Goals of This Course (1) Nativism Vs. Empiricism Behaviourism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Goals of This Course (1) Nativism Vs. Empiricism Behaviourism 1/15/16 Goals of this course (1) Nativism, Empiricism, Representation, and Domain-specificity Examine the Big Questions of cognitive science through the lens of computational modelling. • Is cognition a collection of separate domain-specific abilities or an interacting whole? Topics in Cognitive Modelling • How much of cognition is innate? Jan. 15, 2016 • Are mental representations symbolic or distributed? • Are mental processes based on rules or associations? John Lee, Chris Lucas • To what extent are our cognitive abilities determined by our School of Informatics physical body and environment (i.e., grounded/embodied)? University of Edinburgh 2 Nativism vs. empiricism Behaviourism Nativism: much of humans’ cognitive ability is inborn. • Dominant view in psychology from • (cf. Leibniz, Kant, Chomsky, Pinker) 1920s-1950s. • Only study observable behaviour, not unobservable mental representations, Empiricism: our cognitive abilities are the result of states and processes. learning from experience. • All behaviour results from learned • (cf. Locke, Hume, Skinner) associations (stimulus-response). We’ll discuss modern points of view on both sides, and ideas about representation and domain-specificity that typically go along with these views. 3 4 Image: life.com Behaviourism Problems with behaviourism • Dominant view in psychology from • What happens in moments of 1920s-1950s. “insight”? • Only study observable behaviour, not • Ex: Chimps figuring out how to get unobservable mental representations, out-of-reach bananas (Kohler, 1927). states and processes. • All behaviour results from learned associations (stimulus-response). • A highly empiricist view: eschews “human nature”, believes social environment is key. 5 6 Image: retrobookshop.co m Image: Kohler (1927). 1 1/15/16 Problems with behaviourism Problems with behaviourism • What makes humans different from other animals • How can learning even happen if nothing exists first? and why do human universals exist across cultures? “Nothing exists in the intellect that was not first in the • Partial list of cultural universals compiled by D. E. Brown:* senses.” – Locke* aesthetics; age statuses, terms; anthropomorphization; baby “Except the intellect itself.” – Leibniz* talk ; belief in s uper natur al/r eligion; beliefs about death, for tune and mis for tune; body ador nment; c hildbir th c us toms ; childhood fear of loud noises; classification of age, body parts, colors, fauna, flora, kin, sex, tools, weather conditions; • The bias-variance dilemma in statistical machine collective identities; conflict; coyness display; crying; learning is a more formal statement of this problem. culture/nature distinction; customary greetings; dance; death rituals; diurnality; divination; … 7 8 *As quoted in Pinker (2002). *As quoted in Pinker (2002). The cognitive revolution Nativism in linguistics • Chomsky (1959) attacks Skinner’s book Verbal • Chomsky’s “argument from the poverty of the stimulus”: Behavior. children’s grammatical knowledge is too complex to be learned from the input they receive. • Children do not, e.g., utter “house” every time they see one: language use is stimulus-independ ent. • Ex. Hierarchical structure vs. linear structure in Y-N questions. • Language is infinite; children produce sentences they have I am going. The dog is cute. Hyp: to form Y-N question, move never heard, apparently following complex grammatical rules Am I going? Is the dog c ute? aux. verb to front. (i.e., internal knowledge). • The start of the “cognitive revolution”: the study of the internal mind. • Additionally, Chomsky argues that much grammatical knowledge is innate. 9 10 Nativism in linguistics Nativism in linguistics • Chomsky’s “argument from the poverty of the stimulus”: Chomsky argues: children’s grammatical knowledge is too complex to be • Wrong answer involves linear structure (move the 1st aux). learned from the input they receive. The man who is going is here. • Ex. Hierarchical structure vs. linear structure in Y-N questions. Is the man w ho going is here? I am going. The dog is cute. Hyp: to form Y-N question, move Am I going? Is the dog c ute? aux. verb to front. • Correct answer involves knowing that sentences have hierarchical structure (move the aux in the main clause). [[The [man [w ho [is going]]]] [is here]]. The man who is going is here. Which aux. verb to move? • This type of sentence is not common enough for children to have Is the man w ho going is here? heard it, yet they do not make errors.* or • Therefore, knowledge of hierarchical structure and relevance of main Is the man w ho is going here? clause must be innate. 