Wednesday 18, June 1:30-4:30Pm

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Wednesday 18, June 1:30-4:30Pm Wednesday 18, June 1:30-4:30pm: Parallel Session I Symposium: The Seventeenth Century Origins of Absolute Space and Time Like many metaphysical doctrines of the seventeenth century, the concepts of absolute space and time served both an important scientific function and also fostered vigorous and productive philosophical exchange. The preeminent instances of these dual roles are, respectively, Newton's Principia and the Clarke-Leibniz Correspondence. Consequently these texts have been the main focus for early modern scholars of space and time. The papers in this symposium, while recognizing the centrality of these texts, aim in a number of specific ways to broaden and enrich our understanding of 'the absolutes' in seventeenth century natural philosophy of space and time. First, several of the papers (Dunlop, Gorham, Slowik) investigate anticipations of the Newtonian absolutes in authors known to Newton, especially Gassendi, Barrow, and the Cambridge Platonists, and explore crucial but lesser known Newtonian texts such as the unpublished tract, De Gravitatione. The concern in these papers is not only with the influence on Newton, but also with the intrinsic nature and justification of the particular forms of absolute space and time proposed in the work of these influential authors. A second major theme of the papers (Dunlop, Futch, Gorham) is the epistemic or methodological status of absolute space and time. A major issue for Newton, and for his contemporary and subsequent critics, was the relation between the absolutes and their 'sensible measures' (bodies and motions). This symposium will show how this epistemic concern was at work in the philosophical precursors of Newton, as well as in the development of Leibniz's alternative to absolute space and time. Third, several of the papers (Dunlop, Futch, Gorham) examine the symmetry, or similarity, between absolute space and absolute time, which was a common preoccupation in seventeenth century treatments. While many -- such as Locke -- saw deep analogies between space and time, others -- such as Descartes -- conceived of them as importantly different. The symposium explores the complex role played by considerations of symmetry in arguments both for and against the existence of absolute space and time. Fourth, all of the papers aim to shed new light on the perennial relationalist-substantivalist debate. Slowik and Futch concentrate, respectively, on the original champions in the debate, Newton and Leibniz. But rather than enjoin the debate itself, each paper presents a novel reading of the metaphysical presuppositions of the opposing positions, which clarifies what is ultimately at stake. Dunlop and Gorham offer distinctive explanations for notable asymmetries in Newton's treatment of absolute space vs. absolute time. Dunlop illuminates Newton's approach to the ontology and measurement of space and time by contrasting his conception of geometrical practice with that of his teacher, Isaac Barrow, while Gorham argues that early modern conceptions of absolute space (but not absolute time) have their origin in updated versions of traditional thought experiments involving God's absolute power of annihilation. Analogical Reasoning in Precursors of Absolute Time: Gassendi and Barrow Geoffrey Gorham (St. Olaf College and Minnesota Center for Philosophy of Science) In a recent overview of early modern metaphysics, Nicholas Jolley observes in passing that “philosophical theories that seem primarily tailored to space are often said to apply mutatis mutandis to the case of time”.[1] I examine this tendency to argue by analogy from space to time in two likely influences on Newton: Pierre Gassendi and Isaac Barrow. In the Aristotelian tradition, space implies body and time implies motion. However this symmetry is broken by the end of the sixteenth century: void space is widely entertained but time remains wedded to motion or change. There are many reasons for this asymmetry; but here I emphasize a factor that has been little discussed. Practically every early modern natural philosopher who treats space and time invokes – even if only to refute – traditional metaphysical arguments for endowing space with intrinsic dimensionality apart from body. For example, it is argued that God could annihilate a certain part of the world leaving a vacated space with the same dimensions as the part destroyed. However, as Leibniz recognized, such arguments simply do not extend to time: "If there were a vacuum in space one could establish its size. But if there were a vacuum in time, i.e. duration without change, it would be impossible to establish its length. ....It follows from this that we cannot refute someone who says that two successive worlds are contiguous in time. with no possible interval between them.