Lecture 4: Risk Preferences & Expected Utility Theory

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Lecture 4: Risk Preferences & Expected Utility Theory FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (1) Markus K. Brunnermeier LECTURE 4: RISK PREFERENCES & EXPECTED UTILITY THEORY FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (2) specify observe/specify Preferences & existing Technology Asset Prices • evolution of states NAC/LOOP NAC/LOOP • risk preferences • aggregation State Prices q absolute (or stochastic discount relative asset pricing factor/Martingale measure) asset pricing LOOP derive derive Asset Prices Price for (new) asset Only works as long as market completeness doesn’t change FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (3) Overview: Risk Preferences 1. State-by-state dominance 2. Stochastic dominance [DD4] 3. vNM expected utility theory a) Intuition [L4] b) Axiomatic foundations [DD3] 4. Risk aversion coefficients and portfolio choice [DD5,L4] 5. Uncertainty/ambiguity aversion 6. Prudence coefficient and precautionary savings [DD5] 7. Mean-variance preferences [L4.6] FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (4) State-by-state Dominance - State-by-state dominance is an incomplete ranking 풕 = ퟎ 풕 = ퟏ Cost Payoff 휋1 = 휋2 = 1/2 푠 = 1 푠 = 2 Investment 1 -1000 1050 1200 Investment 2 -1000 500 1600 Investment 3 -1000 1050 1600 - Investment 3 state-by-state dominates investment 1 - Recall: 푦, 푥 ∈ ℝ푆 . 푦 ≥ 푥 ⇔ 푦푠 ≥ 푥푠 for each 푠 = 1, … , 푆 . 푦 > 푥 ⇔ 푦 ≥ 푥, 푦 ≠ 푥 . 푦 ≫ 푥 ⇔ 푦푠 > 푥푠 for each 푠 = 1, … , 푆 FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (5) State-by-state Dominance (ctd.) 풕 = ퟎ 풕 = ퟏ Cost Return 휋1 = 휋2 = 1/2 E[Return] 휎 푠 = 1 푠 = 2 Investment 1 -1000 + 5% + 20% 12.5% 7.5% Investment 2 -1000 - 50% + 60% 5% 55% Investment 3 -1000 + 5% + 60% 32.5% 27.5% • Investment 1 mean-variance dominates 2 • But, investment 3 does not mean-variance dominate 1 FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (6) State-by-state Dominance (ctd.) 풕 = ퟎ 풕 = ퟏ Cost Return 휋1 = 휋2 = 1/2 E[Return] 휎 푠 = 1 푠 = 2 Investment 4 -1000 + 3% + 5% 4.0% 1.0% Investment 5 -1000 + 3% + 8% 5.5% 2.5% • What is the trade-off between risk and expected return? 퐸 푟 −푟 • Investment 4 has a higher Sharpe ratio 푓 than investment 5 for 푟 = 0 푓 FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (7) Overview: Risk Preferences 1. State-by-state dominance 2. Stochastic dominance [DD4] 3. vNM expected utility theory a) Intuition [L4] b) Axiomatic foundations [DD3] 4. Risk aversion coefficients and portfolio choice [DD5,L4] 5. Prudence coefficient and precautionary savings [DD5] 6. Mean-variance preferences [L4.6] FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (8) Stochastic Dominance • No state-space – probabilities are not assigned specific states . Only applicable for final payoff gamble • Not for stocks/lotteries that form a portfolio (whose payoff is final) . Random variables before introduction of (Ω, ℱ, 푃) • Still incomplete ordering . “More complete” than state-by-state ordering . State-by-state dominance ⇒ stochastic dominance . Risk preference not needed for ranking! • independently of the specific trade-offs (between return, risk and other characteristics of probability distributions) represented by an agent's utility function. (“risk-preference-free”) • Next Section: . Complete preference ordering and utility representations FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (9) From payoffs per state to probability state 풔ퟏ 풔ퟐ 풔ퟑ 풔ퟒ 풔ퟓ probability 휋1 휋2 휋3 휋4 휋5 Payoff x 10 10 20 20 20 Payoff y 10 20 20 20 30 