An Inferentialist Account of (Implicit) Definition Dan Kapan

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

An Inferentialist Account of (Implicit) Definition Dan Kapan Abstract: PhDLX 2018: PhDs in Logic X April 13, 2018 An Inferentialist Account of (Implicit) Definition Dan Kapan This paper explores the intersection of two lines of thought. Each line of thought is poten- tially independently explicable, but the conclusion is more powerful by considering where they come together. The first line of thought concerns a philosophical account of definition. Definitions, the thought goes, are of particular philosophical significance not only in themselves but for the fact that all inquiry begins by introducing the terms in which that inquiry will be couched. Sometimes such definitions are given more-or-less explicitly, so Kant begins the Critique of Pure Reason by defining analytic and synthetic judgments as: “In all judgments in which the relation of a subject to the predicate is thought (I take into consideration affirmative judgments only, the subsequent applica- tion to negative judgments being easily made), this relation is possible in two different ways. Either the predicate B belongs to the subject A; or B lies outside the concept A, although it does indeed stand in connection with it. In the one case I entitle the judgment analytic, in the other synthetic” (B10– 11; underlining and bold are my own). Of course no one takes Kant to have actually given us a definite meaning yet with these words (even if all these concepts are clear). We only find out what he means by analytic and synthetic by reading further and understanding what this distinction allow him to conclude about reason, understanding, and which sorts of judgments he takes to be analytic and synthetic. Even in mathematical works, we often come to understand the meaning of a term by seeing how they are used, reasoned about, and what they let us prove. In other words, what the word means is more accurately specified by how we come to use it to reason. One contrast I am here invoking is a distinction between “explicit” definitions—in which a word or linguistic item generally is defined by saying explicitly what it means, i.e. specifying something like an equivalent expression that can take its place (given the proviso that this might involve some rephrasing)—and “implicit” definitions—in which a word or linguistic item generally acquires its meaning by saying something about how it is used or how it figures in true assertion. My contention is that the latter is the more ubiquitous and important notion, and that the principal way such items acquire meaning through implicit definition is via their use in good inference. I therefore want to defend an inferentialist account of implicit definition and my hope is to explain how this can help us understand cases of genuine implicit definition. By “genuine” implicit definition, I mean implicit definition that need not be reducible to an explicit definition conferring a meaning. One problem with this goal, however, is that there are well-known results in the logic of definitions that render it impossible. I have in mind, of course, Beth’s Theorem, which proves that something can be implicitly defined if and only if it can be explicitly defined. This leads me to the second line of thought of the paper. In response to certain paradoxes in logic—often the result of definition—philosophers and logicians have sought to limit the scope of what counts as good definition. For example the 1 Abstract: PhDLX 2018: PhDs in Logic X April 13, 2018 sentence which asserts of itself that absurdity follows—i.e. the Curry Sentence c =df: c !?— leads to a paradox. Granting that A ! A is always valid, then we may reason that c ! c and thus (since c =df: c !?) that c ! (c !?). This of course reduces to c !?. This is equivalent to c, so we’ve just deduced that c. But c together with c !? gives us ? via modus ponens, but surely this is bad. How can merely saying what a sentence means gets us a substantive truth? Worse the “truth” here is absurdity, so it in fact gets us all the truths (and falsehoods). Surely a sentence like the Curry sentence is, if not meaningless, poorly defined. I agree that paradoxes like the above give us reason to draw new distinctions, but I don’t think such distinctions should amount to ruling out a large class of potentially good definitions. Paradoxes gives us reasons to draw new distinctions, but ideally not to simply deny the phenomena. Part of what Beth’s theorem gives us (more accurate, one half of it, which was already attributable to a result by Padoa) is that—given some presuppositions about the underlying logic—properly formed explicit definitions are guaranteed to be safe. The implication is that anything outside of those shouldn’t be thought of as just risky, but in fact as meaningless or confused. I examine the presuppositions of the underlying logic in order to draw new distinctions within what the standard account calls definition. In particular, I want to examine the space between properly formed explicit definition and good implicit definition to see what structure we might