The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE THE: NICOMACHEAN ETHICS OF ARISTOTLE TRASSLA'FED BY F. H. PETERS, M.A. FKLLOW OF UKlV&BLIIR OLLKQK, OXFORD FIFTH EDITION crad adapted Lo Bywater a 7.1. LONDON XEGAN PAUL, TBENOH, TBUBNER k UO., Lk 1893 PREFACE TO THE FIFTH EDITION. MANYmore or less important alterations have been made in this translation, which was first published in 1881, new editions have from time to time been called for. The present edition in particular has been revised throughout, and brought into accordance with Bywater’s text (Oxford, ISSO),’ which is coming to be recognized, not in Oxford only, aa the received text of the Nicomachean Ethics. I wish gratefully to acknowledge the debt which, in common with all lovers of Aristotle, I owe to Mr, Bywater, both for his edition and for his “Contributions to the Textual Criticism of the Nicomachean Ethics ” (Oxford, 1892). To Mr. Stewart also I wish to express my grati- tude, not only for much assistance derived from his admirable “ Notes on the Nicomachean Ethics ” (Oxford, l892), but also for much kindly and helpful criticism in that work and in a review of my first edition (Mind,July, 1881). My old friends Mr. In the few paseagee where this text is not followed, the reading adopted is indicated in a note. vi PREFACE. A. C. Bradley and Mr. J. Cook Wilson (Professors now at Glasgow and Oxford respectively) will allow me to repeat my thanks for the valuable help they gave me when the first edition was passing through the press. To Mr. F. H. Hall of Oriel, and Mr. L. A. Selby Bigge of my own College, I am indebted for some corrections in a subsequent edition. To other translators and commentators I am aIso under inany obligations, which I can only acknowledge in general terms. When I have inserted in the text explanatory words of my own, I have enclosed them in square brackets thus [ 3. A short Index of leading terms and proper names has been added to this edition (in preparing which I have found Mr. Bywater’s Index of the greatest service). This Index makes no pre tension to completeness or anything approaching to completeness (except in regard to proper names). Its aim is merely, in conjunction with the Table of Contents, to help the reader to find the more im- portant passages bearing on the questions in which he may be specially interested. F. H. PETERS. OXFOSU, May, 1893. CONSPECTUS. __3c BOOK Of the good or the end ............ I. Of moral virtue in general ......... 11. Of the mill ............... 111. 1-5. Of the several moral virtues and vices ... 111. 6-enrl of v- Of the intellectual virtues ......... i-1. Of forms of moral character other than virtue or vice ............... VII. 1-10. First account of pleasure ......... VII. 11-cad. Of friendship or love ............ VIII. and IX Second account of pleasure ......... X. 1-5. Conclusion ”. ............ X. 6-end. TABLE OF CONTENTS. -.9c- BOOK L THE ENU. CAIP. PAGl 1. In all he doee man seeks some good aa end or means ... 1 2. Tire end is the good; our subject is this and its scionce, Politics ..................... 2 3. Exactness nor permitted by subject, nor to be expected by student, who needs experience and trniniiig ...... 3 4. Men agree that the good is happiness, but differ as to what this is. We must rmufrom facta accepted without question by the man of trained character ...... 5 6. The pod cannot be pleasure, aa some hold, nor honour, nor virtue ..................... 6 6. Various arguments to show against the Platnni4s that there cunnot be one universe1 gd: even if there were it would not help UB here ............... 8 7. The good is the final end, and happineae is thia To find it we wk, What is man’s funotion 7 Besolting definition of happineaa ..................... 12 8. Thie view harmonizes various current views ...... 18 9. la happiness acquired, or the gift of Gode or chance? ... 22 10. Cannomanbecnlledhnppyduringliie? ......... 23 11. Cannot the fortmea of aurvivora affect the dead 7 ...... 27 12. Happiness BB absolute end ia above praise ......... 28 13. Division of the faculties and resulting division of the virtucs 30 X TABLE OF CONTENTS. BOOK IL NORAL VIRTUE. CHAP. PACE 1. Moral virtne ia acquired by the repetition OF the corre- sponding acta .................. 34 3. These acts must be such as reaeon prescribes : they cannot be defined exactly. but must be neither too much nor too little ..................... 56 3. Virtue is in various way8 concerned with pleasure and pain ........................ 38 4. The conditions of virtuons action &B distinct from artistic production ..................... 