Expressed in “probability lotteries” – only useful for final payoffs (since some cross correlation information ins lost) payoff 10 20 30 Prob x 푝10 = 휋1 + 휋2 푝20 = 휋3 + 휋4 + 휋5 푝30 = 0 Prob y 푞10 = 휋1 푞20 = 휋2 + 휋3 + 휋4 푞30 = 휋5 푆 Preference 푥 ≻ 푦 ∈ ℝ expressed in probabilities 푝푥 ≻ 푞푦 FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (10) Expected Standard Payoff Deviation Payoffs 10 100 2000 Probability 1 .4 .6 0 64 44 Probability 2 .4 .4 .2 444 779 Pr obability F1 1.0 0.9 F2 0.8 0.7 0.6 0.5 F1 and F 2 0.4 0.3 Note: Payoff of $10 is 0.2 equally likely, but can be 0.1 in different states of the world Payoff 0 10 100 2000 FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (11) First Order Stochastic Dominance • Definition: Let 퐹퐴 푥 , 퐹퐵 푥 , respectively, represent the cumulative distribution functions of two random variables (cash payoffs) that, without loss of generality assume values in the interval 푎, 푏 . We say that 퐹퐴 푥 first order stochastically dominates (FSD) 퐹퐵 푥 if and only if for all 푥 ∈ 푎, 푏 퐹퐴 푥 ≤ 퐹퐵 푥 Homework: Provide an example which can be ranked according to FSD, but not according to state dominance. FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (12) First Order Stochastic Dominance 1 0.9 0.8 FB 0.7 FA 0.6 0.5 0.4 0.3 0.2 0.1 0 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 X FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (13) Payoff 1 4 5 6 8 12 Probability 3 0 .25 0.50 0 0 .25 Probability 4 .33 0 0 .33 .33 0 1 0.9 0.8 0.7 0.6 investment 4 0.5 0.4 0.3 0.2 investment 3 0.1 0 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 CDFs of investment 3 and 4 FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (14) Second Order Stochastic Dominance • Definition: Let 퐹퐴 푥 , 퐹퐵 푥 be two cumulative probability distribution for random payoffs in 푎, 푏 . We say that 퐹퐴 푥 second order stochastically dominates (SSD) 퐹퐵 푥 if and only if for any 푥 ∈ 푎, 푏 푥 퐹퐵 푡 − 퐹퐴 푡 푑푡 ≥ 0 −∞ (with strict inequality for some meaningful interval of values of t). FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (15) Mean Preserving Spread 푥퐵 = 푥퐴 + 푧 (where 푧 is independent and has zero mean) Mean Preserving Spread: f x (for normal distributions) A fB x ~x, Payoff x fA xdx x fBxdx FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (16) Mean Preserving Spread & SSD • Theorem: Let 퐹퐴 푥 and 퐹퐵 푥 be two distribution functions defined on the same state space with identical means. Then the following statements are equivalent : . 퐹퐴 푥 SSD 퐹퐵 푥 . 퐹퐵 푥 is a mean-preserving spread of 퐹퐴 푥 FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (17) Overview: Risk Preferences 1. State-by-state dominance 2. Stochastic dominance [DD4] 3. vNM expected utility theory a) Intuition [L4] b) Axiomatic foundations [DD3] 4. Risk aversion coefficients and portfolio choice [DD5,L4] 5. Prudence coefficient and precautionary savings [DD5] 6. Mean-variance preferences [L4.6] FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (18) A Hypothetical Gamble • Suppose someone offers you this gamble: . "I have a fair coin here. I'll flip it, and if it's tails I pay you $1 and the gamble is over. If it's heads, I'll flip again. If it's tails then, I pay you $2, if not I'll flip again. With every round, I double the amount I will pay to you if it turns up tails." • Sounds like a good deal. After all, you can't lose. So here's the question: . How much are you willing to pay to take this gamble? FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (19) Proposal 1: Expected Value 1 1 1 • With probability you get $1, × 20 2 2 1 1 2 • With probability you get $2, × 21 4 2 1 1 3 • With probability you get $4, × 22 8 2 • … . The expected payoff is given by the sum of all these terms, i.e. ∞ 푡 ∞ 1 1 × 2푡−1 = = ∞ 2 2 푡=1 푡=1 FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (20) St. Petersburg Paradox • You should pay everything you own and more to purchase the 0.5 right to take this gamble! • Yet, in practice, no one is 0.4 prepared to pay such a high price. Why? 0.3 • Even though the expected 0.2 payoff is infinite, the distribution of payoffs is not 0.1 attractive… 0 . with 93% probability 0 20 40 60 we get $8 or less; . with 99% probability we get $64 or less FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (21) Proposal 2 • Bernoulli suggests that large gains should be weighted less. He suggests to use the natural logarithm. [Cremer - another great mathematician of the time - suggests the square root.] ∞ 푡 1 × ln 2푡−1 = ln 2 < ∞ 2 푡=1 According to this Bernoulli would pay at most 푒ln 2 = 2 to participate in this gamble FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (22) Representation of Preferences A preference ordering is (i) complete, (ii) transitive, (iii) continuous and [(iv) relatively stable] can be represented by a utility function, i.e. ′ ′ ′ 푐0, 푐1, … , 푐푆 ≻ 푐0, 푐1, … , 푐푆 ′ ′ ′ ⇔ 푈 푐0, 푐1, … , 푐푆 > 푈 푐0, 푐1, … , 푐푆 (preference ordering over lotteries – (푆 + 1)-dimensional space) FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (23) Indifference curves in ℝ2 (for 푆 = 2) 푐2 흅 푧 45° 푐1 푧 FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (24) Preferences over Prob. Distributions • Consider 푐0 fixed, 푐1 is a random variable • Preference ordering over probability distributions • Let . 푃 be a set of probability distributions with a finite support over a set 푋, . ≽ preference ordering over 푃 (that is, a subset of 푃 × 푃) FIN501 Asset Pricing Lecture 04 Risk Prefs & EU (25) Prob.
Recommended publications
  • Stochastic Dominance Under Independent Noise
    Stochastic Dominance Under Independent Noise∗ § Luciano Pomatto† Philipp Strack‡ Omer Tamuz May 21, 2019 Abstract Stochastic dominance is a crucial tool for the analysis of choice under risk. It is typically analyzed as a property of two gambles that are taken in isolation. We study how additional independent sources of risk (e.g. uninsurable labor risk, house price risk, etc.) can affect the ordering of gambles. We show that, perhaps surprisingly, background risk can be strong enough to render lotteries that are ranked by their expectation ranked in terms of first-order stochastic dominance. We extend our re- sults to second order stochastic dominance, and show how they lead to a novel, and elementary, axiomatization of mean-variance preferences. 1 Introduction A choice between risky prospects is often difficult to make. It is perhaps even harder to predict, since decision makers vary in their preferences. One exception is when the prospects are ordered in terms of stochastic dominance. In this case, a standard prediction is that the dominant option is chosen. For this reason, stochastic dominance has long been seen as a central concept in decision theory and the economics of information, and remains an area of active research (see, e.g. Müller et al., 2016; Cerreia-Vioglio et al., 2016, among others). More generally, stochastic dominance is an important tool for non-parametric comparison of distributions. arXiv:1807.06927v5 [math.PR] 20 May 2019 In the typical analysis of choices under risk, stochastic dominance is studied as a property of two prospects X and Y that are taken in isolation, without considering other risks the decision maker might be facing.
