The Serpentine Wall of Separation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Serpentine Wall of Separation Michigan Law Review Volume 101 Issue 6 2003 The Serpentine Wall of Separation John Witte Jr. Emory University Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, First Amendment Commons, Legal History Commons, Religion Law Commons, and the Supreme Court of the United States Commons Recommended Citation John Witte Jr., The Serpentine Wall of Separation, 101 MICH. L. REV. 1869 (2003). Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/mlr/vol101/iss6/21 This Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Michigan Law Review at University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Michigan Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THAT SERPENTINE WALL OF SEPARATION John Witte, Jr.* THOMAS JEFFERSON AND THE WALL OF SEPARATION BETWEEN CHURCH AND STATE. By Daniel L. Dreisbach. New York and Lon­ don: New York University Press. 2002. Pp. x, 283. $42: SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE. By Philip Hamburger. Cam­ bridge and London: Harvard University Press. 2002. Pp. xiii, 514. $49.95. I. INTRODUCTION "The task of separating the secular from the religious in education is one of magnitude, intricacy, and delicacy," Justice Jackson wrote, concurring in McCollum v. Board of Education, the Supreme Court's first religion in public schools case.1 "To lay down a sweeping constitu­ tional doctrine" of absolute separation of church and state "is to decree a uniform ...unchanging standard for countless school boards representing and serving highly localized groups which not only differ from each other but which themselves from time to time change atti­ tudes. "2 If we persist in this experiment, Justice Jackson warned his brethren, "we are likely to make the legal 'wall of separation between church and state' as winding as the famous serpentine wall designed by Mr. Jefferson for the University he founded."3 While a majority of the United States Supreme Court embarked on a four-decade project of building this "serpentine wall,"4 Justice Jackson took little further part in the effort. He continued to regard the separation of church and state as essential to the protection of * Jonas Robitscher Professor of Law, Director of Law and Religion Program, Director of Center for the Interdisciplinary Study of Religion, Emory University. B.A. 19 82, Calvin College; J.D. 19 85, Harvard. - Ed. My thanks to Harold Rerman, Russell Hittinger, Robert A. Schapiro, and Charles A. Shanor for their helpful comments on a draft of this Review. 1. McCollum v. Bd. of Educ., 333 U.S. 203, 237 (1948) (Jackson, J., concurring). 2. Id. 3. Id. at 238; see also DREISBACH, p. 109. 4. DREISBACH, pp. 100-04 (summarizing cases); HAMBURGER, pp. 463-78. The most recent Supreme Court cases where the separationist principle dominated the Court's rea­ soning were Texas Mont hly Inc. v. Bullock, 489 U.S. 1 (1989); Agui lar v. Felt on, 473 U.S. 402 (1985); and Larki n v. Grendel' s Den Inc., 459 U.S. 116 (19 82). 1869 1870 Michigan Law Review [Vol. 101:1869 religious liberty, along with the freedoms of conscience,5 exercise, and speech.6 But he had no patience with unilateral or extreme applica­ tions of any of these First Amendment principles,7 not least the princi­ ple of separation of church and state. Imprudent application of this latter principle, he wrote, would draw the Court into "passionate dialectics" about "nonessential details" that were often better left to state and local governments to resolve.8 In his last years on the bench, Jackson thus led the Court in a case that denied standing to a party who argued that religious instruction in a public school violated the separation of church and state.9 He was the sole dissenter in a church property dispute case, where the Court read the principle of separa­ tion to require a state to defer to the internal religious law of the dis­ putants rather than apply its own state laws.10 He dissented again from the Court's decision to uphold a public school program that gave stu­ dents release time to participate in religious events off site.11 Arguing that this was precisely the kind of case where the principle of separa­ tion did apply, he complained: "The wall which the Court was pro­ fessing to erect between Church and State has become even more warped and twisted than I expected. "12 For all his growing misgivings about separationism, however, even this bold dissenter on the Court,13 well trained in legal history,14 never 5. See, e.g., United States v. Ballard, 32 2 U.S. 78, 92-9 5 (19 44) (Jackson, J., dissenting from decision to use the truth of a professed religious belief to question a party's sincerity); Prince v. Massachusetts, 321 U.S. 158, 176-78 (1944) (Jackson, J., dissenting from decision to uphold child-labor laws against distribution of religious literature by a minor); West Virginia State Bd. of Educ. v. Barnette, 319 U.S. 642 (19 43) (Jackson, J., writing for the majority, ex­ empting Jehovah's Witnesses from compulsory flag salute). 