains his belief ogy that share some vaguely defined salient through wholly appropriate thought, then the feature. Any definition of the term is to believer is justified in so believing?where some extent Mentalism codi? the appropriateness of the thought is a mat? stipulative. fies one standard in which the word ter purely internal to the mind of the subject, way has been used. and not dependent on what lies beyond.6 Somewhat more internalism as We find two distinct but related precisely, closely we characterize it is committed to the fol? characterizations of internalism in passages two theses. The first asserts the such as these. One characterization uses a lowing strong of notion of access. What we shall call supervenience epistemic justifi? cation on the mental: "accessibilism" holds that the epistemic S. The status of a justification of a person's belief is deter? justificatory person's doxastic attitudes strongly supervenes on mined by things to which the person has the person's occurrent and dispositional some special sort of access. BonJour calls mental states, events, and conditions. this access a "suitable awareness."7 Audi thesis out a says that the access is through "introspec? The second spells principal tion or reflection." Others say that the implication of S: access must be "direct."8 The quotations M. If any two possible individuals are exactly a from Pollock and Sosa suggest somewhat alike mentally, then they are exactly alike same are different account. They suggest that justificationally, e.g., the beliefs internalism is the view that a person's be? justified for them to the same extent.10 liefs are things that are justified only by (M) implies that mental duplicates in differ? internal to the mental life. We person's ent possible worlds have the same attitudes shall call this version of internalism "men justified for them. This cross world compari? talism."9 A mentalist may assert that theory son follows from the strong supervenience is determined oc justification entirely by condition in (S).11 Externalists characteristi? current mental factors, or by dispositional cally hold that differences in justification can ones as well. As as the that are long things result from contingent non-mental differ? said to contribute to are in the justification ences, such as differing causal connections mind, the view as a ver? person's qualifies or reliability. Theories that appeal to such sion of mentalism. factors clearly deny (S) and (M). Thus, our We think it that have likely philosophers way of spelling out the internalism/exter not mentalism from accessibilism separated nalism distinction properly classifies because have assumed that the they tacitly characteristically externalist views. extensions of the two do not differ in any One advantage of our way of understand? way. have assumed that significant They ing the distinction between internalism and INTERNALISMDEFENDED / 3 one externalism in epistemology is that it Thus, modest asset of mentalism is closely parallels the counterpart distinction that it renders readily intelligible the nomi? to in the philosophy of mind.12 In the philoso? nal connection of epistemic internalism phy of mind case, the main idea is to mind internalism. A much stronger consid? that it turns distinguish the view that the contents of eration in favor of mentalism is as we attitudes depend entirely on things within out to be entirely defensible, shall a person's own cognitive apparatus from try to show. the view that there are factors external to IL A Defense of Internalism the person that help to determine attitudinal content. Mind internalism is naturally ren? Our argument for internalism focuses on dered as a supervenience thesis. Roughly, the pairs of examples that we take to be repre? thesis is that a person's mental content su? sentative. Either in one member of the pair pervenes on the person's "purely internal" someone has a justified belief in a propo? states, events, and conditions. The relevant sition while someone else's belief in that as supervenience base cannot be specified proposition is not justified, or one person's "the mental," as we have done for epistemic belief is better justified than the other's. internalism, since a mental states, person's We contend that these contrasts are best events, and conditions are trivially suffi? explained by supposing that internal dif? cient for the person's attitudes with their ferences make the epistemic difference. specific contents. But the root idea is the Here are the examples. same. The mind internalist is trying to ex? Example 1) Bob and Ray are sitting in clude such plainly external factors as the an air-conditioned hotel lobby reading environmental causal origins and the so? yesterday's newspaper. Each has read that cial milieu of the person's attitudes. it will be very warm today and, on that Likewise, the epistemic internalist is prin? basis, each believes that it is very warm cipally opposed to the existence of any today. Then Bob goes outside and feels the justification-determining role for heat.