    [Show full text]
  • Risk Aversion and Stochastic Dominance: a Revealed Preference Approach
    Risk Aversion and Stochastic Dominance: A Revealed Preference Approach David M. Bruner† This version: December 2007 Abstract Theoretically, given a choice over two risky assets with equivalent expected returns, a risk averse expected utility maximizer should choose the second-order stochasti- cally dominant asset. We develop a theoretical framework that allows for decision error, which should decrease in risk aversion. We conduct an experiment using a risk preference elicitation mechanism to identify risk averse individuals and eval- uate the frequency that they choose the stochastically dominant of two lotteries. 75.76% of risk averse and 96.15% of very risk averse subjects chose at least 7 out of 10 dominant lotteries. Estimates of the effect of elicited risk aversion on the number of stochastically dominant lotteries chosen are positive and highly significant across specifications. The results suggest risk averse individuals make choices that satisfy stochastic dominance and violations are due, in large part, to decision error, which is decreasing in risk aversion. Keywords: stochastic dominance, risk, uncertainty, experiments JEL classification: C91, D81 †Department of Economics, University of Calgary, 2500 University Drive NW, SS 409, Calgary Alberta T2N 1N4, Canada. E-mail address: [email protected] I would like to thank Christopher Auld, John Boyce, Michael McKee, Rob Oxoby, and Nathaniel Wilcox for their many helpful comments and suggestions. This research was undertaken at the University of Calgary Behavioural and Experimental Economics Laboratory (CBEEL). Risk Aversion and Stochastic Dominance Bruner 1 Introduction This paper presents the results of an experiment intended to determine the frequency that risk averse individuals make choices that satisfy second-order stochastic dominance (SSD).
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 2 — Risk and Risk Aversion
    Chapter 2 — Risk and Risk Aversion The previous chapter discussed risk and introduced the notion of risk aversion. This chapter examines those concepts in more detail. In particular, it answers questions like, when can we say that one prospect is riskier than another or one agent is more averse to risk than another? How is risk related to statistical measures like variance? Risk aversion is important in finance because it determines how much of a given risk a person is willing to take on. Consider an investor who might wish to commit some funds to a risk project. Suppose that each dollar invested will return x dollars. Ignoring time and any other prospects for investing, the optimal decision for an agent with wealth w is to choose the amount k to invest to maximize [uw (+− kx( 1) )]. The marginal benefit of increasing investment gives the first order condition ∂u 0 = = u′( w +− kx( 1)) ( x − 1) (1) ∂k At k = 0, the marginal benefit isuw′( ) [ x − 1] which is positive for all increasing utility functions provided the risk has a better than fair return, paying back on average more than one dollar for each dollar committed. Therefore, all risk averse agents who prefer more to less should be willing to take on some amount of the risk. How big a position they might take depends on their risk aversion. Someone who is risk neutral, with constant marginal utility, would willingly take an unlimited position, because the right-hand side of (1) remains positive at any chosen level for k. For a risk-averse agent, marginal utility declines as prospects improves so there will be a finite optimum.
    [Show full text]
  • Stochastic Dominance for Project Screening and Selection Under Uncertainty by Adekunle M
    Stochastic Dominance for Project Screening and Selection under Uncertainty by Adekunle M. Adeyemo B.Sc., Chemical Engineering, University of Lagos (2006) S.M., Chemical Engineering Practice, MIT (2012) Submitted to the Department of Chemical Engineering in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy at the MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY February 2013 c Massachusetts Institute of Technology 2013. All rights reserved. Author.............................................................. Department of Chemical Engineering February 27 2013 Certified by.......................................................... Gregory J. McRae Hoyt C. Hottel Professor of Chemical Engineering (Emeritus) Thesis Supervisor Accepted by......................................................... Patrick S. Doyle Chairman, Department Committee on Graduate Theses 2 Stochastic Dominance for Project Screening and Selection under Uncertainty by Adekunle M. Adeyemo Submitted to the Department of Chemical Engineering on February 27 2013, in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Abstract At any given moment, engineering and chemical companies have a host of projects that they are either trying to screen to advance to the next stage of research or select from for implementation. These choices could range from a relative few, like the expansion of production capacity of a particular plant, to a large number, such as the screening for candidate compounds for the active pharmaceutical ingredient in a drug development program. This choice problem is very often further complicated by the presence of uncertainty in the project outcomes and introduces an element of risk into the screening or decision process. It is the task of the process designer to prune the set of available options, or in some cases, generate a set of possible choices, in the presence of such uncertainties to provide recommendations that are in line with the objectives of the ultimate decision maker.
