AUGUSTINE on SUFFERING and ORDER: PUNISHMENT in CONTEXT by SAMANTHA ELIZABETH THOMPSON a Thesis Submitted in Conformity With

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

AUGUSTINE on SUFFERING and ORDER: PUNISHMENT in CONTEXT by SAMANTHA ELIZABETH THOMPSON a Thesis Submitted in Conformity With AUGUSTINE ON SUFFERING AND ORDER: PUNISHMENT IN CONTEXT BY SAMANTHA ELIZABETH THOMPSON A Thesis Submitted in Conformity with the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Samantha Elizabeth Thompson 2010 Augustine on Suffering and Order: Punishment in Context Samantha Elizabeth Thompson Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2010 Abstract Augustine of Hippo argues that all suffering is the result of the punishment of sin. Misinterpretations of his meaning are common since isolated statements taken from his works do give misleading and contradictory impressions. This dissertation assembles a comprehensive account of Augustine’s understanding of the causes of suffering to show that these views are substantive and internally consistent. The argument of the dissertation proceeds by confronting and resolving the apparent problems with Augustine’s views on sin and punishment from within the broader framework of his anthropology and metaphysics. The chief difficulty is that Augustine gives two apparently irreconcilable accounts of suffering as punishment. In the first, suffering is viewed as self-inflicted because sin is inherently self-damaging. In the second, God inflicts suffering in response to sin. This dissertation argues that these views are united by Augustine’s concern with the theme of ‘order.’ The first account, it argues, is actually an expression of Augustine’s doctrine that evil is the privation of good; since good is for Augustine synonymous with order, we can then see why he views all affliction as the concrete experience of disorder brought about by sin. This context in turn allows us to see that, by invoking the ii notion of divinely inflicted punishment in both its retributive and remedial forms, Augustine wants to show that disorder itself is embraced by order, either because disorder itself must obey laws, or because what is disordered can be reordered. In either case, Augustine’s ideas of punishment may be seen as an expression of his conviction that order in the universe is unassailable. It is hoped that these observations contribute to a greater appreciation not only of Augustine’s theory of punishment, but also of the extent to which the theme of order is fundamental to his thought. iii In memory of George Snell. requiescat in pace iv Acknowledgments Special thanks are due to the following individuals. My early fascinating conversations with Claudia Eisen Murphy validated my ideas and consolidated the framework of my argument. Larry Schmidt has been an ever loyal friend, cheerleader, and surrogate father, always ready to read and discuss ragged bits and pieces of my work as well as to meet for lunches and state-of- the-world rants. He has never failed to affirm my ability and my sanity when I have at times doubted both. Brad Inwood has been my constant link to the philosophy department and to academe. Without his unflagging interest and incisive down-to-earth advice, this thesis would never have been completed. He has shown kindness far beyond the call of duty more times than I can count. My supervisor, John Rist, has consistently maintained his lightning fast response time to my questions and draft revisions, despite his being across the Atlantic, which he so generously traversed to be present at my thesis defence. Lastly, I thank my mother whose boundless patience and love have sustained me through numerous challenges, of which this dissertation has been the least. v Contents Abbreviations. vii Preface. x Introduction. Augustine’s Problem: Suffering as Punishment.. 1 PART I: The Natural Account. 33 Chapter 1. Evil and Dependence: The Foundation and Scope of the Natural Account.. 34 Chapter 2. Order and Existence: What Goodness is. 50 1. Augustine’s Dualism: Unity and Order. 53 2. The Sharing of Order: The Hierarchy of Goodness. 74 Chapter 3. Order and Experience: What Goodness is like. 89 Prolegomenon: Happiness and Love as Organizing Principles. 91 1. Happiness and Order. 97 2. Suffering and Disorder.. 114 PART II: The Legal Account. 134 Chapter 4. The Problem Revisited: God and Disorder. 135 Chapter 5. Retributive Punishment: Good for the Universe. 161 Chapter 6. Remedial Punishment: Good for the Sinner.. 