Recommended publications
  • Connecting Science and Wisdom Derstood Them in Her Lifetime
    ew concepts are so rich in meaning and at the same time so open to a diversity of interpretations as is “nature.” “Na- ture” refers to the immense reality in which every thing and Fperson exists and of which they constitute an integral part. It is precisely this reality of nature that I will discuss, tracing briefly The “Book of Nature” some of its characteristics as Chiara Lubich experienced and un- Connecting Science and Wisdom derstood them in her lifetime. The term “nature” generally refers to all existing things, with Sergio Rondinara particular regard to their objective configuration and their essen- Sophia University Institute tial constitutive principles. This connection between totality and essentiality—as the etymology of the word “nature” suggests1—is also found in Chiara’s reflections. Their deeply theological charac- Rondinara explores the reality of nature, both in its totality and in ter must be understood not so much as human speech about God its essence, from different perspectives. In so doing, he discusses how and the divine mystery but in their proper meaning as a subjective Chiara Lubich envisions nature in relation to God and humankind. genitive—a word that is both noun and verb.2 In language that First, he examines the God- nature relation as Chiara understood it, as seems ordinary, her texts shine with clarity and incisiveness. They both immanent and transcendent. Then, he turns to Chiara’s notion of offer God’s vision of things and of the natural world, a contempla- nature as an ongoing “event” in history leading to the recapitulation of tive gaze that—metaphorically speaking—comes from the “eyes of all things in God.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant on Formative Power
    26 Ina Goy INA GOY KANT(Concordia ON FORMATIVE University, Montreal POWER) The notion of a formative1 power is one of the most obscure in Kant’s theory of biology . Before I discuss Kant’s biological use of the term ‘formative power’, in section 1 of this paper I provide a list of all passages in which Kant uses the term, claiming that the older meaning of ‘formative power’ in Kant’s writings is an epi- stemological one, whereas the biological meaning of the term ap- pears not before the mid-1780s. I present and discuss some of thoseCriti passagesque of thein closer power detail, of jud andgment give a precise interpretation of the most central passage in Kant’s philosophy2 of biology in §65 of the . I defend the view that, for Kant, the formative power is a basic, immaterial, and intrinsic natural power in the organism belonging to an account of final causation. As a cause, it does not generate form and matter, or the matter of organisms, but only the end-directed teleological3 form of the matter of an organism. AsKant an on alternative vital force. Metaphysical to White’s concernsclaim ver- sus1 scientific practice Kants Philosophie der Natur. Ihre Entwick- lungFor imrecent inquiries seeund H. van ihre den WirkungBerg, Bildungskraft, in E.-O. und Onnasch Bildungstrieb (ed.), bei ibid. Der Baum imOpus Baum. postumumModellkörper, reproductive, Berlin Systeme- New und York, die DeDifferenzGruyterzwischen, 2009, pp. Leben 115- digem136; G.F. und Frigo, Unlebendigem bei Kant und Bonnet ibidKant, in , pp. 9-23; T. BlCheung,umenbach and Kant on mechanism and teleology in nature: the case of the formative drive The problem of animal generation in early, in modern, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • CHAPTER 2.1 Augustine: Commentary
    CHAPTER 2.1 Augustine: Commentary Augustine Aurelius Augustinus Hipponensis (henceforth Augustine) was born in 354 A.D. in the municipium of Thagaste (modern day Souk Ahras, Algeria, close to the border with Tunisia). He died in 430, as the Arian1 Vandals besieged the city of Hippo where he was bishop, marking another stage in the demise of the Roman Empire. Rome had already been sacked in 410 by Alaric the Visigoth, but the slow decline of Roman grandeur took place over a period of about 320 years which culminated in 476 when Romulus Augustus, the last Emperor of the Western Roman Empire, was deposed by Odoacer, a Germanic chieftain. Augustine thus lived at a time which heralded the death knell of the ancient world and the beginnings of mediaeval western European Christendom.2 Augustine‘s great legacy to western civilization is that intellectually he united both worlds in drawing from the ancient thought of Greece and Rome and providing a Christian understanding of the intellectual achievements of the ancients. His new synthesis is a remarkable achievement even today and for those of us, who remain Christians in the West, our debates, agreements and disagreements are still pursued in Augustine‘s shadow.3 1 Arianism was a schismatic sect of Christianity that held the view that the Second Person of the Trinity, Christ, is created and thus does not exist eternally with the Father. 2 See J. M. Rist‘s magnificent Augustine: Ancient Thought Baptized, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2003. Rist notes that, ‗Despite his lack of resources he managed to sit in judgment on ancient philosophy and ancient culture.‘ p.