41 5. Virtue not an emotion, nor u faculty, but a trained faculty or habit ..................... 42 6. Viz. the habit OF choosing the mean ............ 43 7. This must he applied to the several virtues ......... 48 8. The two vicious estremes are opposed to one another and to the intermediate virtne ............... 52 8. The mean is hard to hit, and is a mntter of perception not ofreasoning ..................... 55 CIUETEBS 1-6. THE WILL 1. An act is involuntary when done (a) under compulsion, or (b) through ignorance : (a)means not originated by doer, (b) means through ignorance of the circumstances: voluntary, then, means originated with knowledge of cimumstancee .................. 58 2. Purpose, a mode of will, means choice after deliberation ... 66 . 3. We deliberate on whst we can do-not on ends, but means 68 . 4. We wish for the end, the real or apparent good ...... 72 . 6. Virtue and vice are dike voluntary :our acts are oar own ; for we are punished for them : ignomnce is no excuee when dne to negliligence :if this be our chemcter, we have made it by repeated acta : even bodily vices are blelu- able when thus formed. We cannot plend that our TABLE OF CONTENTS. xi CRAF. PAQZ notion of good depends on our nature: for (1) vice would still be as voluntary ria virtue. (2) we help to make our- selves what we are .................. 74 CHAPTERS6-12 . THE SEVERAL MORAL VIRTUES AND VICES . 6 . Of courage and the opposite vices ............ 80 7. Of coursg+mi!inued .................. 82 8. Of murage improperly EO called ............ 85 Q . How courage involves both pain and pleasure ...... 89 10. Of temperance ..................... 91 11. Of temperance-continual ............... 93 12. Eow profiigaey ia more voluntary than cowardice ...... 96 BOOK IV . THE GAME.Gnlisued . 1. bf liberality ............ ... ... ... 99 2. Of magnibence ............ ... ... ... 108 3 . Of high-mindednesa ......... ... ... ... 113 4 . Of a similar virtue in smaller matters ... ... ... 120 5. Of gentleneaa ............ ... ... ... 122 6 . Of agreeableness ......... ... ... ... 125 7 . Of truthfulness ............ ... ... ... 127 8 . Of wittiness ............ ... ... ... 131 9 . Of the feeling of ahame ...... ... ... ... 133 BOOK V . THE BAME-Concluded . JUSTICE. 1. Preliminary. Two sew of justice distinguished. of juatioe (1) = obedienm to hw. = oomplete virtue ... 136 8 . Of judice (2) = fairneq how related to jaetioe (1). "hat ia just in distribution dietinpished from whet i~ just in correction ..................140 xii TABLE OF CONTENTS. CAAP. PAGE 3. Of what is just in distribution, and ita role of geometrical propor tion ..................... 144 4. Of what is just incorrection, and ita rule of arithmetical propor tion ..................... 147 6. Saple requital M not identical with what is just, but pro- portionate requital is what is just in exchauge: and thia is effected by means of money. We can now give a general definition of joetice (2) ............ 152 6. (It M possible to act unjustly without being unjust.) That whicb is just in the strict sew is between citizens only, for it implies law ............... 160 7. It L in part natural, in part oonventional ......... 163 8. The internal conditions of a jast or unjust action, and of a just or unjust agent ............... 165 9. Bundry questions about doing and suffering injustice ... 169 10. Of equity ..................... 174 11. Can a man wrong himself 7 ............... 176 BOOK VI. THE INTELLECTUAL VIBTUEB. 1. Mnst be studied because (a) reason preacribea the mean, @) they are a part of human excellence. The intel- 1 lect M (1 ) acientific, (2) calculative : we want the virtue of each ..................... 160 a. The function of the intellect, both in practice and specula- tion, is to attain truth ............... 182 9. Of the five modes of attaining truth: (1) of demonstrative science of thing unalterable ............ 184 4. Of knowledge of things alterable, viz. (2) of art in what we make .....................185 6. And (3)of prudence in what we do, the virtue of the calcula- tive intellect .................. 186 6. (4) Of intuitive TeBSOn aa the baais of demonstrative eaienw ins 7. (5) Of wiedom as the anion of scieuw and intuitive reason. Cornpieon of the two intellectual virtuee, wisdom and prudence ..................... 190 8. Prudence compared with utateBmanehip and other forma of knowledge ............... ... ... 192 ... TABLE OF CONTENTB. Xlll CUAF. rAes .O. Of deliberation ..................... 195 10. Of intelligence ..................... 198 11. Of judgment. Of remon or intuitive perception BB the baais of the practical intellect ............ 