find there.1 These two lines of thoughts intersect in the thought that there might be good implicit definitions that don’t yet amount to properly-formed explicit definition. The second line of thought provides the resources for making some distinctions between these two sorts of definition, while the first gives us a philosophically informed understanding of meaning to make such distinctions plausible. I proceed as follows in the paper: I begin by rehearsing the standard account of definition and explaining how adequacy of definition is envisaged.2 Throughout the rest of the paper I do not attempt to challenge these criteria. I accept the orthodoxy, but try to draw some internal distinctions. Following this I rehearse some problems standardly associated with accounts of implicit definition.3 I also explain how the standard account understands implicit definition. Next, I turn to my own account of definition. I begin by explaining what an inferentialist theory of meaning is, and what it means to understand meaning in terms of role in inference.4 Next, I explain how I conceive of implicit definition. In contrast to the standard account of implicit definition, where it is the taking to be true of a sentence or theory containing the defined term, on my account it is the taking to be good of an implication or inferential relation in which such new vocabulary appears. Following this I introduce several other notions of definition and the connections between them. Under classical logic they all collapse into one another (as is well known from Beth’s Theorem), but I hope my analysis there makes plausible a layer between them. 1Work by Nuel Belnap and Anil Gupta shares a similar ambition here: i.e. to elucidate a different notion of “good definition” (Gupta and Belnap, 1993). 2My main sources for examining the “standard account” may be found in: (Belnap, 1993; Gupta, 2015; Suppes, 1957). 3See e.g. (Hale and Wright, 2000, 2001; Horwich, 1997, 1998). 4I here rely heavily on e.g. (Brandom, 2009; Peregrin, 2014). 2 Abstract: PhDLX 2018: PhDs in Logic X April 13, 2018 References Belnap, N. (1993). On rigorous definitions. Philosophical studies, 72(2):115–146. Beth, E. (1953). On padoa’s method in the theory of definition. (15):330–339. Brandom, R. (2009). Articulating reasons. Harvard University Press. Gupta, A. (2015). Definitions. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015). Gupta, A. and Belnap, N. D. (1993). The revision theory of truth. MIT Press. Hale, B. and Wright, C. (2000). Implicit definition and the a priori. In Boghossian, P. and Peacocke, C., editors, New essays on the a priori, pages 286–319. Oxford: OUP. Hale, B. and Wright, C. (2001). The Reason’s Proper Study: Essays Toward a Neo-Fregean Philosophy of Mathematics. Clarendon Press. Horwich, P. (1997). Implicit definition, analytic truth, and apriori knowledge. Nous, 31(4):423–440. Horwich, P. (1998). Meaning. Oxford University Press. Kant, I. (1999). Critique of pure reason. Cambridge University Press. Padoa, A. (1967). Logical introduction to any deductive theory. In van Heijenoort, J., editor, From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931, pages 118–123. Harvard University Press. Peregrin, J. (2014). Inferentialism: Why Rules Matter. Palgrave Macmillan. Suppes, P. (1957). Introduction to logic. The University series in undergraduate mathematics. D. Van Nostrand Company, Inc. 3.
Recommended publications
  • Kripke's Theory of Truth
    Kripke’s Theory of Truth (for the strong Kleene scheme) Presented by Christopher Gauker Version: July 26, 2006 Contemporary discussions of truth often make reference to Kripke’s theory of truth (presented by Kripke only his 1975 Journal of Philosophy paper). What Kripke did was show how to interpret a language in such a way that it contains its own truth predicate. The fact that the language he describes contains its own truth predicate is proved by means of something called a fixed-point theorem. I have written this document and posted it on the web because it is hard to find a presentation of Kripke’s theory that will be understandable even to readers who have had only a first course in logic. It is my intention that this presentation will be understandable to all readers who have been exposed to at least the following: The languages of ordinary predicate logic. Recursive definitions of truth in a structure for such languages. (Structures are also called models or interpretations.) The basic concepts and notation of set theory, such as curly brackets, membership (“∈”), inclusion (“⊆”), ordered n-tuples, relations and functions. Kripke’s theory of truth builds on a three-valued interpretation of a language. (So sentences may be neither true nor false (N) as well as (T) or false (F).) Various three- valued valuation schemes may be used. Here we will consider only the strong Kleene scheme, which is the only one most people care about. I can take no credit for this presentation. It is nothing more than a distillation from the more general presentation in Anil Gupta and Nuel Belnap’s book, The Revision Theory of Truth (MIT Press, 1993) (who in turn acknowledge debts to Fitting and Visser).