[2] The relative paucity of empirical investigations of changeless time, as compared with local spatial vacua, is unsurprising given the inherent conceptual barrier to gauging such duration. It is in this precisely this context that analogical arguments from space to time come to the fore. Drawing on recent philosophical discussions of analogical reasoning in science, I show how time is endowed with an intrinsic dimensionality and measure isomorphic to an already articulated absolute space. This kind of reasoning is pervasive in the seventeenth century but Gassendi and Barrow are especially influential and instructive instances. The former develops an elaborate version of the traditional thought experiment for absolute space, but his case for changeless time rests primarily on the otherwise strong analogy between time and his geometrical space: both are extended, continuous, neither substance nor accident, and composed of parts. Given these similarities, Gassendi concludes, time is simply the successive counterpart of absolute space: "there exist two diffusions, extensions, or quantities, one permanent, namely place or space, and one successive, namely time or duration".[3] Similarly, in Barrow absolute time emerges parasitic on absolute space and inherits spatial features: the 'space of motion' (spatium motas), as he refers to time, is conceived as successive existence stretched out along a single spatial dimension.[4] Finally, I will argue that the Gassendi-Barrow methodology is assimilated by Newton in his early accounts of absolute space and time (e.g. De Gravitatione). From this point of view, I suggest, we can make better sense of certain otherwise puzzling features of Newton’s famous Scholium, especially his comparatively limp defense of absolute time vs. absolute space and motion. [1] 'Metaphyiscs', Cambridge Companion to Early Modern Philosophy, 128-9. [2] New Essays, II, xv. [3] Syntagma, I, ii. [4] Geometrical Lectures, I. Cambridge Platonism and Newton's Ontology of Absolute Space Edward Slowik (Winona State University and Pittsburgh Center for Philosophy of Science) This presentation will investigate the influence of Cambridge neo-Platonic concepts and arguments on Newton’s natural philosophy of space, matter, and motion, with special emphasis placed on the manner by which both Henry More and Walter Charleton may have prompted or informed Newton’s ontology of space. A number of important questions, much discussed in the recent literature on Newton, will be addressed. (1) Did Newton accept a form of “substantivalism”, which (among other things) regards space as a form of substance or entity? (2) Did Newton ground the existence of space upon an incorporeal being (i.e., God or World Spirit), as did his neo-Platonic predecessors and contemporaries? (3) What is the status of the parts or points of space in Newton’s scheme, and does his pronouncement on the identity of the points of space (in his tract, De Gravitatione) undermine his alleged substantivalism? As regards (1), A number of important reappraisals by Howard Stein and Robert DiSalle have concluded that the content and function of Newton’s concept of “absolute” space should be kept separate from the question of Newton’s commitment to substantivalism. In Stein’s contribution to The Cambridge Companion to Newton, he further contends, more controversially, that Newton does not sanction substantivalism, a view that may also be evident in various early articles by J. E. McGuire. Concerning (2), Stein rejects any significant neo- Platonic content, as did McGuire’s early work. Finally, the problem of the points of space, raised by an enigmatic discussion in the De Gravitatione, has brought about several recent reappraisals by Nerlich and Huggett concerning the viability of Newton’s espoused substantivalism. This presentation will examine the ontology of Newton’s spatial theory in order to determine the adequacy of these interpretations and arguments. As will be demonstrated, Newton’s spatial theory is not only deeply imbued in neo-Platonic speculation, contra (2), but these neo-Platonic elements likewise compromise any strong non-substantivalist interpretation, contrary to (1). Throughout our investigation, however, the specific details and subtleties of Newton’s particular brand of neo-Platonism will be contrasted with the ontologies of his contemporaries and predecessors, especially More and Charleton, and by this means a more adequate grasp of the innovations and foreword-looking aspects of his theory of space can be obtained. In short, the spatial theory that Newton advances, especially in De Gravitatione, bears much in common with a property view of space, such that space is correlated and coextensive with the existence of an immaterial
Recommended publications
  • Arthur Pap Archive I. Manuscripts and Typscripts I.1