199 12. Of the nees of wisdom and prudence. How prudence is related to clevernees ...............202 13. How prudence ia reloted to mod virtue ......... 295 BOOK VIL CHAPTICRE1-10. CHARACTERS OTHER THAN VIRTUE AND VICE. 1. Of continence and incontinence, heroic virtue and brutality. Of method. Statement of opinions about mntinenoe 208 2. Etatement of di5cul ties aa tu how one am kuow right and do wrong ..................... 210 3. Solution: to know han many sensa; in what senee such a man ~OWS..................... 214 4. Of incontinence in the strict and in the metaphorical mum 220 5. Of incontinence in respect of brutal or morbid appetites ... 224 6. Incontinence in linger less blamed than in appetite ... 227 7. Inwntinence yields tu pleasure, softness to pain.
Recommended publications
  • Plato Journal
    DEZ 2013 ISSN 2079-7567 I3 eISSN 2183-4105 Established 1989 http://platosociety.org/ Papers William H.F. Altman “The Missing Speech of the Absent Fourth: Reader Response and Plato’s Timaeus-Critias” David Levy, “Socrates vs. Callicles: Examination and Ridicule in Plato’s Gorgias.” Nathalie Nercam, “En tout et pour tout (Théétète 204a-210b)” Matthew Robinson, “Competition, Imagery, and Pleasure in Plato’s Republic, 1-91” Scott J. Senn, “Ignorance or Irony in Plato’s Socrates?: A Look Beyond Avowals and Disavowals of Knowledge” INTERNATIONAL PLATO SOCIETY PLATO INTERNATIONAL PL ATO Société Platonicienne JOURNALInternationale Associazione Internazionale dei Platonisti Sociedad Internacional de Platonistas Internationale Platon-Gesellschaft Imprensa da Universidade de Coimbra Coimbra Universiy Press 2 | Enicaper ficaed susta nondin is es nonim et dolore CREDITS EditOriAL BOARD INterNAtiONAL PLATO Francisco Gonzalez SOcietY EXecutiVE University of Ottawa COmmittee (2013-16) Irmgard Männlein-Robert President: Francisco Bravo Universität Tübingen Universidad Central de Venezuela Angela Ulacco President: Gabriele Cornelli Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg Universidade de Brasília Vice President: Tom Robinson ScieNtific BOArd University of Toronto Luc Brisson Ex-President: Mauro Tulli CNRS – UPR76 Centre Jean-Pépin, Paris Università degli Studi di Pisa Tomás Calvo Next President: Luc Brisson Universidad Complutense, Madrid CNRS – UPR76 Centre Jean-Pépin, Paris John Dillon Next President: Olivier Renaut Trinity College, Dublin Université Paris
    [Show full text]
  • Forms of Goodness : the Nature and Value of Virtue in Socratic Ethics. Scott .J Senn University of Massachusetts Amherst
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-2004 Forms of goodness : the nature and value of virtue in Socratic ethics. Scott .J Senn University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Senn, Scott .,J "Forms of goodness : the nature and value of virtue in Socratic ethics." (2004). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2378. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2378 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. FORMS OF GOODNESS: THE NATURE AND VALUE OF VIRTUE IN SOCRATIC ETHICS A Dissertation Presented by SCOTT J. SENN Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY May 2004 Department of Philosophy © Copyright by Scott J. Senn 2004 All Rights Reserved FORMS OF GOODNESS: THE NATURE AND VALUE OF VIRTUE IN SOCRATIC ETHICS A Dissertation Presented by SCOTT J. SENN Approved as to style and content by: Gareth B. Matthews, Chair C. c Vere C. Chappell, Member Department of Philosophy DEDICATION To Russell E. Senn, my first philosophy teacher ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS "I have to speak to you of one who was in many ways the greatest man that ever lived[. Thus begins an account of Platonic thought by John Burnet (1928) that inspired the work whose product is the present paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Wittgenstein's Critical Physiognomy
    Nordic Wittgenstein Review 3 (No. 1) 2014 Daniel Wack [email protected] Wittgenstein’s Critical Physiognomy Abstract In saying that meaning is a physiognomy, Wittgenstein invokes a philosophical tradition of critical physiognomy, one that developed in opposition to a scientific physiognomy. The form of a critical physiognomic judgment is one of reasoning that is circular and dynamic, grasping intention, thoughts, and emotions in seeing the expressive movements of bodies in action. In identifying our capacities for meaning with our capacities for physiognomic perception, Wittgenstein develops an understanding of perception and meaning as oriented and structured by our shared practical concerns and needs. For