    [Show full text]
  • A Note on Extension, Intension, and Truth Author(S): Anil Gupta and Nuel Belnap Source: the Journal of Philosophy, Vol
    Journal of Philosophy, Inc. A Note on Extension, Intension, and Truth Author(s): Anil Gupta and Nuel Belnap Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 84, No. 3 (Mar., 1987), pp. 168-174 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2026597 Accessed: 28/05/2009 11:06 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jphil. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy. http://www.jstor.org 168 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY A NOTE ON EXTENSION, INTENSION, AND TRUTH* I T is common knowledge that two predicates may coincide in extension but differ in intension and that, for any predicate, one can construct an infinity of coextensional predicates that differ in intension.
    [Show full text]
  • Gupta Comment
    Discussion of Anil Gupta's “Outline of an Account of Experience” The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation Byrne, Alex et al. "Discussion of Anil Gupta's “Outline of an Account of Experience”." Analytic Philosophy 59, 1 (March 2018): 75-88 © 1999-2020 John Wiley & Sons, Inc. As Published http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/phib.12121 Publisher Wiley Version Author's final manuscript Citable link https://hdl.handle.net/1721.1/123434 Terms of Use Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-Share Alike Detailed Terms http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-sa/4.0/ Comments on Gupta Alex Byrne 1. Transitions Fundamental to Gupta’s picture is the idea of a “rational transition”. The role of experience, he thinks, “is not to provide the subject knowledge of anything or to bestow a rational or justificatory status on…beliefs or judgments”, but to “render rational certain transitions, including transitions from views to judgments”. His central non-perceptual example of a rational transition involves modus-ponens reasoning from the two premises, B and if B then C, to the conclusion C. And that does indeed seem to be rational or reasonable, in some sense of these elastic terms. Something is going right if someone reasons in this way—at least it’s better than affirming the consequent. Since valid reasoning, as Gupta emphasizes, implies nothing about whether the premises are true, or justifiably believed, or known, this example might seem to suggest that the rationality of transitions and the rationality of beliefs are quite different matters.
    [Show full text]
  • M.A. Philosophy Programme Is a Two Year Course Divided Into Four-Semester
    UNIVERSITY OF DELHI MASTER OF ARTS (Acronym for the Course) (Effective from Academic year 2018-19) PROGRAMME BROCHURE (M.A.) Department of Philosophy Faculty of Arts University of Delhi Delhi-110007 2 University of Delhi Examination Branch Date: 18 June 2018 Courses: M. A. in Philosophy Check List of new Course evaluation for AC Consideration S.No. Parameters Status 1. About the Department 2 Introduction to CBCS 3. Programme Structure 4. Codification of Papers 5. Scheme of Examinations 6. Pass Percentage 7. Promotion Criteria 8. Division Criteria 9. Qualifying Papers 10. Span Period 11. Attendance Requirements 12. Course content for each Paper 13. List of Readings 2 3 I ABOUT THE DEPARTMENT Faculty of Arts, North Campus, Delhi University The History and Profile of the Department of Philosophy, University of Delhi. Located in the heart of the main Humanities Block of the Arts Faculty, North Cam- pus, facing an inner quadrangle garden, the Department of Philosophy is one of the oldest in the University of Delhi. This building constructed in the early part of the twentieth century is well known for its red brick colonial structure. This Department began as a combined Department of Philosophy and Psychology in the year 1953. The Department of Psychology became independent in 1962. Since then the Department of Philosophy is an Autonomous Department. Various distinguished scholars who have either taught or been associated with the Department of Philosophy, Delhi University include N.V. Banerjee, S.S Barlingay, R. C. Pandeya, Margaret Chatterjee, S.K. Saxena, Ram Chandra Gandhi and Mrinal Miri. A large number of eminent philosophers from India and abroad have lectured in the De- partment.