180 Concluding Remarks. 206 Bibliography.. 211 1. Texts and Translations. 211 2. Secondary Works. 214 vi Abbreviations (as in Fitzgerald 1999) b. vita De beata vita cat. rud. De catechizandis rudibus civ. Dei De civitate Dei conf. Confessiones corrept. De correptione et gratia dial. De dialectica div. qu. De diversis quaestionibus octoginta tribus doc. Chr. De doctrina Christiana duab. an. De duabus animabus en. Ps. Enarrationes in Psalmos ench. Enchiridion (ad Laurentium) de fide spe at caritate ep. Epistulae ep. Jo. In epistulam Joannis (ad Parthos) tractatus c. ep. Man. Contra epistulam Manichaei quam vocant fundamenti ex. Gal. Expositio Epistulae ad Galatas f. et symb. De fide et symbolo c. Faust. Contra Faustum Manicheum c. Fort. Acta contra Fortunatum Manicheum gest. Pel. De gestis Pelagii vii Gn. litt. De Genesi ad litteram Gn. litt. imp. De Genesi ad litteram imperfectus liber Gn. adv. Man. De Genesi adversos Manicheos Jo. ev. tr. In Johannis evangelium tractatus c. Jul. Contra Julianum c. Jul. imp. Contra Julianum opus imperfectum lib. arb. De libero arbitrio mag. De magistro mor. De moribus ecclesiae catholicae at de moribus Manichaeorum mus. De musica nat. b. De natura boni nat. et gr. De natura et gratia ord. De ordine pecc. mer. De peccatorum meritis et remissione et de baptismo parvulorum perf. just. De perfectione justitiae hominis pers. De dono perseverantiae quant. De animae quantitate retr. Retractationes s. Sermones s. Dom. mon. De sermone Domini in monte Simpl. Ad Simplicianum viii sol. Soliloquia spir. et litt. De spiritu et littera Trin. De Trinitate util. jejun. De utilitate jejunii vera rel. De vera religione ix Preface In The Augustinian Revolution in Theology, Thomas Allin writes that Saint Augustine of Hippo “is par excellence a penologist” (1911, 129).1 This statement is not meant as a compliment. The target of Allin’s criticism is Augustine’s conviction that all suffering has its origin in the sin of the sufferer; all suffering is essentially punishment.2 Allin contends that this view is itself evil (24-25) and in this he is not original. Versions of his objection were known to Augustine in his own time and are echoed today. Critics have argued against Augustine’s view on the grounds that it is repugnant (it is a cruel attempt to “blame the victim”); that it is unchristian (a punitive God is not the God of Christianity); or that it is patently untrue (suffering all too obviously bears no correlation to the merits or misdeeds of individuals).3 What they hardly ever ask, however, is what exactly Augustine means by it. This is on one level not surprising. The idea that those who suffer must have brought that suffering on themselves has an ancient and universal lineage.4 For this reason it is perhaps too easy to assume we know what Augustine means when he says that all suffering is a punishment: as the story from Genesis goes, human beings sin and God punishes them (Gn 3). And yet Augustine has much more to say than just this (as indeed, in his view, does scripture): so much more, in fact, that one would expect scholars to engage in some systematic discussion of it. To 1 Allin penned his condemnation of Augustine’s influence on Western theology almost 100 years ago; but since he expresses himself with a useful forthrightness and as his views are by no means passé, I have used his comments to represent a fairly common view that Augustine is obsessed with sin and punishment in a myopic and simplistic way (see note 3). 2 Allin and many critics who share similar views (see note 3) tend to target a composite of views for which Augustine, largely through such criticism, has become notorious. This composite includes original sin, the damnation of children who die unbaptised, and predestination. However, it becomes clear that the underlying claim rejected by critics is his view that those who suffer (which suffering includes damnation) have brought their suffering on themselves through sin. In other words, unlike Augustine they believe there is innocent suffering. Allin himself identifies this root criticism when he characterizes Augustine as a “penologist.” For a similar view see Kirwan 1989, 76-77. 3 A critic of Augustine’s own time was Julian of Eclanum who believed Augustine depicted God as a monster (c. Jul. imp. 1.48). For modern versions particularly of the first view see, for example, Solomon (1999, 125-6); of the second view, Kirwan (1989, 77), Burnaby (1938, 204-206), and Pagels (1988, chaps. 