    [Show full text]
  • AUGUSTINE on SUFFERING and ORDER: PUNISHMENT in CONTEXT by SAMANTHA ELIZABETH THOMPSON a Thesis Submitted in Conformity With
    AUGUSTINE ON SUFFERING AND ORDER: PUNISHMENT IN CONTEXT BY SAMANTHA ELIZABETH THOMPSON A Thesis Submitted in Conformity with the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Samantha Elizabeth Thompson 2010 Augustine on Suffering and Order: Punishment in Context Samantha Elizabeth Thompson Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2010 Abstract Augustine of Hippo argues that all suffering is the result of the punishment of sin. Misinterpretations of his meaning are common since isolated statements taken from his works do give misleading and contradictory impressions. This dissertation assembles a comprehensive account of Augustine’s understanding of the causes of suffering to show that these views are substantive and internally consistent. The argument of the dissertation proceeds by confronting and resolving the apparent problems with Augustine’s views on sin and punishment from within the broader framework of his anthropology and metaphysics. The chief difficulty is that Augustine gives two apparently irreconcilable accounts of suffering as punishment. In the first, suffering is viewed as self-inflicted because sin is inherently self-damaging. In the second, God inflicts suffering in response to sin. This dissertation argues that these views are united by Augustine’s concern with the theme of ‘order.’ The first account, it argues, is actually an expression of Augustine’s doctrine that evil is the privation of good; since good is for Augustine synonymous with order, we can then see why he views all affliction as the concrete experience of disorder brought about by sin. This context in turn allows us to see that, by invoking the ii notion of divinely inflicted punishment in both its retributive and remedial forms, Augustine wants to show that disorder itself is embraced by order, either because disorder itself must obey laws, or because what is disordered can be reordered.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cybernetic Brain
    THE CYBERNETIC BRAIN THE CYBERNETIC BRAIN SKETCHES OF ANOTHER FUTURE Andrew Pickering THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS CHICAGO AND LONDON ANDREW PICKERING IS PROFESSOR OF SOCIOLOGY AND PHILOSOPHY AT THE UNIVERSITY OF EXETER. HIS BOOKS INCLUDE CONSTRUCTING QUARKS: A SO- CIOLOGICAL HISTORY OF PARTICLE PHYSICS, THE MANGLE OF PRACTICE: TIME, AGENCY, AND SCIENCE, AND SCIENCE AS PRACTICE AND CULTURE, A L L PUBLISHED BY THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS, AND THE MANGLE IN PRAC- TICE: SCIENCE, SOCIETY, AND BECOMING (COEDITED WITH KEITH GUZIK). THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS, CHICAGO 60637 THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS, LTD., LONDON © 2010 BY THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO ALL RIGHTS RESERVED. PUBLISHED 2010 PRINTED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA 19 18 17 16 15 14 13 12 11 10 1 2 3 4 5 ISBN-13: 978-0-226-66789-8 (CLOTH) ISBN-10: 0-226-66789-8 (CLOTH) Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Pickering, Andrew. The cybernetic brain : sketches of another future / Andrew Pickering. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN-13: 978-0-226-66789-8 (cloth : alk. paper) ISBN-10: 0-226-66789-8 (cloth : alk. paper) 1. Cybernetics. 2. Cybernetics—History. 3. Brain. 4. Self-organizing systems. I. Title. Q310.P53 2010 003’.5—dc22 2009023367 a THE PAPER USED IN THIS PUBLICATION MEETS THE MINIMUM REQUIREMENTS OF THE AMERICAN NATIONAL STANDARD FOR INFORMATION SCIENCES—PERMA- NENCE OF PAPER FOR PRINTED LIBRARY MATERIALS, ANSI Z39.48-1992. DEDICATION For Jane F. CONTENTS Acknowledgments / ix 1. The Adaptive Brain / 1 2. Ontological Theater / 17 PART 1: PSYCHIATRY TO CYBERNETICS 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Radical Internalism – Draft 4.5 (Spring 2020)
    Radical Internalism – draft 4.5 (Spring 2020) Radical Internalism ZOË JOHNSON KING New York University ’Cause the circle of hatred continues unless we react We gotta take the power back! – Rage Against The Machine 1. Introduction We live in dark times, morally, politically, and epistemically. Oppressive social structures create hierarchies of dominance and marginalization between social groups — hierarchies based on gender, race, class, sexual orientation, and disability, for example. And these social hierarchies each reinforce and are reinforced by ideologies that both limit the evidence we receive about them and distort the ways we learn to respond to the evidence that we have. 1 It is thus difficult to figure out the truth about morally and politically important matters, not only because these matters are complex, but also because ideology prevents us from acquiring and appropriately reacting to accurate information about them. In this way, ideology sustains oppressive social structures by preventing us from learning about them. If you disagree with some of what I’ve said so far, then you can stop reading now. This paper is addressed to those who agree with this rough description of the times we are in and would like to figure out what we ought to do — morally and epistemically — in light of it. Amia Srinivasan (2020) introduces the term “radical worldview” for the sort of worldview I just articulated. Srinivasan’s paper is a novel and powerful defense of externalism about epistemic justification. She argues that externalism should be preferred to internalism by those who hold a radical worldview (like the one I just articulated).