11 12 *Both of these points have been disputed more recently. 2 1/15/16 Theoretical assumptions What is in UG? In LAD? • A set of strong constraints on the possible forms that Basic idea: All languages follow certain principles, with languages can take (Universal Grammar). UG is certain parameters of variation. • Domain specific (e.g., refers to linguistic notions like nouns and Pr inc iple A: verbs, plus much more technical ones) A reflexive pronoun must have a higher antecedent in some domain. • Represented using symbols and deterministic rules. The domain parameter: Option (a): domain = the smallest clause containing the reflexive pronoun. Option (b): domain = the sentence containing the reflexive pronoun. • An associated learning system (Language Acquisition Device) that works with UG to allow acquisition of particular languages. Reflexive pronoun: himself, herself, etc. 13 Antec edent: the thing the pr onoun r efer s to. 14 What is in UG? In LAD? Nativism in other domains Basic idea: All languages follow certain principles, with Spelke (1994) presents a nativist view of development certain parameters of variation. in other domains. Pr inc iple A: A reflexive pronoun must have a higher antecedent in some domain. Claims that “core knowledge” of physics, psychology, The domain parameter: number, and geometry is innate. Option (a): domain = the smallest clause containing the reflexive pronoun. Option (b): domain = the sentence containing the reflexive pronoun. •E.g., Contact principle for physics: an object can only affect the motion of another object through contact. Parameters are set based on observed input data. Domain-specific: does not apply to animals. Various specific algorithms have been proposed, often based on “cues” or “triggers”, specific types of sentences that indicate specific parameter settings. 15 16 Infant knowledge of physical laws Infant knowledge of physical laws An experiment: • If a principle is innate, very young children should be surprised by seeing it violated. • Looking-time studies: 1. Habituate (bore) children with one display. Habituation Superficially different Violates principle 2. Compare time they look at two new displays: a. Violates principle but looks similar. b. Obeys principle but superficially different. 17 18 Image: Spelke, 1994 3 1/15/16 Infant knowledge of physical laws Spelke’s nativism: Results: Similar assumptions to Chomsky: •Infants look longer at violations of continuity than • Innate knowledge is domain-specific. violations of inertia (objects changing paths) • E.g., law of contact refers only to physics of objects. • Innate knowledge is about fundamental properties of the •At the same time, infants reach predictively in world that are not necessarily perceptually salient or even accordance with inertia. possible to perceive. Spelke’s interpretation: Similar arguments to Chomsky: •Innate knowledge of continuity principle. • Sophisticated early knowledge without much experience indicates innateness: “it just wouldn’t be possible to learn X based on the input received.” 19 20 Summing up Connectionism Strongly nativist researchers assume • A new incarnation of empiricism, stemming from AI • Many basic cognitive functions (perception, reasoning, research in the late 70s/early 80s. language, etc.) rely largely on innate knowledge. • The beginning of the “statistical revolution” in machine • This knowledge is domain-specific, generally using symbolic learning, moving from rule-based to statistical algorithms. representations. • Artificial neural networks show promise as robust and • Learning processes are also domain-specific, though many successful method for learning from data. nativists don’t actually say much about learning, focusing • In machine learning, research on ANNs and their more on what is not learned. descendants continues as a practical technique. • Sometimes assume strong modularity: different parts of the • In cognitive science, use of ANNs is typically part of a brain are responsible for different functions, and internal philosophical view: connectionism. workings of modules are opaque to each other. 21 22 Rethinking Innateness (Elman et al., 1996) Artificial neural networks • Elman et al.’s “biologically inspired” • ANNs reproduce what Elman et al. believe to be the empiricism: critical aspects of neural structure: • Learning mechanisms and experience are • Distributed computation using small computational elements. more powerful than nativists believe. • Each element accesses only local information. • Hardware implementation (i.e., neural • Information is represented in a distributed way. structure) is critical. • Responses are nonlinear. • Evolutionary origins and environment are also important. 23 24 Image: entwicklungswissenschaft. de Figure: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Artificial_neural_network 4 1/15/16 What is “innate”? What is innate? • Elman et al.: “innate” as resulting from