    Arthur Pap Archive Inventory of the „Nachlass“ of Arthur Pap at the Institute Vienna Circle, by Christoph Limbeck-Lilienau I. Manuscripts and Typscripts I.1 Pap „Absolute Motion and the Clock Paradox“ [1953], 34 p., A4, Typscript Box 1/Folder 1 “Are Physical Magnitudes Operally Definable?” 1959, Typscript with a few handwritten corrections, 19 p., A4, 9 carbon copies. Published in: Box 1/2 Abstract for: “Are Physical Magnitudes Operally Definable?” 1956, Typscript, 3 p., A4 Box 1/3 “Are Physical Magnitudes Operationally Definable?” 1959, Typscript, 19 p., A4, Typscript, Box 1/3 “Are Physical Magnitudes Operationally Definable?” 1959, Typscript, 19 p., A4, Typscript, 8 Copies Box 1/3 “Basic Propositions, Certainty, and Intersubjective Language” [1958], Typscript, 21 p., A4 Box 1/4 “Basic Propositions, Certainty, and Intersubjective Language” [1960], Typscript, marginal handwritten corrections, 21 p., A4 Box 1/4 “Belief and Natural-Language-Intentions” No Date, Typscript, 5 p., A4 (from “Manila Folder”) Box 1/4 Abstract for: “Belief and Proposition” No Date, Typscript, 1 p., A4 Box 1/ 4 “Comments on M. Scriven´s `Certain Weaknesses in the Deductive Model of Explanation´” [1955], 5 p., A4, Typscript, Copy, (Original in the letter of M. Scriven from May 9, 1955) Scriven´s Reply is “Reply to Pap General Points-Specific Points”. Box 1/ 4 Critical Comments on Paul Weiss´ “Real Possibility” No Date, 3 p., A4, Typescript Box 1/ 4 “Mr. O´Connor on Incompatibility” [1955 or later], 4 p., A4, Typescript Box 1/ 4 Criticism of Sellars´ “On the Logic of Complex particulars” (from a letter of July 28) No Date, Typscript, 3 p., A4 (from “Manila Folder”) Box 1/4 1 “The Dispensibility of Material Implication for Applied Logic” 1959, Typescript with handwritten additions, 13 p., A4 (Contains a letter of rejection by John Rawls, see Correspondence “Rawls” (No.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 2021; 2(1): 71–83
    Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 2021; 2(1): 71–83 David J. Stump* The Kantian Elements in Arthur Pap’s Philosophy https://doi.org/10.1515/jtph-2020-0013 Published online October 30, 2020 Abstract: Arthur Pap worked in analytic philosophy while maintaining a strong Kantian or neo-Kantian element throughout his career, stemming from his studying with Ernst Cassirer. I present these elements in the different periods of Pap’s works, showing him to be a consistent critic of logical empiricism, which Pap shows to be incapable of superseding the Kantian framework. Nevertheless, Pap’s work is definitely analytic philosophy, both in terms of the content and the style. According to Pap, the central topics of analytic philosophy concern meaning, modality, and analysis. Pap was also influenced by pragmatism, especially in his dissertation, although he does not fully embrace it in either its classical or its Quinean form. Keywords: Arthur Pap, Ernst Cassirer, a priori, analytic philosophy, neo- Kantianism 1 Introduction Arthur Pap studied with Ernst Cassirer at Yale, writing a Master’s thesis under his supervision. He then returned to Columbia where he had received his under- graduate degree, to earn his Ph. D. under the supervision of Ernest Nagel. One might wonder if either Cassirer, the neo-Kantian, or Nagel, the logical empiricist with a pragmatist streak,1 had a lasting influence on Pap, given that his oeuvre is 1 Nagel is a complex figure and hard to categorize. He studied under Morris R. Cohen, who could be described as a rationalist and his early work includes some very important historical pieces on mathematics.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction
    Notes Introduction 1 . Bataille talks of an ‘abyss’ ( 1986 , p. 80); Ryle ( 1971b , p. 182) and Dummett ( 1993 , p. xi) talks of a ‘gulf’. 2 . See Reynolds & Chase, 2011 , pp. 254–255. 3 . A recent survey of the field is given in Floyd, 2009 ; see also Beaney, 1998 ; Preston, 2005 . 4 . See esp. Sluga, 1998 ; Stroll, 2000 ; Glock, 2008 ; Monk, 1996a . See also Hylton, 1990 ; Hacker, 2007 ; Glendinning, 2006 ; Preston, 2007 ; Floyd, 2009 , p. 173. 5 . See e.g. Stroll, 2000 ; Glock, 2008 . See also Reynolds and Chase, 2010 ; Reynolds et al., 2010 . 6 . An early variant of this view is proposed by Urmson (1992 ), who divides the history of philosophical analysis into four types: (i) ‘classical’ analysis (Russell), (ii) ideal-language analysis (early Wittgenstein, Vienna Circle, Quine, Goodman), (iii) ‘therapeutic positivist’ (p. 299) analysis (later Wittgenstein, Ryle, Wisdom, Waismann), and (iv) ‘ordinary language’ analysis (Austin). Weitz ( 1966 ) similarly comments that ‘it has become established practice in anthologies and histories of twentieth century philosophy to divide its analytic parts into (a) Realism, (b) Logical Analysis or Logical Atomism, (c) Logical Positivism, and (d) Linguistic, Ordinary Language, or Conceptual Analysis’ (p. 1). Russell ( 1959 , p. 216) talked of three waves in British philosophy 1914–1959, Wittgenstein’s Tractatus , Logical Positivism, and the later Wittgenstein. More recently, Hacker ( 1996 , pp. 4–5; 2007 ) proposed a similar understanding of analytic philosophy as a series of phases in the history of philosophy, rather than defining it as either a set of necessary and sufficient conditions or as a family resem- blance concept. Whereas Urmson emphasises the ‘decisive break’ (1960 , p.