Wittgenstein, critical physiognomy is both fundamental for any meaningful interaction with others and a capacity we cultivate, and so expressive of taste in actions and ways of living. In recognizing how fundamental our capacity for physiognomic perception is to our form of life Wittgenstein inherits and radicalizes a tradition of critical physiognomy that stretches back to Kant and Lessing. Aesthetic experiences such as painting, poetry, and movies can be vital to the cultivation of taste in actions and in ways of living. Introduction “Meaning is a physiognomy.” –Ludwig Wittgenstein (PI, §568) In claiming that meaning is a physiognomy, Wittgenstein appears to call on a discredited pseudo-science with a dubious history of justifying racial prejudice and social discrimination in order to 113 Daniel Wack BY-NC-SA elucidate his understanding of meaning. Physiognomy as a science in the eighteenth and nineteenth century aimed to provide a model of meaning in which outer signs serve as evidence for judgments about inner mental states.
    [Show full text]
  • 7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul
    7 Aristotle on Greatness of Soul Roger Crisp n the recent revival of interest in Aristotelian ethics, relatively little attention has been paid to the virtue of greatness of soul (megalopsuchia). This is partly Ibecause of the focus on the more structurally central concepts of Aristotle’s theory, in particular happiness (eudaimonia) and virtue (aret¯e). But in fact a study of greatness of soul can reveal important insights into the overall shape of Aristotelian ethics, including the place of external goods and luck in the virtuous life, and the significance of “the noble” (to kalon). Further, Aristotle describes the great-souled person in more detail than any other, and calls greatness of soul a “sort of crown of the virtues” (NE IV.3.1124a1–2). Many have found aspects of the portrait of the great-souled person in the Nicomachean Ethics repellent or absurd, but that is no good reason for the student of Aristotle to shy away from it. In this chapter, I shall elucidate Aristotle’s account of greatness of soul, addressing some puzzles internal to that account and bringing out its place in, and implications for, the ethics of Aristotle and of those modern writers influenced by him. Greatness of Soul as a Virtue To understand greatness of soul as an Aristotelian virtue requires first understand- ing Aristotle’s conception of virtue itself. Aristotle distinguishes virtues into two classes – intellectual virtues and virtues of character – corresponding to distinct aspects of the human soul (NE I.13). Greatness of soul is a virtue of character, though, like all such virtues, it requires its possessor to have the intellectual virtue of practical wisdom (phron¯esis; NE VI.13).
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle (384-322 BCE)
    Aristotle (384-322 BCE) The Pythagoreans, Socrates, and Plato attempted to reconcile an element of human freedom with material determinism and causal law. But the first major philosopher to argue convincingly for some indeterminism was probably Aristotle. This is despite the fact that he described a causal chain back to a prime mover or first cause, and he elaborated the four possible causes (material, efficient, formal, and final). In his Physics and Metaphysics Aristotle also said there were "accidents" caused by "chance(τυχή)." In his Physics, he clearly reckoned chance among the causes. Aristotle might have added chance as a fifth cause - an uncaused or self-caused cause - that happens when two causal chains come together by accident (συμβεβεκός). He noted that the early physicists found no place for chance among the causes. Aristotle knew that many decisions were quite predictable based on habit and character, but they were no less free if one's character itself and predictable habits were developed freely in the past and were changeable in the future. This was the view of Eastern philosophies and religions. Our karma has been determined by our past actions (even from past lives), and strongly influences our current actions, but we are free to improve our karma by future good actions. As a principal architect of the concept of causality, and the formulator of the four causes, Aristotle's statements on indefinite causes are perhaps his most significant contribution to freedom, in the world and in human decisions. In his Metaphysics, Aristotle makes the case for chance and uncaused causes (causa sui) and in the Nicomachean Ethics he shows our actions can be voluntary and "up to us" so that we can be morally responsible.