Recommended publications
  • Literature and the Cognitive Revolution: an Introduction
    Literature and the Cognitive Revolution: An Introduction Alan Richardson English, Boston College Francis F. Steen Communication Studies, UCLA Literary studies and the cognitive sciences, pursuing common interests in language, mental acts, and linguistic artifacts, have developed markedly different approaches to similar phenomena of reading, imaginative involve- ment, and textual patterning. Until quite recently, the distance between them has drawn more attention than their possible convergence (Franchi and Güzeldere ). A number of literary theorists and critics, however, have steadily been producing work that finds its inspiration, its method- ology, and its guiding paradigms through a dialogue with one or more fields within cognitive science: artificial intelligence, cognitive psychology, post- Chomskian linguistics, philosophy of mind, neuroscience, and evolution- ary biology. Reuven Tsur () has been developing his ‘‘cognitive poet- ics’’ since the s; the prominent psychoanalytic critic Norman Holland (: ) demonstrated the advantages of attending to the ‘‘more powerful psychology’’ emerging from cognitive neuroscience in ; Mark Turner (: viii) advanced his far-reaching project of a ‘‘cognitive rhetoric’’ in ; and Ellen Spolsky (: ) trenchantly brought a theory of ‘‘cogni- tive instability’’ to bear on literary interpretation in . These and like- minded critics respond to the limitations (or, in Spolsky’s case, missed op- portunities) of poststructuralist conceptions of meaning and interpretation by questioning the reigning models in the field, whether in the interest of Poetics Today : (Spring ). Copyright © by the Porter Institute for Poetics and Semiotics. Downloaded from http://read.dukeupress.edu/poetics-today/article-pdf/23/1/1/458295/01.pdf by guest on 25 September 2021 2 Poetics Today 23:1 displacing, reworking, supplementing, or fundamentally regrounding them (Hart ).
    [Show full text]
  • Anthropology's Disenchantment with the Cognitive Revolution
    Topics in Cognitive Science 4 (2012) 354–361 Copyright Ó 2012 Cognitive Science Society, Inc. All rights reserved. ISSN: 1756-8757 print / 1756-8765 online DOI: 10.1111/j.1756-8765.2012.01199.x Anthropology’s Disenchantment With the Cognitive Revolution1 Richard A. Shweder Department of Comparative Human Development, University of Chicago Received 25 June 2011; received in revised form 3 November 2011; accepted 28 November 2011 Abstract Beller, Bender, and Medin should be congratulated for their generous attempt at expressive aca- demic therapy for troubled interdisciplinary relationships. In this essay, I suggest that a negative answer to the central question (‘‘Should anthropology be part of cognitive science?’’) is not necessar- ily distressing, that in retrospect the breakup seems fairly predictable, and that disenchantment with the cognitive revolution is nothing new. Keywords: Cognitive revolution; Behaviorism; Anthropology; Jerome Bruner; Roy D’Andrade; Clifford Geertz; Roger Shepard Some of the leaders of the cognitive revolution of the late 1950s and 1960s began parting from the cause almost as soon as it triumphed. Jerome Bruner, for example, who always enjoyed writing essays for both the left hand and the right hand, turned to hermeneutics, the study of law, and the interpretation of narratives (see Bruner, 1979, 1990). Even in the early days of the rebellion Bruner was attentive to language pragmatics, which may be one reason he named his 1960s big tent interdisciplinary center at Harvard University the ‘‘Center for Cognitive Studies’’ and not the ‘‘Center for Cognitive Science.’’ Bruner had just as much interest in the humanistic writings of E. H. Gombrich, Nelson Goodman, and Clifford Ge- ertz as in the latest claims about basic ⁄fundamental⁄universal cognitive processes coming out of experimental labs situated in Cambridge, London, or Geneva.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cognitive Revolution: a Historical Perspective