6. See ROBERT H. JACKSON, THE SUPREME COURT IN THE AMERICAN SYSTEM OF GOVERNMENT 76-77 (1955); Paul A. Freund, Mr. Just ice Jacks on and Indi vi dual Ri ghts , in MR. JUSTICE JACKSON: FOUR LECTURES IN HIS HONOR 29 , 36-43 (1969) (summarizing cases). 7. See, e.g., Kunz v. New York, 340 U.S. 29 0, 29 5-314 (1951) (Jackson, J., dissenting from holding that a city may not deny a license to a Baptist preacher in a public park); Terme­ niello v. Chicago, 337 U.S. 1, 13-37 (1949) (Jackson, J., dissenting from holding that free speech protects anti-Semitic hate speech that causes riot); Saia v. New York, 334 U.S. 558, 566-72 (1948) (Jackson, J., dissenting fromholding that banning religious broadcasts without a license violates free speech); Murdock v. Pennsylvania, 319 U.S. 105, 117-34 (1 943) (Reed and Jackson, JJ., dissenting from holding that free-exercise rights prohibit laws requiring re­ ligious solicitors to procure a license in advance). 8. Zorach v. Clauson, 343 U.S. 306, 32 5 (1952) (Jackson, J., dissenting); see also JACKSON, supra note 6, at 65- 83 (examining role of Supreme Court in state and local dis­ putes). 9. Doremus v. Bd. of Educ., 342 U.S. 42 9 (1952). 10. Kedroff v. St. Nicholas Cathedral, 344 U.S. 94, 12 6-32 (1 952) (Jackson, J., dissent- ing). 11. Zorach, 343 U.S. at 32 3-25 (Jackson, J., dissenting). 12 . Id. at 32 5. 13. See EUGENE c. GERHART, AMERICA'S ADVOCATE: ROBERT H. JACKSON 294-300 (1958). Of Justice Jackson's 32 4 Supreme Court opinions, 109 were dissents, 63 concur- May 2003] . The. Serpentine Wall 1871 once questioned the historical foundation or constitutional imperative of strict separationism. In Everson v. Board of Education,15 the Supreme Court for the first time applied the First Amendment disestablishment guarantee to the states. Justice Black, Jackson's nemesis,16 wrote for the Everson majority. After a lengthy historical recitation, Black quoted Thomas Jefferson's famous 1802 Letter to the Danbury Baptist Association as dispositive evidence that the "First Amendment has erected a wall of separation between church and state" that "must be kept high and impregnable."17 Though Jackson dissented from the Everson holding, he accepted the Court's account of. the history and meaning of the First Amendment.18 Jackson was concerned about the rhetorical "undertones" of "advocating complete and uncompromising separation of Church from state."19 He was not concerned about the historical underpinnings of separationism itself. Indeed, Jackson thought his views to be in full accord with the intent of the founders - not least his hero President Thomas Jefferson.20 Justice Jackson might well have come to a different opinion had he enjoyed the luxury of reading the two exquisite books here under re­ view. He would have learned that the history of separationism was far more "serpentine" than the straightforward history lesson of Everson had led him to believe. And he would have learned that the wall-of­ separation metaphor was itself potentially "serpentine" - now in the sense of the ancient serpent in the garden of Eden who offered access to enduring wisdom by means of a seductively simple formula.21 "Metaphors in law are to be narrowly watched," Benjamin Cardozo had warned in 1926, "for starting as devices to liberate thought, they end often by enslaving it. "22 So it has been with the metaphor of a wall of separation.23 What started as one of several useful principles of rences. Id. at 504 n.95; Bi bliography: The Judi ci al Opi ni ons of Just ice Robert H. Jackson in the Supreme Court ofth e Unit ed St at es October 6, 1941 - October 9, I954, 8 STAN. L. REV. 60, 60-71 (1955). 14. See ROBERT H. JACKSON, THE STRUGGLE FOR JUDICIAL SUPREMACY (1941) (giv- ing a detailed history of constitutional law). 15. 330 U.S. 1 (1947). 16. Dennis J. Hutchinson, The Black-J ackson Feud, 1988 SUP. er. REV. 203. 17. Everson, 330 U.S. at 18. 18. Id. at 28. 19. Id. at 19. 20. JACKSON, supra note 14, at 315 (discussing Jefferson). 21. Genesi s 3:1-7. 22. Berkey v. Third Ave. Ry. Co., 155 N.E. 58, 61 (N.Y. 1926). 23. See DREISBACH, pp. 107-28, and HAMBURGER, pp.