5-6); and of the third view, Schilling (1977, 94) and Burnaby (1938, 206). The tenor of both Allin’s (1911) and N.P. Williams’ (1929) books is that many of Augustine’s most distinctive views are unchristian. More recently Gerald Bonner has commented on Augustine’s “brutality,” although it is not clear whether he does so as a devil’s advocate (2007, 13-19). 4 For an overview of this idea as found in the Judeo-Christian tradition see Schilling 1977, 119-145. x see the complexity of his view (or views), we need only sample a few of his claims on the topic: sin is directly harmful to the physical body; the punishment of sin includes a tendency to sin more; suffering follows sin because sin is inherently self-damaging; suffering is the result of divine punishment; God is not – and cannot be – responsible for the damage caused by sin; the purpose of the punishment of sin is wholly accomplished by our suffering, even though we gain no personal benefit from it; by our suffering God means ultimately to heal us of our suffering.
Recommended publications
  • Liberal Neutrality: a Reinterpretation and Defense*
    Liberal Neutrality: A Reinterpretation and Defense* Alan Patten, Princeton University (1) Introduction After a brief ascendancy in the 1970s and `80s, the idea of liberal neutrality has fallen out of favor in recent years. A growing chorus of liberal writers has joined anti-liberal critics in arguing that there is something confused and misguided about the insistence that the state be neutral between rival conceptions of the good. Assuming we can even make sense of the idea of neutrality, these writers contend, it is a mistake to think that there is anything in liberal principles that commits the liberal state to neutrality.1 With a number of former neutralists softening their support for the idea, the rejection of neutrality is quickly becoming a consensus position, even amongst liberal political philosophers.2 According to one writer, all that remains to be done is an “autopsy” on the idea of state neutrality.3 Much of the critique of neutrality has proceeded on the basis of four assumptions. The first contrasts neutrality with perfectionism. To defend state neutrality is to deny that the state can legitimately use its power to encourage ways of life that it supposes to be valuable or to discourage ones that it regards * Earlier versions of this paper were presented at Washington University, at Queenʼs University, at the Canadian Political Science Associationʼs 2010 Annual Conference , and in a workshop at Princetonʼs University Center for Human Values. In addition to thanking the participants in and organizers of these events, I am grateful to Arash Abizadeh, Andrew Lister, Stephen Macedo, Ian MacMullen, Jonathan Quong, Ryan Pevnick, and Anna Stilz for their written feedback.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Three Separation Theses James Morauta Abstract. Legal Positivism's
    Three Separation Theses James Morauta Abstract . Legal positivism’s “separation thesis” is usually taken in one of two ways: as an analytic claim about the nature of law—roughly, as some version of the Social Thesis ; or as a substantive moral claim about the value of law—roughly, as some version of the No Value Thesis . In this paper I argue that we should recognize a third kind of positivist separation thesis, one which complements, but is distinct from, positivism’s analytic and moral claims. The Neutrality Thesis says that the correct analytic claim about the nature of law does not by itself entail any substantive moral claims about the value of law. I give careful formulations of these three separation theses, explain the relationships between them, and sketch the role that each plays in the positivist approach to law. [A version of this paper is published in Law and Philosophy (2004).] 1. Introduction Everybody knows that legal positivists hold that there is some kind of “separation”— some kind of distinction—between law and morality. But what exactly is this positivist separation thesis ? In what way, according to legal positivism, are law and morality distinct? There are many possible answers to this question. Legal positivism is standardly thought of as a cluster of three kinds of claims: an analytic claim about the nature of law; a moral claim about law’s value; and a linguistic claim about the meaning of the normative terms that appear in legal statements. 1 I won’t have anything to say here about the linguistic issue.