    Review TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences Vol.7 No.3 March 2003 141 The cognitive revolution: a historical perspective George A. Miller Department of Psychology, Princeton University, 1-S-5 Green Hall, Princeton, NJ 08544, USA Cognitive science is a child of the 1950s, the product of the time I went to graduate school at Harvard in the early a time when psychology, anthropology and linguistics 1940s the transformation was complete. I was educated to were redefining themselves and computer science and study behavior and I learned to translate my ideas into the neuroscience as disciplines were coming into existence. new jargon of behaviorism. As I was most interested in Psychology could not participate in the cognitive speech and hearing, the translation sometimes became revolution until it had freed itself from behaviorism, tricky. But one’s reputation as a scientist could depend on thus restoring cognition to scientific respectability. By how well the trick was played. then, it was becoming clear in several disciplines that In 1951, I published Language and Communication [1], the solution to some of their problems depended cru- a book that grew out of four years of teaching a course at cially on solving problems traditionally allocated to Harvard entitled ‘The Psychology of Language’. In the other disciplines. Collaboration was called for: this is a preface, I wrote: ‘The bias is behavioristic – not fanatically personal account of how it came about. behavioristic, but certainly tainted by a preference. There does not seem to be a more scientific kind of bias, or, if there is, it turns out to be behaviorism after all.’ As I read that Anybody can make history.
    [Show full text]
  • Empiricism, Cognitive Science, and the Novel
    Empiricism, Cognitive Science, and the Novel Jonathan Kramnick Rutgers University “I see into minds, you see,” the robot continued, “and you have no idea how complicated they are. I can’t begin to understand everything because my own mind has so little in common with them—but I try, and your novels help.” —Isaac Asimov, Liar! No one literary form has a proprietary stake in the mind, but as genres go the novel has since its inception taken remarkable interest in mental states. Among other things, eighteenth-century fiction is so much writing about the mind: about how thoughts represent things, cause other thoughts to happen, or lead to actions. The same might be said for empiricism. Seventeenth- and eighteenth-century philosophy paid unusual attention to the content of minds and the nature of ideas, to “human understanding” as Locke and Hume put it. While the connection between empiricism and the rise of the novel is a touch- stone of literary studies, with a venerable tradition of scholarship dating back to the beginnings of the profession, only recently have critics drawn upon phi- losophy of mind and cognitive science to talk about the way in which thinking takes shape in particular works from the period.1 This is of course not so much of a surprise, since criticism is as a rule skeptical of framing older texts with present-day models. The risk is one of anachronism or universalism, either shoehorning recalcitrant descriptions of the mind into our current language of cognition or locating both within a timeless and unchanging account of the psyche.
    [Show full text]
  • Situated Cognition
    Roth, W.-M., & Jornet, A. G. (2013). Situated cognition. WIREs Cognitive Science, 4, xxx–xxx. doi: 10.1002/wcs.1242 Article type: Overview Article title: Situated cognition First author: Full name and affiliation; plus email address if corresponding author Wolff-Michael Roth*, University of Victoria, Victoria, BC, V8W 3N4, Canada [email protected] Second author: Full name and affiliation; plus email address if corresponding author Alfredo Jornet, InterMedia, University of Oslo, 0318 Oslo, Norway Abstract Following the cognitive revolution, when knowing and learning have come to be theorized in terms of representations stored and processed in the mind, empirical and theoretical developments in very different scholarly disciplines have led to the emergence of the situated cognition hypothesis, which consists of a set of interlocking theses: cognition is embodied, fundamentally social, distributed, enacted, and often works without representations. We trace the historical origins of this hypothesis and discuss the evidential support this hypothesis receives from empirical and modeling studies. We distinguish the question of where cognition is located from the question of what cognition is, because the confounding of the two questions leads to misunderstandings in the sometimes-ardent debates concerning the situated cognition hypothesis. We conclude with recommendations for interdisciplinary approaches to the nature of cognition. At the end of the 1980s, just about at the time when the cognitive revolution—based on information processing and the mind as computer metaphor—had become the dominant approach to cognition and learning, a new way of theorizing human performance emerged: situated cognition. There are claims that situated cognition view has grown rapidly over the past decade, including in the areas of cognitive and social neuroscience and (cognitive, social, and developmental) psychology.1 Such claims are substantiated by citation counts.