    [Show full text]
  • Stochastic Dominance: the State of the Art in Agricultural Economics
    116 STOCHASTIC DOMINANCE: THE STATE OF THE ART IN AGRICULTURAL ECONOMICS by Mark J. Cochran* In recent years the family of stochastic dominance techniques has become a very popular way to rank alternative risk management strategies consistent with the Expected Utility Hypothesis (EUH). As such, much of the success and the shortcomings of stochastic dominance can be related to its foundation in the EUH. This paper will attempt to survey the use of stochastic dominance in the field of agricultural economics, discuss theoretical bases, and describe some recent developments in the applica- tion of risk analysis with stochastic dominance. The paper is divided into several different sections. The theoretical foundations, the axioms of the EUH, and technique descriptions will be presented first. The second section will review the recent experience in agriculture to elicit risk preferences. This will be followed by a brief comparison of stochastic dominance with other methodologies such as E-V analysis, E-Sh analysis, Target Motad and Mean Gini -Analysis. The final section will focus on some of the problems of implementing stochastic dominance and a review of selected works in progress designed to resolve some of these difficulties. Much of the discussion will focus on the trade-offs between Type I and Type II errors. A Type I error will correspond to a situation where an inaccurate ranking of the alternative management strategies has occurred. That is to say that the analysis results in a conclusion that alternative A is preferred to alternative B when in reality B is pre- ferred to A or there is no evidence to support preference of either alternative.
    [Show full text]
  • Portfolio Selection by Second Order Stochastic Dominance Based on the Risk Aversion Degree of Investors
    Portfolio Selection by Second Order Stochastic Dominance based on the Risk Aversion Degree of Investors by Leili Javanmardi A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Department of Chemical Engineering and Applied Chemistry University of Toronto c Copyright 2013 by Leili Javanmardi Abstract Portfolio Selection by Second Order Stochastic Dominance based on the Risk Aversion Degree of Investors Leili Javanmardi Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Department of Chemical Engineering and Applied Chemistry University of Toronto 2013 Second order stochastic dominance is an optimal rule for portfolio selection of risk averse investors when we only know that the investors' utility function is increasing concave. The main advantage of SSD is that it makes no assumptions regarding the return distributions of investment assets and has been proven to lead to utility maximization for the class of increasing concave utility functions. A number of different SSD models have emerged in the literature for portfolio selection based on SSD. However, current SSD models produce the same SSD efficient portfolio for all risk averse investors, regardless of their risk aversion degree. In this thesis, we have developed a new SSD efficiency model, SSD-DP, which unlike existing SSD efficiency models in the literature, provides an SSD efficient portfolio as a function of investors' risk aversion degrees. The SSD-DP model is based on the linear programming technique and finds an SSD efficient portfolio by minimizing the dual power transform (DP) of a weighted portfolio of assets for a given risk aversion degree. We show that the optimal portfolio of the proposed model is SSD efficient, i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1807.10895V5 [Econ.TH] 8 Aug 2020 the Standard View in Normative Decision Theory Holds We Should Rank Options by Their Expectations
    Exceeding Expectations: Stochastic Dominance as a General Decision Theory Christian J. Tarsney∗ Version 8, August 2020 Abstract The principle that rational agents should maximize expected utility or choicewor- thiness is intuitively plausible in many ordinary cases of decision-making under uncer- tainty. But it is less plausible in cases of extreme, low-probability risk (like Pascal's Mugging), and intolerably paradoxical in cases like the St. Petersburg and Pasadena games. In this paper I show that, under certain conditions, stochastic dominance reasoning can capture most of the plausible implications of expectational reasoning while avoiding most of its pitfalls. Specifically, given sufficient background uncertainty about the choiceworthiness of one's options, many expectation-maximizing gambles that do not stochastically dominate their alternatives `in a vacuum' become stochas- tically dominant in virtue of that background uncertainty. But, even under these conditions, stochastic dominance will not require agents to accept options whose ex- pectational superiority depends on sufficiently small probabilities of extreme payoffs. The sort of background uncertainty on which these results depend looks unavoidable for any agent who measures the choiceworthiness of her options in part by the total amount of value in the resulting world. At least for such agents, then, stochastic dom- inance offers a plausible general principle of choice under uncertainty that can explain more of the apparent rational constraints on such choices than has previously been recognized. 1 Introduction Given our epistemic limitations, every choice you or I will ever make involves some degree of risk. Whatever we do, it might turn out that we would have done better to do something else.