Recommended publications
  • Islam and Religious Freedom: the Experience of Religious Majorities and Minorities
    SYMPOSIUM ISLAM AND RELIGIOUS FREEDOM: THE EXPERIENCE OF RELIGIOUS MAJORITIES AND MINORITIES Brett G. Scharffs* INTRODUCTION One of the most interesting stories in the history of religious freedom is the journey of the Catholic Church, from being perhaps the most powerful institution on earth opposed to religious freedom in the eighteenth and into the nineteenth centuries, to being perhaps the most powerful institution on earth in defense of religious freedom from the middle of the twentieth century and into the early decades of the twenty-first century.1 Whereas in most countries today there is a very high correlation between dominant religious majorities and a low degree of religious freedom, regardless of whether the religious majority is Orthodox Christian, Muslim, Buddhist, Jewish, or Hindu, there is a striking exception: in countries with large Catholic majorities, limitations on religious freedom—measured both in terms of legal restrictions and social hostilities—tend to be low or very low.2 In an article in the Notre Dame Law Review celebrating the fiftieth anniversary of Dignitatis Humanae, I documented this remarkable anomaly and suggested that this was due to the Catholic Church’s journey toward finding within its own religious tradition the theological resources for identifying freedom of religion as a basic component of human dignity and thus a fundamental human right.3 In a subsequent article, Andrea Pin (whose article Is There a Place for Islam in the West? © 2018 Brett G. Scharffs. Individuals and nonprofit institutions may reproduce and distribute copies of this Essay in any format, at or below cost, for educational purposes, so long as each copy identifies the author, provides a citation to the Notre Dame Law Review Online, and includes this provision and copyright notice.
    [Show full text]
  • Adaptation Strategies of Islamist Movements April 2017 Contents
    POMEPS STUDIES 26 islam in a changing middle east Adaptation Strategies of Islamist Movements April 2017 Contents Understanding repression-adaptation nexus in Islamist movements . 4 Khalil al-Anani, Doha Institute for Graduate Studies, Qatar Why Exclusion and Repression of Moderate Islamists Will Be Counterproductive . 8 Jillian Schwedler, Hunter College, CUNY Islamists After the “Arab Spring”: What’s the Right Research Question and Comparison Group, and Why Does It Matter? . 12 Elizabeth R. Nugent, Princeton University The Islamist voter base during the Arab Spring: More ideology than protest? . .. 16 Eva Wegner, University College Dublin When Islamist Parties (and Women) Govern: Strategy, Authenticity and Women’s Representation . 21 Lindsay J. Benstead, Portland State University Exit, Voice, and Loyalty Under the Islamic State . 26 Mara Revkin, Yale University and Ariel I. Ahram, Virginia Tech The Muslim Brotherhood Between Party and Movement . 31 Steven Brooke, The University of Louisville A Government of the Opposition: How Moroccan Islamists’ Dual Role Contributes to their Electoral Success . 34 Quinn Mecham, Brigham Young University The Cost of Inclusion: Ennahda and Tunisia’s Political Transition . 39 Monica Marks, University of Oxford Regime Islam, State Islam, and Political Islam: The Past and Future Contest . 43 Nathan J. Brown, George Washington University Middle East regimes are using ‘moderate’ Islam to stay in power . 47 Annelle Sheline, George Washington University Reckoning with a Fractured Islamist Landscape in Yemen . 49 Stacey Philbrick Yadav, Hobart and William Smith Colleges The Lumpers and the Splitters: Two very different policy approaches on dealing with Islamism . 54 Marc Lynch, George Washington University The Project on Middle East Political Science The Project on Middle East Political Science (POMEPS) is a collaborative network that aims to increase the impact of political scientists specializing in the study of the Middle East in the public sphere and in the academic community .