    [Show full text]
  • Consciousness Is a Thing, Not a Process
    applied sciences Opinion Consciousness Is a Thing, Not a Process Susan Pockett School of Psychology, University of Auckland, Auckland, New Zealand; [email protected] Received: 30 October 2017; Accepted: 23 November 2017; Published: 2 December 2017 Featured Application: If the theory outlined here is correct, the construction of artificial consciousness will certainly be possible, but a fundamentally different approach from that currently used in work on artificial intelligence will be necessary. Abstract: The central dogma of cognitive psychology is ‘consciousness is a process, not a thing’. Hence, the main task of cognitive neuroscientists is generally seen as working out what kinds of neural processing are conscious and what kinds are not. I argue here that the central dogma is simply wrong. All neural processing is unconscious. The illusion that some of it is conscious results largely from a failure to separate consciousness per se from a number of unconscious processes that normally accompany it—most particularly focal attention. Conscious sensory experiences are not processes at all. They are things: specifically, spatial electromagnetic (EM) patterns, which are presently generated only by ongoing unconscious processing at certain times and places in the mammalian brain, but which in principle could be generated by hardware rather than wetware. The neurophysiological mechanisms by which putatively conscious EM patterns are generated, the features that may distinguish conscious from unconscious patterns, the general principles that distinguish the conscious patterns of different sensory modalities and the general features that distinguish the conscious patterns of different experiences within any given sensory modality are all described. Suggestions for further development of this paradigm are provided.
    [Show full text]
  • Language and Cognition Catherine L Harris, Boston University, Massachusetts, USA
    Galley: Article - 00559 Level 1 Language and Cognition Catherine L Harris, Boston University, Massachusetts, USA CONTENTS Introduction Cognitive linguistics Concepts of cognition and language The Cognitive neuroscience movement Connectionism Conclusion Cognitive scientists have long debated whether lan- The second way ofconceptualizing human cog- 0559.003 guage and cognition are separate mental faculties, nition emphasizes the differences between lan- or whether language emerges from general cogni- guage and other abilities. A key idea is that many tive abilities. distinct domains ofcognition exist and must be learned separately, using different mental mechan- INTRODUCTION isms. This approach is referred to as the `modular- ity ofcognition' or `mental modules' approach. At 0559.001 What is the relationship between language and first glance it may seem contrary to the interdiscip- cognition? Do people who speak different lan- linary spirit ofcognitive science and to the possibil- guages think differently? Is a certain level of ity ofa unified theory ofcognition. However, the cognitive development required for language ac- unifying theory is the thesis of distinct mental quisition? These questions were ofkeen interest to modules, which are believed to have evolved to thinkers in the early twentieth century and remain accomplish specific tasks relevant to mammalian important in anthropology, linguistics and psych- evolution, such as visual exploration, or relevant ology. However, the cognitive revolution ofthe to human evolution, such as language use. Much of 1950s brought a new question about the relation- the appeal of this approach comes from findings in ship between language and cognition: is language neuropsychology showing that distinct areas ofthe the same type ofmental entity as other cognitive brain serve distinct functions such as vision, lan- abilities, or is it fundamentally different? guage processing, motor coordination, memory, 0559.002 A hallmark ofmodern cognitive science is the and face recognition.