    [Show full text]
  • Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 2021; 2(1): 47–69
    Journal of Transcendental Philosophy 2021; 2(1): 47–69 Thomas Mormann* Two Kindred Neo-Kantian Philosophies of Science: Pap’s The A Priori in Physical Theory and Cassirer’s Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics https://doi.org/10.1515/jtph-2021-0001 Published online April 8, 2021 Abstract: The main thesis of this paper is that Pap’s The Functional A Priori in Physical Theory and Cassirer’s Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics may be conceived as two kindred accounts of a late Neo-Kantian philosophy of science. They elucidate and clarify each other mutually by elaborating conceptual possibilities and pointing out affinities of neo-Kantian ideas with other currents of 20th century’s philosophy of science, namely, pragmatism, conventionalism, and logical empiricism. Taking into account these facts, it seems not too far fetched to conjecture that under more favorable circumstances Pap could have served as a mediator between the “analytic” and “continental” tradition thereby overcoming the dogmatic dualism of these two philosophical currents that has characterized philosophy in the second half the 20th century. Keywords: neo-Kantianism, pragmatism, logical empiricism, Arthur Pap, Ernst Cassirer 1 Introduction The main thesis of this paper is that Pap’s The A Priori in Physical Theory (Pap 1946, henceforth FAP) and Cassirer’s Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics (Cassirer 1937, henceforth DI) may be conceived as two kindred accounts of a late Neo-Kantian philosophy of science. They elucidate and clarify each other mutually by elaborating conceptual possibilities and pointing out affinities of neo-Kantian ideas with other currents of 20th century’s philosophy of science, namely, prag- matism, conventionalism, and logical empiricism.
    [Show full text]
  • Paul Edwards: a Rationalist Critic of Kierkegaard's Theory of Truth
    St. John Fisher College Fisher Digital Publications Philosophy and Classical Studies Faculty/Staff Publications Philosophy and Classical Studies 2012 Paul Edwards: A Rationalist Critic of Kierkegaard's Theory of Truth Timothy Madigan St. John Fisher College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://fisherpub.sjfc.edu/philosophy_facpub Part of the History of Philosophy Commons How has open access to Fisher Digital Publications benefited ou?y Custom Citation Madigan, Timothy J. "Paul Edwards: A Rationalist Critic of Kierkegaard's Theory of Truth." Kierkegaard's influence on philosophy: omeT III, Anglophone philosophy. Ed. Jon Stewart. Farnham, England: Ashgate, 2012. 71-85. Web. This document is posted at https://fisherpub.sjfc.edu/philosophy_facpub/1 and is brought to you for free and open access by Fisher Digital Publications at St. John Fisher College. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Paul Edwards: A Rationalist Critic of Kierkegaard's Theory of Truth Abstract In lieu of an abstract, below is the chapter's first paragraph. Best known as the editor-in-chief of the monumental Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Paul Edwards (1923-2004) was a modern philosophe. Like the Enlightenment writers he himself so admired, Voltaire, Diderot, and D'Alembert, he spent his career defending the ideas of rationalism, freethought, materialism, and the application of scientific methodology to philosophy. In addition, deeply influenced yb the Vienna Circle, he used his editorship of the Encyclopedia to keep alive the memories of many of the philosophers connected with that particular Logical Positivist movement. As a Positivist of sorts himself, he had no love for philosophers whom he considered to lack clarity, and like the philosophes—especially Voltaire, whose work he anthologized in a volume entitled Voltaire Selections—he had a gift for using biting humor to attack those with whom he disagreed.