    [Show full text]
  • Religious Studies
    RELIGIOUS STUDIES Religious Studies The Celtic Church in Ireland in the Fifth, Sixth and Seventh Centuries Unit AS 5 Content/Specification Section Page The Arrival of Christianity in Ireland 2 Evidence for the presence of Christianity in Ireland before the arrival of St. Patrick 6 Celtic Monasticism 11 Celtic Penitentials 17 Celtic Hagiography 21 Other Aspects of Human Experience Section 25 Glossary 42 RELIGIOUS STUDIES The Arrival of Christianity in Ireland © LindaMarieCaldwell/iStock/iStock/Thinkstock.com Learning Objective – demonstrate knowledge and understanding of, and critically evaluate the background to the arrival of Christianity in Ireland, including: • The political, social and religious background; • The arrival of and the evidence for Christianity in Ireland before Patrick; and • The significance of references to Palladius. This section requires students to explore: 1. The political, social and religious background in Ireland prior to the arrival of Christianity in Ireland. 2. Evidence of the arrival of Christianity in Ireland before Patrick (Pre-Patrician Christianity. 3. References to Palladius and the significance of these references to understanding the background to Christianity in Ireland before Patrick’s arrival. Early Irish society provided a great contrast to the society of the Roman Empire. For example, it had no towns or cities, no central government or no standard currency. Many Scholars have described it as tribal, rural, hierarchical and familiar. The Tuath was the basic political group or unit and was a piece of territory ruled by a King. It is estimated that there were about 150 such Tuath in pre – Christian Ireland. The basic social group was the fine and included all relations in the male line of descent.
    [Show full text]
  • Religious Law Versus Secular Law the Example of the Get Refusal in Dutch, English and Israeli Law
    Religious law versus secular law The example of the get refusal in Dutch, English and Israeli law Matthijs de Blois* 1. Introduction The revelation of the Torah on Mount Sinai as described in the book of Exodus is archetypical for religious law. ‘Then God spoke all these words (…).’1 Religious law is God-given. The law is theonomous and is binding ipso facto, independent of the consent of the governed. It may be a living instrument, but it is not subject to adaptation to changing opinions or practices among those who are bound by it. It is in that sense unchangeable, although it has to be interpreted by the members of the religious community or more specifically by those endowed with the task of interpreting the law. As far as the contents of the law are concerned, religious law tends to stress inter alia communal values and a submission to authority within hierarchical structures. It should also be underlined that in religious law there is no ‘public’ and ‘private’ distinction, which is so common to an Enlightenment approach to the law. It is not even possible to separate the relation- ship between God and man from those between men among each other. A violation of our obligations towards other persons implies a violation of God’s law and it therefore has its effect on the relationship with God. The religious is not a separate sphere next to the secular. There is no secular sphere. That is especially true for Judaism, which, in Maoz’s words, ‘encompasses all aspects of society and of an individual’s life.’2 In this day and age we can safely assume that religious law is based on a long tradition which already existed long before the idea of a pure secular law entered the scene with the Enlightenment.
    [Show full text]
  • Gájer László XIII. Leó Pápa Megnyilatkozásainak
    PÁZMÁNY PÉTER KATOLIKUS EGYETEM HITTUDOMÁNYI KAR Gájer László XIII. Leó pápa megnyilatkozásainak filozófiatörténeti előzményei (Különös tekintettel a vallásszabadságra) Dissertatio ad Doctoratum Témavezető: DDr. Rokay Zoltán Budapest 2013 Tartalomjegyzék Tartalomjegyzék .......................................................................................................................... 2 Irodalomjegyzék .......................................................................................................................... 4 Rövidítések ................................................................................................................................ 13 Bevezetés ................................................................................................................................... 14 I. Történeti előzmények ............................................................................................................. 19 1. Vallásszabadság a Szentírásban .......................................................................................... 19 1.1. Vallási türelem az Ószövetségben: Isten, istenek, kultuszok, hamis próféták ............... 19 1.2. Vallási türelem az Újszövetségben ............................................................................... 21 2. A patrisztikus kor ............................................................................................................... 26 2.1. Az Egyház és az állam viszonya az egyházatyák írásaiban a konstantini fordulat előtt .. 26 2.1.1. Tertulliánusz
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Religion in Public Life and Official Pressure to Participate in Alcoholics Anonymous, 65 U