    [Show full text]
  • The Spoils of Shame
    The Spoils of Shame: Queer Affect in the Works of Oscar Wilde, James Joyce, Radclyffe Hall, and Virginia Woolf By Dominique D. Groeneveld Dissertation Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of English at Brown University PROVIDENCE, RHODE ISLAND MAY, 2011 @ Copyright 2011 by Dominique D. Groeneveld This dissertation by Dominique D. Groeneveld is accepted in its present form by the Department of English as satisfying the dissertation requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Date ___________ ____________________________________ Prof. Barbara Herrnstein Smith, Advisor Recommended to the Graduate Council Date ___________ ____________________________________ Prof. Ellen Rooney, Reader Date ___________ ____________________________________ Prof. Tamar Katz, Reader Approved by the Graduate Council Date ___________ ____________________________________ Prof. Peter Weber, Dean of the Graduate School iii Curriculum Vitae Dominique D. Groeneveld attended the University of Amsterdam, the Netherlands, where she earned a Master‟s degree (Cum Laude) in the Department of Comparative Literature in 1995. Her Master‟s thesis interrogates critical constructions of the law in Continental modernist writing. Between 1997 and 1999, she has taught in the courses in English literature at Houston Community College and the University of Houston. As a graduate student in the Department of English Literature at Brown University, she has specialized in the fields of Anglophone literature from 1900-1945, literary theory, and the study of gender and sexuality; on the latter, she has designed and taught a number of undergraduate seminars at Brown. She was the recipient of the Florence Harnish Dissertation Fellowship and the Graduate Fellowship to the 2003-2004 Pembroke Seminar.
    [Show full text]
  • The Metaphysical Foundations Underlying Augustine's Solution to the Problem of Evil
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 11-30-2007 Between Being and Nothingness: The Metaphysical Foundations Underlying Augustine's Solution to the Problem of Evil Brian Keith Kooy Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Kooy, Brian Keith, "Between Being and Nothingness: The Metaphysical Foundations Underlying Augustine's Solution to the Problem of Evil." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2007. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/32 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BETWEEN BEING AND NOTHINGNESS: THE METAPHYSICAL FOUNDATIONS UNDERLYING AUGUSTINE’S SOLUTION TO THE PROBLEM OF EVIL by BRIAN KEITH KOOY Under the Direction of Dr. Timothy M. Renick ABSTRACT Several commentators make the claim that Augustine is not a systematic thinker. The purpose of this thesis is to refute that claim in one specific area of Augustine's thought, the metaphysical foundations underlying his solutions to the problem of evil. Through an exegetical examination of various works in which Augustine writes on evil, I show that his solutions for both natural and moral evil rely on a coherent metaphysical system,
    [Show full text]
  • Speech As Metaphor of Human Becoming According to St. Augustine of Hippo
    Speech as Metaphor of Human Becoming According to St. Augustine of Hippo by Yana Filipenko Institute for Christian Studies, 2000 Content Explanatory Notes.................................................................................................................v Latin-English Equivalent...................................................................................................vi Introduction..........................................................................................................................vii I. Ontological Relation of Being and Becoming when Mapped on to the Biblical Creator/Creation Distinction............................................................................................. 1 1.1. Philo sophico-Historical Setting of Augustine’s Doctrine of Being and Becoming..............................................................................................................................1 Parmenides on Being.....................................................................................................2 Plato’s Dualism.............................................................................................................. 2 Plotinus and the One......................................................................................................3 Augustine’s Use of the Tradition................................................................................. 5 1.2. God as Being (esse) and Creator According to St. Augustine. Creation in the Order o f Being....................................................................................................................5
    [Show full text]
  • Should Deliberative Democratic Inclusion Extend to Children?