    [Show full text]
  • Choice Under Uncertainty
    Choice under Uncertainty Jonathan Levin October 2006 1 Introduction Virtually every decision is made in the face of uncertainty. While we often rely on models of certain information as you’ve seen in the class so far, many economic problems require that we tackle uncertainty head on. For instance, how should in- dividuals save for retirement when they face uncertainty about their future income, thereturnondifferent investments, their health and their future preferences? How should firms choose what products to introduce or prices to set when demand is uncertain? What policies should governments choose when there is uncertainty about future productivity, growth, inflation and unemployment? Our objective in the next few classes is to develop a model of choice behavior under uncertainty. We start with the von Neumann-Morgenstern expected utility model, which is the workhorse of modern economics. We’ll consider the foundations of this model, and then use it to develop basic properties of preference and choice in the presence of uncertainty: measures of risk aversion, rankings of uncertain prospects, and comparative statics of choice under uncertainty. As with all theoretical models, the expected utility model is not without its limitations. One limitation is that it treats uncertainty as objective risk – that is, as a series of coin flips where the probabilities are objectively known. Of course, it’s hard to place an objective probability on whether Arnold Schwarzenegger would be a good California governor despite the uncertainty. In response to this, we’ll discuss Savage’s (1954) approach to choice under uncertainty, which rather than assuming the existence of objective probabilities attached to uncertain prospects 1 makes assumptions about choice behavior and argues that if these assumptions are satisfied, a decision-maker must act as if she is maximizing expected utility with respect to some subjectively held probabilities.
    [Show full text]
  • Implementing Stochastic Dominance with Respect to a Function
    65 IMPLEMENTING STOCHASTIC DOMINANCE WITH RESPECT TO A FUNCTION Robert P. King and Lindon J. Robison r Introduction The expected utility hypothesis is the basis for much of the large body ... of theory concerned with decision making under uncertainty. It is the source of a general decision rule--expected utility maximization--which permits the synthesis of information on decision maker preferences and expectations in.· , a manner that ts both analytically elegant and intuitively appealing. Despite · its wide acceptance as a theoretical tool, however, the usefulness of the expected utility hypothesis in the solution of practical problems has been limited by several important operational difficulties. One particularly serious problem associated with the implementation of the expected utility hypothesis is that empirically estimated utility func­ tions often prove to be unreliable representations of decision maker prefer­ ences (Robison and King). Sources of error include shortcomings in the design of elicitation interviews, failure to consider more than a single performance criterion by which choices are evaluated, and respondents' own lack of precise knowledge about their preferences. Despite such problems, a utility function, once estimated, is usually treated as though it were an exact representation of preferences when it is used to order alternative choices, and any absolute difference in the expected .utilities associated with two possible action· choices is taken as a clear indication that one is preferred to the other. As a result, inaccuracies in an elicited utility function can cause the rejection of an action choice that is actually pre­ ferred by the decision maker. Imprecision in the measurement of decision maker preferences can be recognized explicitly in 9 decision analysis by using an efficiency criterion rather than a single valued utility function to evaluate alternative choices.