    [Show full text]
  • European Philosophy of Science
    Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook Maria Carla Galavotti Elisabeth Nemeth Friedrich Stadler Editors European Philosophy of Science - Philosophy of Science in Europe and the Viennese Heritage EUROPEAN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE – PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE IN EUROPE AND THE VIENNESE HERITAGE VIENNA CIRCLE INSTITUTE YEARBOOK 17 VIENNA CIRCLE INSTITUTE YEARBOOK 17 Institut Wiener Kreis Society for the Advancement of the Scientifi c World Conception Series-Editor: Friedrich Stadler University of Vienna, Austria and Director, Institut Wiener Kreis Advisory Editorial Board: Honorary Consulting Editors: Jacques Bouveresse, Collège de France, Paris, France Robert S. Cohen, Boston University, USA Martin Carrier, University of Bielefeld, Germany Wilhelm K. Essler, University of Frankfurt/M., Nancy Cartwright, London School of Economics, UK Germany Richard Creath, Arizona State University, USA Kurt Rudolf Fischer, University of Vienna, Austria Massimo Ferrari, University of Torino, Italy Adolf Grünbaum, University of Pittsburgh, USA Michael Friedman, Stanford University, USA Rudolf Haller, University of Graz, Austria Maria Carla Galavotti, University of Bologna, Italy Gerald Holton, Harvard University, USA Peter Galison, Harvard University, USA Jaakko Hintikka, Boston University, USA Malachi Hacohen, Duke University, USA Allan S. Janik, University of Innsbruck, Austria Rainer Hegselmann, University of Bayreuth, Germany Andreas Kamlah, University of Osnabrück, Michael Heidelberger, University of Tübingen, Germany Germany Don Howard, University of Notre Dame, USA Eckehart Köhler, University of Vienna, Austria Paul Hoyningen-Huene, University of Hanover, Germany Brian McGuinness, University of Siena, Italy Clemens Jabloner, Hans-Kelsen-Institut, Vienna, Austria Erhard Oeser, University of Vienna, Austria Anne J. Kox, University of Amsterdam, The Netherlands Jan Šebestík, CNRS Paris, France Martin Kusch, University of Vienna, Austria Christian Thiel, University of Erlangen, Germany James G.
    [Show full text]
  • Cassirer's Children Corrected Version.Mormann
    Two Kindred Neo-Kantian Philosophies of Science: Pap’s The Functional A Priori in Physical Theory and Cassirer’s Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics Abstract. The main thesis of this paper is that Pap’s The Functional A Priori of Physical Theory (Pap 1946, henceforth FAP) and Cassirer’s Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics (Cassirer 1937, henceforth DI) may be conceived as two kindred accounts of a late Neo-Kantian philosophy of science. They elucidate and clarify each other mutually by elaborating conceptual possibilities and pointing out affinities of neo-Kantian ideas with other currents of 20th century’s philosophy of science, namely, pragmatism, conventionalism, and logical empiricism. Taking into account these facts, it seems not too far fetched to conjecture that under more favorable circumstances Pap could have served as a mediator between the “analytic” and “continental” tradition thereby overcoming the dogmatic dualism of these two philosophical currents that has characterized philosophy in the second half the 20th century. Keywords: Neo-Kantianism, Pragmatism, Logical Empiricism, Arthur Pap, Ernst Cassirer. 1. Introduction. The main thesis of this paper is that Pap’s The Functional A Priori of Physical Theory (Pap 1946, henceforth FAP) and Cassirer’s Determinism and Indeterminism in Modern Physics (Cassirer 1937, henceforth DI) may be conceived as two kindred accounts of a late Neo-Kantian philosophy of science. They elucidate and clarify each other mutually by elaborating conceptual possibilities and pointing out affinities of neo-Kantian ideas with other currents of 20th century’s philosophy of science, namely, pragmatism, conventionalism, and logical empiricism. In his early papers Pap heavily drew on Cassirer’s DI.