    University of Kentucky UKnowledge Law Faculty Scholarly Articles Law Faculty Publications Summer 1997 The Role of Religion in Public Life and Official essurPr e to Participate in Alcoholics Anonymous Paul E. Salamanca University of Kentucky College of Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://uknowledge.uky.edu/law_facpub Part of the Constitutional Law Commons, and the First Amendment Commons Right click to open a feedback form in a new tab to let us know how this document benefits ou.y Recommended Citation Paul E. Salamanca, The Role of Religion in Public Life and Official Pressure to Participate in Alcoholics Anonymous, 65 U. Cin. L. Rev. 1093 (1997). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Faculty Publications at UKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Law Faculty Scholarly Articles by an authorized administrator of UKnowledge. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Role of Religion in Public Life and Official essurPr e to Participate in Alcoholics Anonymous Notes/Citation Information University of Cincinnati Law Review, Vol. 65, No. 4 (Summer 1997), pp. 1093-1168 This article is available at UKnowledge: https://uknowledge.uky.edu/law_facpub/412 THE ROLE OF RELIGION IN PUBLIC LIFE AND OFFICIAL PRESSURE TO PARTICIPATE IN ALCOHOLICS ANONYMOUS Paul E. Salamanca* [F]or an hour it was deadly dull, and I was fidgety. Miss Watson would say, "Dont put your feet up there, Huckleberry;" and "dont scrunch up like that, Huckleberry-set up straight;" and pretty soon she would say, "Don't gap and stretch like that, Huckleberry-why don't you try to behave?" Then she told me all about the bad place, and I said I wished I was there.
    [Show full text]
  • The Religious, the Secular, and the Antithetical
    Brigham Young University Law School BYU Law Digital Commons Faculty Scholarship 1-1-1991 The Religious, The Secular, and the Antithetical Frederick Mark Gedicks BYU Law, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.byu.edu/faculty_scholarship Part of the Religion Commons, and the Religion Law Commons Recommended Citation Frederick Mark Gedicks, The Religious, The Secular, and the Antithetical, 20 Cᴀᴘ. U. L. Rᴇᴠ., 113 (1991). This Article is brought to you for free and open access by BYU Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Scholarship by an authorized administrator of BYU Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE RELIGIOUS, THE SECULAR, AND THE ANTITHETICAL FREDERICK MARK GEDICKS° Since the Enlightenment, religious belief and secular knowl- edge in the West have been at loggerheads. The Enlightenment aimed to rid Western society of ideological superstitions, especially religious ones. Although the relationship between belief and knowl- edge during the last three centuries has been complex and variable, it has almost always been adversarial. Religion and secularism have settled at opposite poles on a continuum between subjectivity (belief) and objectivity (knowledge). In most of the intellectual con- frontations between these two adversaries, knowledge has prevailed in a way that has discredited belief, so that belief was steadily relo- cated from the center of Western politics to its periphery. This has resulted in a contemporary public culture in the United States that is largely secular, despite an American private life in which religion has remained vital and vibrant.1 The eclipse of belief by knowledge was momentous.
    [Show full text]
  • Separation of Church and State: a Theologically Liberal, Anti-Catholic, and American Principle Philip Hamburger
    University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Occasional Papers Law School Publications 2002 Separation of Church and State: A Theologically Liberal, Anti-Catholic, and American Principle Philip Hamburger Follow this and additional works at: http://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/occasional_papers Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Philip Hamburger, "Separation of Church and State: A Theologically Liberal, Anti-Catholic, and American Principle," University of Chicago Law Occasional Paper, No. 43 (2002). This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Law School Publications at Chicago Unbound. It has been accepted for inclusion in Occasional Papers by an authorized administrator of Chicago Unbound. For more information, please contact [email protected]. OCCASIONAL PAPERS FROM THE LAW SCHOOL THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO NUMBER 43 2002 Occasional Papers from The University of Chicago Law School Number 43 November 2002 Separation of Church and State A Theologically Liberal, Anti-Catholic, and American Principle By Philip Hamburger John P. Wilson Professor of Law 'A Theologically Liberal, Anti-Catholic, andAmerican Principle"isan excerptfrom Separation of Church and State by Philip Hamburger,Harvard University Press, 2002. @ 2002 INTRODUCTION This Occasional Paper reproduces a chapter from Professor Philip Hamburger's new book, Separation of Church and State, published in the summer of 2002 by Harvard University Press. The book argues that during the past two centuries the adoption of the idea of separa- tion between church and state has transformed American conceptions of the religious liberty guaranteed by the First Amendment. Many Americans take the idea of separation between church and state for granted.