    [Show full text]
  • Stochastic Dominance Under Independent Noise∗
    Stochastic Dominance Under Independent Noise∗ Luciano Pomatto† Philipp Strack‡ Omer Tamuz§ May 20, 2019 Abstract Stochastic dominance is a crucial tool for the analysis of choice under risk. It is typically analyzed as a property of two gambles that are taken in isolation. We study how additional independent sources of risk (e.g. uninsurable labor risk, house price risk, etc.) can affect the ordering of gambles. We show that, perhaps surprisingly, background risk can be strong enough to render lotteries that are ranked by their expectation ranked in terms of first-order stochastic dominance. We extend our results to second order stochastic dominance, and show how they lead to a novel, and elementary, axiomatization of mean-variance preferences. 1 Introduction A choice between risky prospects is often difficult to make. It is perhaps even harder to predict, since decision makers vary in their preferences. One exception is when the prospects are ordered in terms of stochastic dominance. In this case, a standard prediction is that the dominant option is chosen. For this reason, stochastic dominance has long been seen as a central concept in decision theory and the economics of information, and remains an area of active research (see, e.g. Müller et al., 2016; Cerreia-Vioglio et al., 2016, among others). More generally, stochastic dominance is an important tool for non-parametric comparison of distributions. In the typical analysis of choices under risk, stochastic dominance is studied as a property of two prospects X and Y that are taken in isolation, without considering other risks the decision maker might be facing.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. Expected Utility, Risk Aversion and Stochastic Dominance
    1. Expected utility, risk aversion and stochastic dominance 1.1 Expected utility 1.1.1 Description of risky alternatives 1.1.2 Preferences over lotteries 1.1.3 The expected utility theorem 1.2 Monetary lotteries and risk aversion 1.2.1 Monetary lotteries and the expected utility framework 1.2.2 Risk aversion 1.2.3 Measures of risk aversion 1.2.4 Risk aversion and portfolio selection 1.3 Stochastic dominance 1.3.1 First degree stochastic dominance 1.3.2 Second degree stochastic dominance 1.3.3 Second degree stochastic monotonic dominance 1 The objective of this part is to examine the choice of under uncertainty. We divide this chapter in 3 sections. The first part begins by developing a formal apparatus for modeling risk. We then apply this framework to the study of preferences over risky alternatives. Finally, we examine conditions of the preferences that guarantee the existence of a utility function that represents these preferences. In the second part, we focus on the particular case in which the outcomes are monetary payoffs. Obviously, this case is very interesting in the area of finance. In this part we present the concept of risk aversion and its measures. In the last part, we are interested in the comparison of two risky assets in the case in which we have a limited knowledge of individuals’ preferences. This comparison leads us to the three concepts of stochastic dominance. 2 1.1 Expected utility 1.1.1 Description of risky alternatives Let us suppose that an agent faces a choice among a number of risky alternatives.
    [Show full text]
  • Application of Stochastic Dominance Tests to Utility Resource Planning Under Uncertainty
    &qy Vol. 15. No. 11, pp. 949-961, 1990 0360-5442/90 $3.00 + 0.00 Printed in Great Britain. All tights resmwd Copyright6 1990 Pergamon Press plc APPLICATION OF STOCHASTIC DOMINANCE TESTS TO UTILITY RESOURCE PLANNING UNDER UNCERTAINTY JONATHAN A. LESSER Washington State Energy Office, 809 Legion Way SE., Olympia, WA 98504-1211, U.S.A. (Receiued 2 Mmch 1990) Atic&Uncertainty and risk have become critical elements of electric-utility planning. Planning has become more complex because of uncertainties about future growth in electricity demand, cost and performance of new generating resources, performance of demand-side resources that increase end-use efficiencies, and overall structure and competition within electricity markets. Current methodologies for incorporating risk and uncertainty into planning are limited by their potential lack of consistency with economic theory, or the necessity to specify expected utility functions that are difficult to defend. In this paper, we describe these limitations and suggest a new approach to utility planning under uncertainty, called stochastic dominance, which can augment or, in some cases, replace existing methods to evaluate uncertainty. Stochastic dominance permits com- parison of resource plans with uncertain performance in a theoretically consistent manner, without having to assess or justify individual expected utility functions. Stochastic dominance tests can also be implemented with little additional effort over current decision methodologies, especially those methodologies that rely on Monte-Carlo models as a planning tool. Stochastic dominance tests can incorporate alternative risk attitudes of decision makers more easily than existing empirical methods and therefore provide more robust solutions to decision making under uncertainty.
    [Show full text]