    [Show full text]
  • Defending the Wall Between Church & State
    THE INTERNATIONAL SECULAR HUMANIST MAGAZINE Spring 1996 Vol.16, No.2 DO WE NEED GOD TO BE MORAL? PAUL KURTZ debates JOHN FRAME MARTIN GARDNER Adventist Flimflams CHRISTOPHER DURANG The Lost Encyclical DEFENDING THE WALL BETWEEN CHURCH & STATE SPRING 1996, VOL. 16, NO. 2 ISSN 0272-0701 Contents !ree 3 LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Editor: Paul Kurtz Executive Editor: Timothy J. Madigan 4 DO WE NEED GOD TO BE MORAL? Managing Editor: Andrea Szalanski Senior Editors: Vern Bullough, Thomas W. Flynn, 4 Without a Supreme Being, Everything Is Permitted John M. Frame R. Joseph Hoffmann, Gerald Larue, Gordon Stein 6 Rebuttal Paul Kurtz Contributing Editors: 5 The Common Moral Decencies Don't Depend on Faith Paul Kurtz Robert S. Alley, Joe E. Barnhart, David Berman, H. James Birx, Jo Ann Boydston, Bonnie Bullough, 7 Rebuttal John M. Frame Paul Edwards, Albert Ellis, Roy P. Fairfield, Charles W. Faulkner, Antony Flew, Levi Fragell, Adolf 8 RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SCHOOLS Grünbaum, Marvin Kohl, Jean Kotkin, Thelma Lavine, Tibor Machan, Ronald A. Lindsay, Michael 8 Introduction Andrea Szalanski Martin, Delos B. McKown, Lee Nisbet, John Novak, 9 Church and State: A Humanist View Vern L. Bullough Skipp Porteous, Howard Radest, Robert Rimmer, Michael Rockier, Svetozar Stojanovic, Thomas Szasz, V. M. Tarkunde, Richard Taylor, Rob Tielman POINT Associate Editors: 12 The Case for Affirmative Secularism Thomas W. Flynn Molleen Matsumura, Lois Porter COUNTERPOINT Editorial Associates: Doris Doyle, Thomas Franczyk, Roger Greeley, 20 Religious and Philosophical Freedom for Everybody: James Martin-Diaz, Steven L. Mitchell, Warren A Reply to Tom Flynn Rob Boston Allen Smith Cartoonist: Don Addis 21 Church-State Separation: The 1996 Elections CODESH.
    [Show full text]
  • Paul Feyerabend and the Forgotten 'Third Vienna Circle' 49
    Annals of the Academy of Romanian Scientists Series on Philosophy, Psychology, Theology and Journalism Online ISSN 2067 – 113X Volume 6, Number 1–2/2014 47 PAUL FEYERABEND AND THE FORGOTTEN ∗ 'THIRD VIENNA CIRCLE' ∗∗ Friedrich STADLER Abstract . The study contradicts the image of Feyerabend as a herald of postmodern “anything goes” and as destroyer of rational philosophy and anarchist, in an approach of the formative intellectual socialization of Feyerabend in Vienna, until his move to England and America. It shows a deep rootedness in the Austrian tradition of philosophy and science, which can be detected up tohis return to Europe. At the same time, the text presents a consistent intellectual profile that tracks the empirically oriented complementarity of science and art and science of history and philosophy of science toward an abstract, normative philosophy of science at various levels, with a loose agenda. This is conceived in the form of a historically oriented tbsrelativism and aims rather to interpret Feyerabend’s contribution as a continuation of the productive approaches spilled into the History and Philosophy of Science since Mach than considering his work a big break or settlement with the philosophy of science, as evidenced also inFeyerabend’s notes, in his autobiography. Keywords : Feyerabend, rationalism, empiricism, relativism, Vienna Circle, Austrian philosophy. Paul Feyerabend (1924-1994): “The Worst Enemy of Science”? Even though many years have passed since his death, Paul Feyerabend continues to be discussed – by philosophers and the scientific community – but he is also the subject of a broader public debate. Especially in the German-speaking world, his image as an enfant terrible of philosophy continues to be nourished by fragments that have appeared posthumously (Feyerabend 2005).
    [Show full text]