    [Show full text]
  • Cognitive Science: an Introduction to the Study of Mind
    FM-Friedenberg-4747.qxd 8/22/2005 10:17 AM Page i COGNITIVE SCIENCE FM-Friedenberg-4747.qxd 8/22/2005 10:17 AM Page ii FM-Friedenberg-4747.qxd 8/22/2005 10:17 AM Page iii COGNITIVE SCIENCE An Introduction to the Study of Mind Jay Friedenberg Manhattan College Gordon Silverman Manhattan College FM-Friedenberg-4747.qxd 8/22/2005 10:17 AM Page iv Copyright © 2006 by Sage Publications, Inc. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or utilized in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. For information: Sage Publications, Inc. 2455 Teller Road Thousand Oaks, California 91320 E-mail: [email protected] Sage Publications Ltd. 1 Oliver’s Yard 55 City Road London EC1Y 1SP United Kingdom Sage Publications India Pvt. Ltd. B-42, Panchsheel Enclave Post Box 4109 New Delhi 110 017 India Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Friedenberg, Jay. Cognitive science : an introduction to the study of mind / Jay Friedenberg, Gordon Silverman. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and indexes. ISBN 1-4129-2568-1 (pbk.) 1. Cognitive science—Textbooks. I. Silverman, Gordon. II. Title. BF311.F743 2006 153—dc22 2005009522 050607080910987654321 Acquiring Editor: Jim Brace-Thompson Associate Editor: Margo Beth Crouppen Production Editor: Sanford Robinson Editorial Assistant: Karen Ehrmann Typesetter: C&M Digitals (P) Ltd. Indexer: Jeanne Busemeyer Cover Designer: Janet Foulger FM-Friedenberg-4747.qxd 8/22/2005 10:17 AM Page v Contents Preface xv Acknowledgments xxiii 1.
    [Show full text]
  • The Cognitive Revolution in 1981 Dr
    APPENDIX ONE The Cognitive Revolution In 1981 Dr. Roger Sperry of Caltech won a Nobel Prize for his pioneering work on understanding the organization of the brain. Since it was Sperry's work that led to the insights we have been exploring in this book, a review of his fascinating split-brain experiments is in order. The brains of all mammals are divided into two dis­ tinctly separate halves, or hemispheres, which are con­ nected only by a narrow band of nerves called the corpus callosum. Each half of the brain is directly connected only to the nerves and muscles on the opposite side of the body. The optic nerve connections to the retina of the eye are likewise crossed so that the right half of the brain sees only the left side of the visual field 1 and vice versa. This sepa­ ration of control has a survival value because during a battle you have two independent channels at work: Threats from the right can be dealt with by the left brain while at the same time the right brain handles threats from the left. 257 258 APPENDIX ONE THE SPLIT-BRAIN EXPERIMENTS Back in the 1950s, Dr. Sperry began doing animal experiments to discover how the two halves of the brain interact. These experiments ultimately led to his being awarded the Nobel prize. He found that when the two hemispheres of a cat's or monkey's brain were surgically separated, the animals remained remarkably normal. Sperry created an apparatus for separately communicating with each half of the animal's brain by briefly flashing images to their left or right visual field.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction Fundamentals of Cognitive Psychology
    Mark Van Selst San Jose State University COGNITION Chapter 1: Introduction Fundamentals of Cognitive Psychology (Kellogg) Fall 2013 Psychology 135, Cognition Section 3, Fall 2013 Instructor: Mark Van Selst Telephone: 408 924 5674 Email: [email protected] Web: http://www.sjsu.edu/people/mark.vanselst (sjsu.edu Psychology Faculty Van Selst …) Class Days/Time: Monday and Wednesday 9:00 – 10:15 PM Classroom: DMH 359 Office Hours: Monday and Wednesday 10:30 – 11:45 Office Location: DMH 314 (“Jump the Advising Line”) (also advising Tuesday 10-12 and 2-4 so will be around) Prerequisites: PSYC 1 (General Psychology) Class ID Number: 42693 What is COGNITION ? … and where have you seen the term outside of this class? Syllabus (Green Sheet) Course Scope: an INTRODUCTION to the general topic of "how people think" (this course is an overview of a broad range of topics) Memory: The mental processes of acquiring and retaining information for later retrieval, and the mental storage system in which these processes operate. Cognition: The