    [Show full text]
  • Akrasia: Plato and the Limits of Education?
    Akrasia: Plato and the Limits of Education? Colm Shanahan Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Dublin, Trinity College Supervisor: Prof. Vasilis Politis Submitted to the University of Dublin, Trinity College, August 2017 Declaration I declare that this thesis has not been submitted as an exercise for a degree at this or any other university and it is entirely my own work. I agree to deposit this thesis in the University’s open access institutional repository or allow the library to do so on my behalf, subject to Irish Copyright Legislation and Trinity College Library conditions of use and acknowledgement. Signed: __________________________ Date:_____________ (Colm Shanahan) Summary In this dissertation, I shall argue for the following main claim: (1a) the motivational neutrality of reason. I will show that this concept reveals that, for Plato, (1b) reason is itself a necessary condition of the possibility of akrasia, and a central explanatory element in his account of akrasia. In presenting the soul with the capacity to take account of the whole soul, the motivational neutrality of reason seems to be the precondition of moving from having such a capacity, in a speculative manner, to generating desires and actions based upon such considerations. If this were not so, then how could the rational part of the soul, for example, put its good to one side, where such is required, to achieve the good of the whole soul? This distancing from the good associated with the rational part of the soul is precisely the grounding upon which the rational part of the soul generates the space to assess the goods of the other soul parts.
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine and the Art of Ruling in the Carolingian Imperial Period
    Augustine and the Art of Ruling in the Carolingian Imperial Period This volume is an investigation of how Augustine was received in the Carolingian period, and the elements of his thought which had an impact on Carolingian ideas of ‘state’, rulership and ethics. It focuses on Alcuin of York and Hincmar of Rheims, authors and political advisers to Charlemagne and to Charles the Bald, respectively. It examines how they used Augustinian political thought and ethics, as manifested in the De civitate Dei, to give more weight to their advice. A comparative approach sheds light on the differences between Charlemagne’s reign and that of his grandson. It scrutinizes Alcuin’s and Hincmar’s discussions of empire, rulership and the moral conduct of political agents during which both drew on the De civitate Dei, although each came away with a different understanding. By means of a philological–historical approach, the book offers a deeper reading and treats the Latin texts as political discourses defined by content and language. Sophia Moesch is currently an SNSF-funded postdoctoral fellow at the University of Oxford, working on a project entitled ‘Developing Principles of Good Govern- ance: Latin and Greek Political Advice during the Carolingian and Macedonian Reforms’. She completed her PhD in History at King’s College London. Augustine and the Art of Ruling in the Carolingian Imperial Period Political Discourse in Alcuin of York and Hincmar of Rheims Sophia Moesch First published 2020 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN and by Routledge 52 Vanderbilt Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business Published with the support of the Swiss National Science Foundation.
    [Show full text]
  • The Seven Deadly Sins Part Four - Sloth & Gluttony
    The Seven Deadly Sins Part Four - Sloth & Gluttony James 1:13-15 God cannot be tempted by evil, nor does he tempt anyone; but each one is tempted when, by his own evil desire, he is dragged away and enticed. Then, after desire has conceived, it gives birth to sin; and sin, when it is full-grown, gives birth to death. 1 Peter 2:24 He himself bore our sins in his body on the tree, so that we might die to sins and live for righteousness… Sloth is a deadly sin that must die! 1 Timothy 5:13 …they get into the habit of being idle and going about from house to house. And not only do they become idlers, but also gossips and busybodies, saying things they ought not to. Ezekiel 16:49 Your sister Sodom's sins were pride, laziness, and too much food, while the poor and needy suffered outside her door. Sloth does not just mean being lazy on the job. Matthew 25:26 “His master replied, ‘You wicked, lazy servant!’” 1 Timothy 5:8 If anyone does not provide for his relatives, and especially for his immediate family, he has denied the faith and is worse than an unbeliever. Sloth puts us in partnership with the devil. Proverbs 18:9 One who is slack in his work is brother to one who destroys. Matthew 12:30 “He who is not with me is against me, and he who does not gather with me scatters.” God considers hard work a virtue. 1 Thessalonians 4:11-12 Make it your ambition to lead a quiet life, to mind your own business and to work with your hands, just as we told you, so that your daily life may win the respect of outsiders and so that you will not be dependent on anybody.