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae 2015 JAMES THOMAS CARGILE Place and Date
    Curriculum Vitae 2015 JAMES THOMAS CARGILE Place and Date of Birth Ponca City, Oklahoma - 13 April 1938 Education University of Utah, B.A. 1957 University of Virginia, M.A. 1962 University of Cambridge, Ph.D. 1965 Teaching Experience T.A., University of Virginia, 1960-62 Tutor, University of Cambridge, 1962-65 Assistant Professor, University of Virginia, 1965-69 Visiting Asst. Professor, University of Michigan, Fall 1968 Associate Professor, University of Virginia, 1969-80 Visiting Assoc. Professor, University of Illinois, Fall 1970 Professor, University of Virginia, 1981-present FBI Academy (taught logic and ethics) Areas of Specialization Ethics, Epistemology, Metaphysics, Logic, Philosophy of Language Honors and Awards All-University Outstanding Teaching Award, 1997 Publications Books Paradoxes: A Study in Form and Predication, Cambridge University Press, 1979. (This book was re-issued in paperback, 2009). Articles “Logical Form” in The Force of Argument, ed. By Jonathan Lear and Alex Oliver, Routledge, 2010, pp.48-67. Critical Notice of The Language of Thought Revisited by Jerry Fodor (Oxford 2008) in Analysis, February, 2010, pp.1-10. “The Fallacy of Epistemicism” Oxford Studies in Epistemology. 2006. pp. 33-67. “On ‘Alexander’s Dictum’” Topoi vol. 22 (2003). “On Russell’s Argument Against Resemblance Nominalism” Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2003. “Panteismo” in Arete vol XIII no. 2, 2001. Comments on Christopher Peacocke’s Being Known for the Book Symposium Philosophical Books 2001. “Skepticism and Possibilities” Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 2000. “Proposition and Tense” Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 1999. “On an Argument Against Closure” Nous, June 1999. “The Problem of Induction”, Philosophy 73, 1998.
    [Show full text]
  • Anil Gupta, Fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences: Biographical Bibliometric Fact Sheets
    Anil Gupta, Fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences: Biographical Bibliometric Fact Sheets E. R. Prakasan and V. L. Kalyane Scientific Information Resource Division, Knowledge Management Group, Bhabha Atomic Research Centre, Trombay, Mumbai, India – 400 085 *e-mail: [email protected] Anil Gupta, Distinguished Professor Logic, Philosophy of Language, Metaphysics, Epistemology PhD, Pittsburgh, 1977 [email protected] Anil Gupta is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, professor of History and Philosophy of Science, and a fellow of the Center for Philosophy of Science. He is also a fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences. Before joining the department in 2001, he taught at Indiana, Illinois at Chicago, and McGill [1]. Materials and Methods Standard bibliometric methods were used [2-70] for the analysis of the Bibliography (see Appendix) of Anil Gupta [71-117]. Results He is the author of The Logic of Common Nouns (Yale, 1980) and Empiricism and Experience (Oxford, 2006), and a co-author (with Nuel Belnap) of The Revision Theory of Truth (MIT, 1993). Gupta has received fellowships from the NEH and the ACLS, and he was a fellow at the Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences, Stanford, in 1998-99. Gupta’s main research interests lie in logic, philosophy of language, metaphysics, and epistemology. Topics that are of special interest to him include definitions, truth, meaning, and perception. 50 7 Number of publications 45 Cumulative Number of Publications 6 40 ations c i 35 ons ubl 5 P cati 30 of 4 25 publi
    [Show full text]
  • Conditionals in Theories of Truth⋆
    Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Conditionals in Theories of Truth? Anil Gupta · Shawn Standefer Received: date / Accepted: date Abstract We argue that distinct conditionals|conditionals that are gov- erned by different logics|are needed to formalize the rules of Truth Intro- duction and Truth Elimination. We show that revision theory, when enriched with the new conditionals, yields an attractive theory of truth. We go on to compare this theory with one recently proposed by Hartry Field. Keywords Truth, paradox, revision theory, conditionals, circular definitions ? This is a near-final version of our paper published in the Journal of Philosophical Logic. Small differences may exist, so please cite the published version, available at http: //dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10992-015-9393-3. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh E-mail: [email protected] Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne E-mail: [email protected] 2 Anil Gupta, Shawn Standefer 1 Introduction The conditionals we will be concerned with are those used in stating the rules for truth, Truth Introduction (TI) and Truth Elimination (TE): (TI) If A, then `A' is true; and (TE) If `A' is true, then A. We will argue that the two conditionals here are different: they do not mean the same; they are not governed by the same logic. In outline, our argument will be as follows. We will take it that (TI) and (TE) are the best formulations we have of the principal rules governing truth. Aristotle suggested these rules in the Categories; the medievals called them `Aristotle's Rules'; and at least on this bit of logic no one has improved on Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • On Learning from Experience