collection of mental processes and activities used in perceiving, learning, remembering, thinking, and understanding, and the act of using those processes. More Definitions of Cognition Cognition: (People Think) • cognito = "to know" • co = "together" • gnoscere = "know“ • The collection of mental processes and activities used in perceiving, learning, remembering, thinking, understanding, and the act of using those processes. • The study of how people perceive, learn, remember, and think about information. Catalog Description and Required Text Course Description • The activity of knowing: acquisition, organization and use of knowledge. Processes involved in that activity, including perception, memory, thinking, and language.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding the 'Cognitive Revolution' in Psychology
    See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/229735544 Understanding the ‘Cognitive Revolution’ in Psychology Article in Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences · April 1999 DOI: 10.1002/(SICI)1520-6696(199924)35:1<1::AID-JHBS1>3.0.CO;2-4 CITATIONS READS 53 890 1 author: John D Greenwood CUNY Graduate Center 57 PUBLICATIONS 469 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE All content following this page was uploaded by John D Greenwood on 27 January 2016. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file. JHBSÐWILEY RIGHT INTERACTIVE Top of ID Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, Vol. 35(1), 1±22 Winter 1999 ᭧ 1999 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. CCC 0022-5061/99/010001-22 UNDERSTANDING THE ªCOGNITIVE REVOLUTIONº IN PSYCHOLOGY Base of 1st line of ART JOHN D. GREENWOOD In this paper it is argued that the ªcognitive revolutionº in psychology is not best repre- sented either as a Kuhnian ªparadigm shift,º or as a movement from an instrumentalist to a realist conception of psychological theory, or as a continuous evolution out of more ªliberalizedº forms of behaviorism, or as a return to the form of ªstructuralistº psychology practiced by Wundt and Titchener. It is suggested that the move from behaviorism to cognitivism is best represented in terms of the replacement of (operationally de®ned) ªintervening variablesº by genuine ªhypothetical constructsº possessing cognitive ªsurplus meaning,º and that the ªcognitive revolutionº of the 1950s continued a cognitive tradition that can be traced back to the 1920s. ᭧ 1999 John Wiley & Sons, Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • The Philosophy and History of Cognitive Science. Description
    Proposed Syllabus: The philosophy and history of cognitive science. Description: This is a ten week upper-division survey course in the history and philosophy of cognitive science. The goals of this course are to develop a basic understanding of the history of cognitive science and to engage philosophically with some of the main debates and concepts that have characterized the feld. We will discuss, among other topics, behaviorism, functionalism, computation, levels of analysis, mental representation, connectionism and symbolic systems approaches, modularity and domain specifcity, nativism and empiricism, perceptual experience and consciousness. Some background in cognitive science and or the philosophy of mind will be very helpful, but is not necessary so long as students are motivated and work hard. Schedule: The course schedule is divided into two units. The frst unit covers some of the intellectual history behind the rise of cognitive science as well as some concepts which are at the foundation to the discipline. The second unit covers some main theoretical disputes and issues that have characterized the feld. Within each unit the readings are set out for each week. We will do our best to stick to this schedule but some adjustments will most likely be necessary. I will keep you apprised of any needed adjustments as we go along. Unit 1: Foundations. Week 1: Behaviorism in philosophy and psychology. -Descartes, selections from 'Meditations on First Philosophy'. -Ryle, selections from 'Concept of Mind'. -Watson, 'Psychology as the Behaviorist View It'. Week 2: Resistance to Behaviorism and the ‘cognitive revolution’. -Chomsky, review of Skinner’s ‘Verbal Behavior’. -Tollman, 'Cognitive Maps in Mice and Men'.
    [Show full text]