    [Show full text]
  • Islam and the Rule of Law. Between Sharia and Secularization
    ISLAM AND THE RULE OF LAW BETWEEN SHARIA AND SECULARIZATION Birgit Krawietz Helmut Reifeld (Hrsg.) ISBN 978-3-938926-86-6 IM IM www.kas.de PLENUM CONTENT 5 | PREFACE Gerhard Wahlers 9 | INTRODUCTION Birgit Krawietz 17 | I. JUSTICE as A POLITICAL AND LEGAL ORGANIZING priNCipLE 19 | JUSTICE AS A POLITICAL PRINCIPLE IN ISLAM Werner Ende 35 | JUSTICE AS A PERVASIVE PRINCIPLE IN ISLAMIC LAW Birgit Krawietz 49 | II. CONSTITUTION BUILDING 51 | WAYS OF CONSTITUTION BUILDING IN MUSLIM COUNTRIES – THE CASE OF INDONESIA Masykuri Abdillah The published statements reflect the opinion of their authors, 65 | WHERE IS THE “ISLAM” IN THE “ISLAMIC STATE”? but not institutional positions of Konrad-Adenauer-Stiftung. Farish A. Noor © 2008, Konrad-Adenauer-Stiftung e.V., Sankt Augustin/Berlin 71 | THE INFLUENCE OF RELIGIOUS CLAUSES ON All rights reserved. CONSTITUTIONAL LAW IN COUNTRIES WITH AN No part of this publication may be reproduced or utilised in any form or by any ISLAMIC CHARACTER means, electronical or mechanical, without permission in writing from the Naseef Naeem publisher. Design: SWITSCH Kommunikationsdesign, Köln. 81 | THE SUDANESE INTERIM CONSTITUTION OF 2005 – Cover photo: (c) Das Bild des Orients, www.das-bild-des-orients.de A MODEL TO ESTABLISH COEXISTENCE BETWEEN AN Photographer: Joachim Gierlichs, 2003. ISLAMIC AND A SECULAR LEGAL REGIME Translation of German statements: WB Communication, Germersheim. Printed by Druckerei Franz Paffenholz GmbH, Bornheim. Markus Böckenförde Printed in Germany. Printed with the financial support of the Federal Republic of Germany. ISBN 978-3-939826-86-6 5 PREFACE 91 | III. reLIGIOUS versUS seCULar LAW? 93 | ISLAM, CONSTITUTION, CITIZENSHIP RIGHTS For the Konrad-Adenauer-Stiftung, strengthening and devel- AND JUSTICE IN MALAYSIA oping structures that support the rule of law is one of the Norani Othmann most important objectives and elements of its global inter- national cooperation.
    [Show full text]
  • Constitutionalizing Secularism, Alternative
    This article is published in a peer‐reviewed section of the Utrecht Law Review Constitutionalizing secularism, alternative secularisms or liberal-democratic constitutionalism? A critical reading of some Turkish, ECtHR and Indian Supreme Court cases on ‘secularism’ Veit Bader* 1. Introduction Recently, the heated debates on secularism in social sciences, politics and, increasingly, in political theory and political philosophy have also infected legal theory, constitutional law and comparative constitutionalism. Generally speaking, it may indeed be ‘too late to ban the word “secular”’ or to remove ‘secularism’ from our cultural vocabulary. The argument, however, that ‘too many controversies have already been stated in these terms’1 seems unconvincing to me. For the purposes of normative theory generally, and particularly for those of constitutional law and jurisprudence, the focus of this article, I have proposed to replace all normative concepts of ‘secularism’ by ‘priority for liberal-democracy’2 because I am convinced that we are better able to economize our moral disagreements or to resolve the substantive constitutional, legal, jurisprudential and institutional issues and controversies by avoiding to restate them in terms of ‘secularism’ or ‘alternative secularisms’. With regard to the ‘constitutional status of secularism’ we can discern three distinct positions all sharing the argument that ‘secularism (...) in most liberal democracies (…) is not explicitly recognized in the constitutional text or jurisprudence’3 and that it has ‘no clear standing * Professor Emeritus of Social and Political Philosophy (Faculty of Humanities) and of Sociology (Faculty of Social Sciences) at the University of Amsterdam (the Netherlands), email: [email protected] Thanks for critical comments and suggestions to Christian Moe, Ahmet Akgündüs, Yolande Jansen, Bas Schotel, Gunes Tezcur, Asli Bali, Werner Menski, an anonymous reviewer and the participants of conferences in New Delhi, Utrecht, and Istanbul where I presented earlier versions of this article.