    [Show full text]
  • UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT NORTHERN DISTRICT of INDIANA SOUTH BEND DIVISION in Re FEDEX GROUND PACKAGE SYSTEM, INC., EMPLOYMEN
    USDC IN/ND case 3:05-md-00527-RLM-MGG document 3279 filed 03/22/19 page 1 of 354 UNITED STATES DISTRICT COURT NORTHERN DISTRICT OF INDIANA SOUTH BEND DIVISION ) Case No. 3:05-MD-527 RLM In re FEDEX GROUND PACKAGE ) (MDL 1700) SYSTEM, INC., EMPLOYMENT ) PRACTICES LITIGATION ) ) ) THIS DOCUMENT RELATES TO: ) ) Carlene Craig, et. al. v. FedEx Case No. 3:05-cv-530 RLM ) Ground Package Systems, Inc., ) ) PROPOSED FINAL APPROVAL ORDER This matter came before the Court for hearing on March 11, 2019, to consider final approval of the proposed ERISA Class Action Settlement reached by and between Plaintiffs Leo Rittenhouse, Jeff Bramlage, Lawrence Liable, Kent Whistler, Mike Moore, Keith Berry, Matthew Cook, Heidi Law, Sylvia O’Brien, Neal Bergkamp, and Dominic Lupo1 (collectively, “the Named Plaintiffs”), on behalf of themselves and the Certified Class, and Defendant FedEx Ground Package System, Inc. (“FXG”) (collectively, “the Parties”), the terms of which Settlement are set forth in the Class Action Settlement Agreement (the “Settlement Agreement”) attached as Exhibit A to the Joint Declaration of Co-Lead Counsel in support of Preliminary Approval of the Kansas Class Action 1 Carlene Craig withdrew as a Named Plaintiff on November 29, 2006. See MDL Doc. No. 409. Named Plaintiffs Ronald Perry and Alan Pacheco are not movants for final approval and filed an objection [MDL Doc. Nos. 3251/3261]. USDC IN/ND case 3:05-md-00527-RLM-MGG document 3279 filed 03/22/19 page 2 of 354 Settlement [MDL Doc. No. 3154-1]. Also before the Court is ERISA Plaintiffs’ Unopposed Motion for Attorney’s Fees and for Payment of Service Awards to the Named Plaintiffs, filed with the Court on October 19, 2018 [MDL Doc.
    [Show full text]
  • Life with Augustine
    Life with Augustine ...a course in his spirit and guidance for daily living By Edmond A. Maher ii Life with Augustine © 2002 Augustinian Press Australia Sydney, Australia. Acknowledgements: The author wishes to acknowledge and thank the following people: ► the Augustinian Province of Our Mother of Good Counsel, Australia, for support- ing this project, with special mention of Pat Fahey osa, Kevin Burman osa, Pat Codd osa and Peter Jones osa ► Laurence Mooney osa for assistance in editing ► Michael Morahan osa for formatting this 2nd Edition ► John Coles, Peter Gagan, Dr. Frank McGrath fms (Brisbane CEO), Benet Fonck ofm, Peter Keogh sfo for sharing their vast experience in adult education ► John Rotelle osa, for granting us permission to use his English translation of Tarcisius van Bavel’s work Augustine (full bibliography within) and for his scholarly advice Megan Atkins for her formatting suggestions in the 1st Edition, that have carried over into this the 2nd ► those generous people who have completed the 1st Edition and suggested valuable improvements, especially Kath Neehouse and friends at Villanova College, Brisbane Foreword 1 Dear Participant Saint Augustine of Hippo is a figure in our history who has appealed to the curiosity and imagination of many generations. He is well known for being both sinner and saint, for being a bishop yet also a fellow pilgrim on the journey to God. One of the most popular and attractive persons across many centuries, his influence on the church has continued to our current day. He is also renowned for his influ- ence in philosophy and psychology and even (in an indirect way) art, music and architecture.