    [Show full text]
  • ARISTOTLE and the IMPORTANCE of VIRTUE in the CONTEXT of the POLITICS and the NICOMACHEAN ETHICS and ITS RELATION to TODAY Kyle Brandon Anthony Bucknell University
    Bucknell University Bucknell Digital Commons Honors Theses Student Theses 2010 ARISTOTLE AND THE IMPORTANCE OF VIRTUE IN THE CONTEXT OF THE POLITICS AND THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS AND ITS RELATION TO TODAY Kyle Brandon Anthony Bucknell University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.bucknell.edu/honors_theses Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Anthony, Kyle Brandon, "ARISTOTLE AND THE IMPORTANCE OF VIRTUE IN THE CONTEXT OF THE POLITICS AND THE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS AND ITS RELATION TO TODAY" (2010). Honors Theses. 21. https://digitalcommons.bucknell.edu/honors_theses/21 This Honors Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Student Theses at Bucknell Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Honors Theses by an authorized administrator of Bucknell Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Table of Contents Introduction 1 Chapter 1 What does it mean to live a good life? 7 The virtuous life 8 Ethical virtue 13 Bravery as an ethical virtue 20 Justice 22 Chapter 2 The Politics and the ideal polis 28 Development of a polis 29 Features of an ideal polis 32 What does it mean to be a citizen of a polis? 40 Aristotle’s views on education 42 Social groups in a polis who are not recognized as citizens 45 Non-ideal political systems 51 Chapter 3 Connections between the Politics and the Ethics 57 Chapter 4 Difficulties in applying Aristotle’s theories to a modern setting 68 Conclusion Where do we go from here? 87 Bibliography 89 iv Acknowledgements First off, I have to thank God, as He helped me endure this project and gave me the courage to press on when I became frustrated, angry, and ready to quit.
    [Show full text]
  • IS GOD in HEAVEN? John Morreall Religion Department the College of William and Mary
    IS GOD IN HEAVEN? John Morreall Religion Department The College of William and Mary 1. Introduction t first glance, this question may seem as silly as the quip “Is the Pope Catholic?” For in the Biblical traditions what Ais older and more accepted than the idea that God is in heaven? In his prayer dedicating the temple, Solomon says over and over, “Hear in heaven your dwelling place (I Kings 8:30, 32, 34, 36, 39, 43, 45, 49), and many Jewish prayers are addressed to God in heaven. The central prayer of Christians, composed by Jesus, begins, “Our Father, who art in heaven.” Both the Apostles’ Creed and the Nicene Creed say that Jesus ascended into heaven, where he is now “seated at the right hand of the Father.” What I will show, however, is that, far from being an obvious truth, the claim that God is in heaven is logically incoherent, and so necessarily false. I will begin by presenting four features of the traditional concept of heaven, two from the Hebrew Bible, and two from the New Testament and early Christianity. All of these features were developed at a time when God was thought of as a physical being. But, I will then argue, once Christians thought of God as nonphysical, the traditional concept of heaven was no longer acceptable. My argument is that: 1. Heaven is a place. 2. Only what is physical is located in a place. 3. God is not physical. 4. So God is not located in a place. 5. So God is not located in heaven.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle: Movement and the Structure of Being
    Aristotle: Movement and the Structure of Being Author: Mark Sentesy Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/2926 This work is posted on eScholarship@BC, Boston College University Libraries. Boston College Electronic Thesis or Dissertation, 2012 Copyright is held by the author, with all rights reserved, unless otherwise noted. Boston College The Graduate School of Arts and Sciences Department of Philosophy ARISTOTLE: MOVEMENT AND THE STRUCTURE OF BEING a dissertation by MARK SENTESY submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy December 2012 © copyright by MARK SENTESY 2012 Aristotle: Movement and the Structure of Being Mark Sentesy Abstract: This project sets out to answer the following question: what does movement contribute to or change about being according to Aristotle? The first part works through the