    ON LEARNING FROM EXPERIENCE by Ori Beck B.A. in Philosophy and Criminology, Bar-Ilan University, 2005 M.A. in Philosophy, Tel-Aviv University, 2008 M.A. in Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh, 2015 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Kenneth P. Dietrich School of Arts and Sciences in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2015 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH KENNETH P. DIETRICH SCHOOL OF ARTS AND SCIENCES This dissertation was presented by Ori Beck It was defended on September 9, 2015 and approved by Anil Gupta, Alan Ross Anderson Distinguished Professor of Philosophy Edouard Machery, Professor of History and Philosophy of Science John McDowell, Distinguished University Professor of Philosophy Mark Wilson, Professor of Philosophy Dissertation Director: Anil Gupta, Alan Ross Anderson Distinguished Professor of Philosophy ii Copyright c by Ori Beck 2015 iii ON LEARNING FROM EXPERIENCE Ori Beck, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2015 How can I come to justifiably (or knowledgeably) believe that there is an owl over there on the basis of my seeing its being there? More generally: How can we come to justifiably (or knowledgeably) believe things on the basis of our experiences? I argue that we can make do with a simple and intuitive answer: Experiences present us with objects, properties, relations and states of affairs (or, events). If we have the capacities to tell what these presented entities are, we can justifiably (or knowledgeably) form appropriate beliefs on the basis of the experiences. I call this position the “Simple Picture” (or, “SP”). SP stands in contrast to the Representationalist epistemology, according to which expe- riences do not quite present us with entities, as represent how the world is.
    [Show full text]
  • Presence to Self: an Essay on the Phenomenal Origins of Intentionality
    PRESENCE TO SELF: AN ESSAY ON THE PHENOMENAL ORIGINS OF INTENTIONALITY by Christopher Frey B.A. University of California, Los Angeles, 2001 Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Department of Philosophy in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy University of Pittsburgh 2011 UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY This dissertation was presented by Christopher Frey It was defended on 04/08/2011 and approved by Anil Gupta, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh John McDowell, Distinguished University Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh Robert Brandom, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh Karl Schafer, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh Christopher Hill, Professor of Philosophy, Brown University Dissertation Director: Anil Gupta, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh ii Copyright c by Christopher Frey 2011 iii PRESENCE TO SELF: AN ESSAY ON THE PHENOMENAL ORIGINS OF INTENTIONALITY Christopher Frey, PhD University of Pittsburgh, 2011 My dissertation is an examination of an oft-invoked but insufficiently understood feature of perceptual experience, namely, its presentational character. We open our eyes and a world is before us. Someone strikes a tuning fork, and a sound is simply present. To experience is always, in part, to appreciate phenomenally something as other or as before one; it is always, in part, to appreciate phenomenally a manifest opposition between the self|that before which the other is present|and the other|that which is present before the self. I call this aspect of experiential phenomenality, this universally appreciable but non-sensuous sense of otherness in experience, phenomenal presence.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Parmenides This Page Intentionally Left Blank PLATO's PARMENIDES
    Plato's Parmenides This page intentionally left blank PLATO'S PARMENIDES Constance C. Meinwald New York Oxford Oxford University Press 1991 Oxford University Press Oxford New York Toronto Delhi Bombay Calcutta Madras Karachi Petaling Jaya Singapore Hong Kong Tokyo Nairobi Dar es Salaam Cape Town Melbourne Auckland and associated companies in Berlin Ibadan Copyright © 1991 by Constance C. Meinwald Published by Oxford University Press 200 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016 Oxford is a registered trademark of Oxford University Press All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Meinwald, Constance C. Plato's Parmenides / Constance C. Meinwald. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references. Includes index. ISBN 0-19-506445-3 1. Plato. Parmenides. 2. Reasoning. 3. Socrates. 4. Zeno, of Elea. I. Title. B378.M45 1991 90-35419 184—dc20 1 3 5 7 9 8 6 4 2 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper ACKNOWLEDGMENTS My work on Plato's Parmenides began as a 1987 doctoral dissertation at Princeton University. The present book was completed after I had joined the faculty of the University of Illinois at Chicago. Thus, i have received help on this project from many individuals. First of all, I owe thanks to Michael Frede for helping me choose my topic and for his insightful advice over the years. But others at Princeton have given vital help, especially David Furley, Sally Haslanger, Mark Johnston, and Wolfgang Mann.