    [Show full text]
  • In Defense of the Development of Augustine's Doctrine of Grace By
    In Defense of the Development of Augustine’s Doctrine of Grace by Laban Omondi Agisa Submitted to the faculty of the School of Theology of the University of the South in Partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Sacred Theology January 2020 Sewanee, Tennessee Approved ____________________________ _______________ Adviser Date ____________________________ _______________ Second Adviser Date 2 DECLARATION I declare that this is my original work and has not been presented in any other institution for consideration of any certification. This work has been complemented by sources duly acknowledged and cited using Chicago Manual Style. Signature Date 3 ACKNOWLEDGEMENT My study of theology was initiated in 2009 by the then Provost of St. Stephens Cathedral, Nairobi, the late Ven. Canon John Ndung’u who was a great encouragement to me. This was further made possible through my bishop the Rt. Rev. Joel Waweru and the Rev. Geoffrey Okapisi who were sources of inspiration. My studies at Carlile College (Church Army Africa) and St. Paul’s University laid a strong theological foundation and I appreciate among others the influence of the Rev. Dr. John Kiboi who introduced me to Philosophy, Systematic Theology, Ethics, and African Christian Theology that eventually became the foundation for my studies at the University of the South. I also appreciate the encouragement of my lecturers Mrs. Tabitha Waweru and Dr. Scholarstica Githinji during my Study of Education at Kenya Technical Trainers College and at Daystar University respectively. My interest in this topic came as a result of many sittings with two professors at the University of the South, Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Gluttony William I
    University of Michigan Law School University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository Articles Faculty Scholarship 1997 Gluttony William I. Miller University of Michigan Law School, [email protected] Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/articles/697 Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/articles Part of the Food and Drug Law Commons, Legal History Commons, and the Religion Law Commons Recommended Citation Miller, William I. "Gluttony." Representations 60 (1997): 92-112. This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Articles by an authorized administrator of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. WILLIAM IAN MILLER Gluttony Amongthem all, whocan descry A vicemore mean than Gluttony? Of anygroveling slave ofsense, Notone can claimso smallpretense To thatindulgence which the wise Allowto human frailties As theinglorious, beastly sinner, Whoseonly object is-a dinner. -WWm.Combe 1815' GLUTTONY DOES NOT HAVE THE GRANDEUR OF PRIDE, the often brilliantstrategic meanness of envyand avarice,the gloryof wrath.It does man- age to gain some small allure byits associationwith lust, its sexy siblingsin of the flesh. Yet there is somethingirrevocably unseemly about gluttony,vulgar and lowbrow,self-indulgent in a swinishway. Gluttony is not the stuffof tragedyor epic. Imagine Hamlet too fat to take revenge or Homer making his topic the gluttonyof Achilles rather than his wrath.2With gluttony,compare pride and anger,sins thatmark the grand action of revenge,sins thatcan be emblematized by tigers,lions, eagles, and hawks,rather than by pigs and (dare I say it) humans.