argument for the existence of movement in the Physics. This argument includes distinctive innovations in the structure of being, notably the simultaneous unity and manyness of being: while material and form are one thing, they are two in being. This makes it possible for Aristotle to argue that movement is not intrinsically related to what is not: what comes to be does not emerge from non‐being, it comes from something that is in a different sense. The second part turns to the Metaphysics to show that and how the lineage of potency and activity the inquiry into movement. A central problem is that activity or actuality, energeia, does not at first seem to be intrinsically related to a completeness or end, telos. With the unity of different senses of being at stake, Aristotle establishes that it is by showing that activity or actuality is movement most of all, and that movement has and is a complete end.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle and the Privation Theory of Evil
    Aristotle and the Privation Theory of Evil Jonathan J. Sanford, PhD Franciscan University of Steubenville [email protected] Though it conflicts with the standard narrative concerning the historical development of the privation theory of evil, it is nevertheless true that the notion that evil is not simply a privation but a privation of a due good has roots in Aristotle’s Metaphysics Theta. This book is Aristotle’s most complete account of being in the sense of actuality and potentiality, and its internal coherency and far reaching implications are often overlooked in commentaries on the Metaphysics, where most of the ink is spilled over books Zeta and Lambda. In this presentation I focus on Metaphysics Theta, chapter 9, draw upon some of the very fine work on this book of the Metaphysics which has been done in recent years, and try to lay out the case that a mature privation theory of evil is not simply compatible with Aristotle’s metaphysics but deployed therein and with profound implications for other areas of his thought. I. The Standard Narrative Before turning to the text of Metaphysics Theta 9, let’s consider a few features of what I identify as the standard narrative. It is Plotinus himself who emphasizes the distance of his own account from Aristotle’s when in Ennead II.4. 16, 3-8 he rejects the Aristotelian distinction between matter and privation. For Plotinus, matter itself is privation, and in Ennead I.8 matter is identified with evil. It is no secret that Aristotle maintains a notion of privation (steresis), and introduces it in Physics I.7 as one of the three principles (archai) of nature, describes its several senses in Metaphysics V.22 and examines it in the context of contrariety (enantiōsin) in 1 Metaphysics X.4.
    [Show full text]
  • Chart on Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics
    Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle: 384-322 B.C. The Human Good is the Souls’ Activity that Expresses Virtue for “ Political science spends most of its pains on making the citizens to be a certain character, viz. good and capable of noble acts” [1099: 27-32]. I. Prolegomena Action of the soul that expresses II. Virtues of Character: Books III-IV: reason is distinctive of human beings; Book 1: the excellent man’s function is to Book 2: The Virtues & express reason well (8). Excellence is of two kinds: intellectual & moral. Intellectual excellence is Responsibilities: The good is that which all things aim (1) Though happiness could be god- by birth and teaching (requires experience & time) and moral excellence given, it “comes as a result of comes about as a result of habit. Moral excellence does not arise in us by Virtue pertains only to voluntary feelings & actions. Determine the highest good since excellence and some process of nature; we are adapted by nature to receive them & are made perfect by habit; We forgive what is done non-voluntarily; what is everything is subordinate to it ; the learning or training, to be among the we become just by doing just acts, temperate by doing temperate acts, brave forced by something external is non-voluntary and highest good is political science (2) most god-like things; for that which is by doing brave acts [11031]. Habits distinguish between good & bad everything done by reason of ignorance is non- the prize end of excellence seem to be constitutions & between good & bad states.