    [Show full text]
  • Empiricism and Experience (Henceforth, E&E)
    Equivalence, Reliability, and Convergence: Replies to McDowell, Peacocke, and Neta Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh I am grateful to John McDowell, Ram Neta, and Christopher Peacocke for their critical attention to my book.1 Their objections and questions are exactly on the mark, and they help me to place the proposals I have made in a clearer light. McDowell and Peacocke challenge fundamental principles I use to motivate my account, and I should address their arguments first. Then I shall turn to Neta’s objection, which concerns a central element of my account. I. McDowell and the Equivalence Constraint McDowell claims that the very first steps leading to the account I offer are deeply flawed and, furthermore, that my account is unattractive when compared to his own version of disjunctivism.2 I want to examine the argument McDowell mounts for these claims. One of my first steps in the book is to accept the following Equivalence constraint. Let the given in an experience e of a subject S be the total rational contribution of e to S’s view of the world. Then the Equivalence constraint is as follows: Equivalence constraint: Experiences that are subjectively identical yield the same given. Consider an experiencing subject S in two possible situations: in one, S undergoes a veridical experience e, say of a pink cube, and rationally arrives at the belief that there is a pink cube; in the other, S undergoes a subjectively identical experience e*, say an illusion, and arrives at the same 1Empiricism and Experience (henceforth, E&E). 2“The Given in Experience: Comment on Gupta.” All parenthetical references to McDowell are to the pages of this paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Common Sense As Evidence: Against Revisionary Ontology and Skepticism1
    In Peter A. French and Howard K. Wettstein (eds.) Midwest Studies in Philosophy, vol.XXXII: Truth and Its Deformities (Wiley-Blackwell, 2008): 53-78. Common Sense as Evidence: Against Revisionary Ontology and Skepticism1 Thomas Kelly Princeton University 0. How far might philosophy succeed in undermining our ordinary, common sense views about what there is or what we know? Some philosophers suggest: not very far. Thus, according to David Lewis One comes to philosophy already endowed with a stock of opinions. It is not the business of philosophy either to undermine or justify these preexisting opinions to any great extent, but only to try to discover ways of expanding them into an orderly system (1973: 88). Compare Kit Fine: In this age of post-Moorean modesty, many of us are inclined to doubt that philosophy is in possession of arguments that might genuinely serve to undermine what we ordinarily believe. It may perhaps be conceded that the arguments of the skeptic appear to be utterly compelling; but the Mooreans among us will hold that the very plausibility of our ordinary beliefs is reason enough for supposing that there must be something wrong in the skeptic’s arguments, even if we are unable to say what it is. In so far then, as the pretensions of philosophy to provide a world view rest upon its claims to be in possession of the epistemological high ground, those pretensions had better be given up (2001:2). 1 This paper is part of an ongoing, if somewhat slow-moving, campaign on behalf of common sense; an initial foray was Kelly (2005).
    [Show full text]