    [Show full text]
  • Religiously Friendly Democracy: Framing Political And
    RELIGIOUSLY FRIENDLY DEMOCRACY: FRAMING POLITICAL AND RELIGIOUS IDENTITIES IN CATHOLIC AND MUSLIM SOCIETIES A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Notre Dame in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Michael Daniel Driessen Frances Hagopian, Director Graduate Program in Political Science Notre Dame, Indiana April 2011 © Copyright 2011 Michael Daniel Driessen RELIGIOUSLY FRIENDLY DEMOCRACY: FRAMING POLITICAL AND RELIGIOUS IDENTITIES IN CATHOLIC AND MUSLIM SOCIETIES Abstract by Michael Daniel Driessen This research project explores the relationship between faith and nation, and the institutional entanglements of religion, state and democracy in Catholic and Muslim societies. It is specifically animated by the following research question: What are the effects of bringing religion into the public sphere in new democracies, especially those whose theological values are considered to be hostile to democratic precepts? My analysis presents a theory for modeling the dynamics which are created when states allow hostile religions more access to the political and public spheres during moments of democratization (or lesser forms of political liberalization) by a) allowing religious political parties to contest elections and b) biasing religion-state arrangements in favor of religion. Drawing from more than eighteen months of field research in Italy and Algeria, I test the mechanisms of my theory through in-depth case studies in both a Catholic and Islamic setting and then use cross-national data on religion-state arrangements by Grim and Finke (2006) and Fox (2008) to statistically explore the theory‟s wider explanatory weight. To all of my teachers who told me to be patient with the wild within and to listen ii CONTENTS Figures...............................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Religion in the Public Sphere
    Religion in the Public Sphere Ars Disputandi Supplement Series Volume 5 edited by MAARTEN WISSE MARCEL SAROT MICHAEL SCOTT NIEK BRUNSVELD Ars Disputandi [http://www.ArsDisputandi.org] (2011) Religion in the Public Sphere Proceedings of the 2010 Conference of the European Society for Philosophy of Religion edited by NIEK BRUNSVELD & ROGER TRIGG Utrecht University & University of Oxford Utrecht: Ars Disputandi, 2011 Copyright © 2011 by Ars Disputandi, version: September 14, 2011 Published by Ars Disputandi: The Online Journal for Philosophy of Religion, [http://www.arsdisputandi.org], hosted by Igitur publishing, Utrecht University Library, The Netherlands [http://www.uu.nl/university/library/nl/igitur/]. Typeset in Constantia 9/12pt. ISBN: 978-90-6701-000-9 ISSN: 1566–5399 NUR: 705 Reproduction of this (or parts of this) publication is permitted for non-commercial use, provided that appropriate reference is made to the author and the origin of the material. Commercial reproduction of (parts of) it is only permitted after prior permission by the publisher. Contents Introduction 1 ROGER TRIGG 1 Does Forgiveness Violate Justice? 9 NICHOLAS WOLTERSTORFF Section I: Religion and Law 2 Religion and the Legal Sphere 33 MICHAEL MOXTER 3 Religion and Law: Response to Michael Moxter 57 STEPHEN R.L. CLARK Section II: Blasphemy and Offence 4 On Blasphemy: An Analysis 75 HENK VROOM 5 Blasphemy, Offence, and Hate Speech: Response to Henk Vroom 95 ODDBJØRN LEIRVIK Section III: Religious Freedom 6 Freedom of Religion 109 ROGER TRIGG 7 Freedom of Religion as the Foundation of Freedom and as the Basis of Human Rights: Response to Roger Trigg 125 ELISABETH GRÄB-SCHMIDT Section IV: Multiculturalism and Pluralism in Secular Society 8 Multiculturalism and Pluralism in Secular Society: Individual or Collective Rights? 147 ANNE SOFIE ROALD 9 After Multiculturalism: Response to Anne Sofie Roald 165 THEO W.A.
    [Show full text]