    [Show full text]
  • ARISTOTLE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS :Index
    ARISTOTLE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS :Index. ARISTOTLE NICOMACHEAN ETHICS General Index ■ BOOK I ■ BOOK II ■ BOOK III ■ BOOK IV ■ BOOK V ■ BOOK VI ■ BOOK VII ■ BOOK VIII ■ BOOK IX ■ BOOK X file:///D|/Documenta%20Chatolica%20Omnia/99%20-%20Provv...20de%20las%20Categorias%20-%20ES/%23Ethics/0-Ethics.htm2006-05-30 09:57:39 ETHICS: BOOK I , Index. BOOK I Index CHAPTER 1 CHAPTER 2 CHAPTER 3 CHAPTER 4 CHAPTER 5 CHAPTER 6 CHAPTER 7 CHAPTER 8 CHAPTER 9 CHAPTER 10 CHAPTER 11 CHAPTER 12 CHAPTER 13 file:///D|/Documenta%20Chatolica%20Omnia/99%20-%20Provvi...20de%20las%20Categorias%20-%20ES/%23Ethics/1-Ethics0.htm2006-05-30 09:57:40 ETHICS: BOOK II , Index. BOOK II Index CHAPTER 1 CHAPTER 2 CHAPTER 3 CHAPTER 4 CHAPTER 5 CHAPTER 6 CHAPTER 7 CHAPTER 8 CHAPTER 9 file:///D|/Documenta%20Chatolica%20Omnia/99%20-%20Provvi...20de%20las%20Categorias%20-%20ES/%23Ethics/1-Ethics1.htm2006-05-30 09:57:40 ETHICS: BOOK III , Index. BOOK III Index CHAPTER 1 CHAPTER 2 CHAPTER 3 CHAPTER 4 CHAPTER 5 CHAPTER 6 CHAPTER 7 CHAPTER 8 CHAPTER 9 CHAPTER 10 CHAPTER 11 CHAPTER 12 file:///D|/Documenta%20Chatolica%20Omnia/99%20-%20Provvi...20de%20las%20Categorias%20-%20ES/%23Ethics/1-Ethics2.htm2006-05-30 09:57:40 ETHICS: BOOK IV , Index. BOOK IV Index CHAPTER 1 CHAPTER 2 CHAPTER 3 CHAPTER 4 CHAPTER 5 CHAPTER 6 CHAPTER 7 CHAPTER 8 CHAPTER 9 file:///D|/Documenta%20Chatolica%20Omnia/99%20-%20Provvi...20de%20las%20Categorias%20-%20ES/%23Ethics/1-Ethics3.htm2006-05-30 09:57:40 ETHICS: BOOK V , Index. BOOK V Index CHAPTER 1 CHAPTER 2 CHAPTER 3 CHAPTER 4 CHAPTER 5 CHAPTER 6 CHAPTER 7 CHAPTER 8 CHAPTER 9 CHAPTER 10 CHAPTER 11 file:///D|/Documenta%20Chatolica%20Omnia/99%20-%20Provvi...20de%20las%20Categorias%20-%20ES/%23Ethics/1-Ethics4.htm2006-05-30 09:57:41 ETHICS: BOOK VI , Index.
    [Show full text]
  • The Highest Good and the Best Activity: Aristotle on the Well-Lived Life" (2011)
    Loyola University Chicago Loyola eCommons Master's Theses Theses and Dissertations 2011 The Highest Good and the Best Activity: Aristotle on the Well- Lived Life Philip William Bauchan Loyola University Chicago Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses Part of the Ethics in Religion Commons Recommended Citation Bauchan, Philip William, "The Highest Good and the Best Activity: Aristotle on the Well-Lived Life" (2011). Master's Theses. 514. https://ecommons.luc.edu/luc_theses/514 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Theses and Dissertations at Loyola eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Master's Theses by an authorized administrator of Loyola eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 License. Copyright © 2011 Philip William Bauchan LOYOLA UNIVERSITY CHICAGO THE HIGHEST GOOD AND THE BEST ACTIVITY: ARISTOTLE ON THE WELL-LIVED LIFE A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY BY PHILIP WILLIAM BAUCHAN CHICAGO, ILLINOIS AUGUST 2011 When zeroing in on the primary points in the Nicomachean Ethics at which Aristotle explicitly discusses the nature of eudaimonia , Book I.1-5; 7 and Book X.7-8 are always singled out as the most crucial sections. While the entire text is filled with discussions that variably shine light on how Aristotle conceives of eudaimonia , it is the aforementioned passages that must be fully addressed and accounted for in any study of this topic.
    [Show full text]