    Epistemic Inclusion and the Argument from Circumspection A Response to Should Deliberative Democratic Inclusion Extend to Children? James Scott Johnston (Memorial University of Newfoundland) Abstract In this response to Martin’s “Should Deliberate Democratic Inclusion Extend to Children?” I examine Martin’s comments against the “argument from circumspection,” which is dubious regarding the claims children make to change democratic policies and procedures. I explain there are good reasons for being circumspect. One of these concerns the need for all in public discourse to supply not just claims but reasons and to have both these claims and reasons adjudicated in the logical space of rea- sons. Children, as with all who practice public discourse, must have their claims and reasons assessed for these to be admitted as candidates for changing policies and procedures. This augurs for a case- by- case inclusion of children, as opposed to a wholesale one. This article is in response to Martin, C. (2018). Should Deliberative Democratic Inclusion Extend to Children? Democracy and Education, 26(2), Article 4. Available at: https:// democracyeducationjournal .org/ home/ vol26/ iss2/ 4 Introduction problems, to self- consciously deliberative accounts. In the former case, Martin gave examples of Immanuel Kant, John Rawls, and Lawrence Kohlberg (Martin, 2018, p. 5). In these latter, what counts as epistemic principle, epistemic inclusion, and epistemic n “Should Deliberative Democratic Inclusion Extend reason took center stage (Martin, 2018, pp. 8– 9). Sorting this to Children?” Martin (2018) claimed philosophical interest terminology out is a chief feature of this section of his essay. in the ways in which children may be justifiably excluded Martin claimed epistemic principle as the principle of propor- from voting.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine of Hippo: a Historical Theology Critique
    Olivet Nazarene University Digital Commons @ Olivet Honors Program Projects Honors Program Spring 5-2021 Augustine of Hippo: A Historical Theology Critique Zachary Monte Olivet Nazarene University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.olivet.edu/honr_proj Part of the Applied Ethics Commons, Christianity Commons, Epistemology Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, Ethics in Religion Commons, History of Christianity Commons, History of Religions of Western Origin Commons, Liturgy and Worship Commons, Metaphysics Commons, Missions and World Christianity Commons, Other Anthropology Commons, Philosophy of Mind Commons, Political Theory Commons, Practical Theology Commons, Religious Education Commons, Religious Thought, Theology and Philosophy of Religion Commons, and the Rhetoric Commons Recommended Citation Monte, Zachary, "Augustine of Hippo: A Historical Theology Critique" (2021). Honors Program Projects. 122. https://digitalcommons.olivet.edu/honr_proj/122 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Honors Program at Digital Commons @ Olivet. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Program Projects by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ Olivet. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Monte ii Acknowledgements I would like to thank the Olivet Honors Program Faculty for their investment in my academic career. I especially thank Dr. Mark Frisius for his patience and oversight of this research. I would also like to thank my lovely fiancée, Hannah Lewis, for all her support through this season of life. Most of all, I would like to thank my parents for sacrificing as much as needed for my development into a minister and a scholar. Monte iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements............................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Title Meiji Japan's Encounter with Modernization Author(S) Furukawa
    Title Meiji Japan's Encounter with Modernization Author(s) Furukawa, Hisao Citation 東南アジア研究 (1995), 33(3): 497-518 Issue Date 1995-12 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/56553 Right Type Departmental Bulletin Paper Textversion publisher Kyoto University Southeast Asian Studies. Vol. 33, No.3, December 1995 Meiji Japan's Encounter with Modernization Hisao FURUKAWA * I The Modern Age The periodization of history is probably just as important a task for the historian as the establishment of areal divisions is for the researcher in area study. How history is divided, and how the world is divided into areas, express in their demarcations the condensation of a comprehensive view of world history and of a view of the relationship between nature and man. During my two trips to China in 1990 and 1991, I had the pleasure of reading Ichisada Miyazaki's two-volume History of China [Miyazaki 1977], which convinced me that the division of time into four periods - ancient times, the middle ages, pre-modern times, and most-modern times (the modern age) - in a centralized society such as China was appropriate. This four-period system is extended to the whole of world history, and the following reason is given for dividing Europe's modern age from pre-modern times. Silver ingots mined and smelted in the New World by slaves were brought to Europe, which profited from unheard-of prosperity.... The European world came to create an industrial revolutionary culture that practically regarded preceding cultures as worthless. This began in the latter half of the eighteenth century, and the history of Europe at this stage suddenly entered a new phase.
    [Show full text]