    [Show full text]
  • The Evolution of the Seven Deadly Sins: from God to the Simpsons
    96 Journal of Popular Culture sin. A lot. As early Christian doctrine repeatedly points out, the seven deadly sins are so deeply rooted in our fallen human nature, that not only are they almost completely unavoidable, but like a proverbial bag of The Evolution of the Seven Deadly Sins: potato chips, we can never seem to limit ourselves to just one. With this ideology, modern society agrees. However, with regard to the individual From God to the Simpsons and social effects of the consequences of these sins, we do not. The deadly sins of seven were identified, revised, and revised again Lisa Frank in the heads and classrooms of reportedly celibate monks as moral and philosophical lessons taught in an effort to arm men and women against I can personally attest that the seven deadly sins are still very much the temptations of sin and vice in the battle for their souls. These teach- with us. Today, I have committed each of them, several more than once, ings were quickly reflected in the literature, theater, art, and music of before my lunch hour even began. Here is my schedule of sin (judge me that time and throughout the centuries to follow. Today, they remain pop- if you will): ular motifs in those media, as well as having made the natural progres- sion into film and television. Every day and every hour, acts of gluttony, 7:00 - I pressed the snooze button three times before dragging myself out of lust, covetousness, envy, pride, wrath, and sloth are portrayed on televi- bed.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Law and Modern Jurisprudence Joseph V
    Document généré le 1 oct. 2021 06:45 Laval théologique et philosophique Natural Law and Modern Jurisprudence Joseph V. Dolan Volume 15, numéro 1, 1959 URI : https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1019972ar DOI : https://doi.org/10.7202/1019972ar Aller au sommaire du numéro Éditeur(s) Laval théologique et philosophique, Université Laval ISSN 0023-9054 (imprimé) 1703-8804 (numérique) Découvrir la revue Citer cet article Dolan, J. V. (1959). Natural Law and Modern Jurisprudence. Laval théologique et philosophique, 15(1), 32–63. https://doi.org/10.7202/1019972ar Tous droits réservés © Laval théologique et philosophique, Université Laval, Ce document est protégé par la loi sur le droit d’auteur. L’utilisation des 1959 services d’Érudit (y compris la reproduction) est assujettie à sa politique d’utilisation que vous pouvez consulter en ligne. https://apropos.erudit.org/fr/usagers/politique-dutilisation/ Cet article est diffusé et préservé par Érudit. Érudit est un consortium interuniversitaire sans but lucratif composé de l’Université de Montréal, l’Université Laval et l’Université du Québec à Montréal. Il a pour mission la promotion et la valorisation de la recherche. https://www.erudit.org/fr/ Natural Law and Modern Jurisprudence I. LAW AND THE FORMATION OF THE CITIZEN 1. The influence of the community It is almost with surprise that we remark in theEthics, where Aristotle is preparing his transition to thePolitics, the important and even critical role he assigns to law in the formation of virtue.1 It is our habit to think of law as occupied with ends more immediate and pedestrian like monitoring traffic, taxing our cigarettes, and suppressing violence.
    [Show full text]
  • ABSTRACT the Conversion and Therapy of Desire in Augustine's
    ABSTRACT The Conversion and Therapy of Desire in Augustine’s Cassiciacum Dialogues Mark J. Boone, Ph.D. Directors: Thomas S. Hibbs, Ph.D., and Michael P. Foley, Ph.D. The philosophical schools of late antiquity commonly diagnosed human unhappiness as rooted in some fundamental disorder in our desires, and offered various therapies or prescriptions for the healing of desire. Among these only the neo-Platonic treatment for desire requires redirecting desire towards an immaterial world. Although Augustine agrees with the neo-Platonists on the need to redirect our desires to an immaterial world, he does not adopt their therapy for desire. Instead he adopts a thoroughly Christian approach to the healing of desire. The conversion of desire results from the Trinitarian God’s gracious actions taken to heal our desires. Augustine does not recommend fleeing from the influence of the body, as neo-Platonism encourages, but fleeing to Christ, immersing ourselves in the life of the Church, and practicing the theological virtues. In this dissertation I examine Augustine’s Cassiciacum dialogues. In Contra Academicos (Against the Academics), Augustine argues that we must vigorously desire wisdom in order to attain it; that we must have hope in the possibility of attaining wisdom; and that our desire for wisdom must be bound in faith to Christ. In De beata vita (On the Happy Life), Augustine argues that the Trinitarian God is the only perennially satisfying object of desire and shows that the pursuit of God is the activity of a prayerful community of believers who are practicing faith, hope, and charity. In De ordine (On Order), Augustine recommends that the reordering of our desires be pursued through a liberal arts education and through Christian morals.
    [Show full text]