Eastern Regional Meeting of the Society of Christian Philosophers Concurrent Paper Abstracts

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Eastern Regional Meeting of the Society of Christian Philosophers Concurrent Paper Abstracts Eastern Regional Meeting of the Society of Christian Philosophers Concurrent Paper Abstracts Majid Amini, Virginia State University From Absolute to Maximal God: Would that Solve the Problem? The classical monotheistic concept of God has been bedeviled by a plethora of logical and metaphysical paradoxes. Recently there have been a number of attempts claiming that by reforming the traditional concept of God as an omniscient, omnipotent and omnibenevolent being to a concept of God as the being with maximal consistent set of knowledge, power and benevolence, the monotheistic concept of God can be rescued from contradictions and thereby reinstating a viable version of Anselmian theism. By focusing on omnipotence specifically, the purpose of this paper is therefore twofold: (1) to show the logical impossibility of maintaining an absolute or infinite conception of divine attributes, and (2) to show that even a maximal conception of divine attributes is plagued with the problem of uniqueness of God and a variant of the paradox of omnipotence thus indicating that such reformulations are still beset with dilemmas and paradoxes. Greg Bassham, King’s College A Critique of C. S. Lewis’s Argument from Desire In various places, C. S. Lewis offers an argument for God and/or a heavenly afterlife that is now widely called the argument from desire. Lewis appears to give at least two versions of the argument, one inductive and the other deductive. Both versions focus on a special form of spiritual or transcendental longing that Lewis calls “Joy.” The gist of his deductive argument is this: Joy is an innate, natural desire. All innate, natural desires have possible satisfactions. So, Joy must have a possible satisfaction. But Joy does not have a possible satisfaction in this world. Therefore, Joy must have a possible satisfaction in the next world. In this paper, I examine both the inductive and deductive versions of Lewis’s argument from desire, and argue that neither version succeeds. Anthony Bolos , Virginia Commonwealth University Re-Imagining the Imago Dei I offer a compatible account of understanding the theology of the imago Dei in conjunction with contemporary views in evolutionary biology. I discuss two related problems: First, there is the theological challenge to explain—or even merely to describe—the special nature of humankind in the face of evolutionary science. Second, there is the challenge to provide an account of exactly when humans became God’s image bearers. In response to the first challenge I argue that the special nature of humans is that we are uniquely equipped to be God’s image bearers. In response to the second challenge I argue that humans became God’s image bearers at the moment they were apt to serve in this unique role. I also claim that my account does not come with any theological disadvantages when considering the evolutionary origins of modern humans and further provides an important philosophical insight: namely, humans, in this environment as God’s image bearers, couldn’t have been significantly different than they currently are. Kenneth Boyce, University of Missouri Andrew Moon, Rutgers University 1 In Defense of Proper Functionalism: Cognitive Science Takes on Swampman According to proper functionalist theories of warrant, a belief is warranted only if it is formed by cognitive faculties that are properly functioning according to a good, truth-aimed design plan. A formidable challenge to proper functionalism is the Swampman objection, according to which there are possible scenarios involving creatures who have warranted beliefs but whose cognitive faculties are not properly functioning. In this paper, we draw lessons from cognitive science to argue that the Swampman objection fails by showing that the underlying, central intuition motivating it is false. Aaron Brooks, Florida State University Science, Religion, and Incompatibility: Can Philosophy of Science Help? Attempts to discredit religion by using science seem to assume the rationale of two major, heavily-critiqued philosophies of science: logical positivism and critical rationalism. As a case study, this essay will show the correlation between these two philosophies and the writing of philosopher of science Alex Rosenberg. Rather than critiquing Rosenberg via critiques of these philosophies, I will attempt to show the compatibility of science and religion when these philosophies are assumed. The essay will proceed by first explicating logical positivism, especially as evidenced in the thought of Moritz Schlick and the young Ludwig Wittgenstein. In the second section, the essay will explore the critical rationalism of Karl Popper. At the end of each section, it will be argued that if something like the logic of these two respective schools is being employed by critics like Rosenberg, religious claims can still function compatibly with science. Donald Bungum, Saint Louis University Revealed to the Little Ones: Love, Presence, and Hiddenness In the debate over divine hiddenness, one crucial question concerns whether explicit belief in God’s existence is required for relationship with God. In this paper, I argue that explicit belief in God’s existence is not required, and I contend that one can hold this view without positing a defective relationship between God and human beings. Following Eleonore Stump, I first argue that love is fulfilled between lovers just when they are fully and personally present to one another. I then use results from developmental psychology to argue that the capacity to be mutually personally present does not require the capacity for propositional thought. These claims support a model of divine-human relationship on which the following analogy holds: just as infants can have meaningful relationships with their caregivers while lacking explicit beliefs about them, so adult human beings can have meaningful relationships with God while lacking explicit belief in His existence. Laura Frances Callahan, Rutgers University Evil: Only Sometimes Evidence against God Benton, Hawthorne, and Isaacs (forthcoming) claim, contra sceptical theism, that evil must be evidence against God’s existence, because the absence of evil would be (presumably excellent) evidence for it. Their argument is an interesting one, and valid. But even if we accept its somewhat controversial premises, its implications are far more limited than they suggest. Seeing this requires no endorsement of sceptical theism but just a more natural way of drawing 2 distinctions between epistemic possibilities. If one could learn simply ‘that there was evil,’ perhaps via an oracle, one would gain evidence against God. But when we commonly observe that there is evil in the world, we learn a proposition much stronger. And determining the evidential impact of that much stronger proposition, about the specific amount and types of evil as well as good there are in the world, remains a complex affair. Eddy Keming Chen, Rutgers University Daniel Rubio, Rutgers University Pascal’s Wager Meets Surreal Numbers Although expected utility theory has proven a fruitful and elegant theory in the finite realm, attempts to generalize it to include infinite utilities have resulted in many para- doxes. Nevertheless, one of the most venerable decision problems—Pascal’s Wager— employ exactly these things. In this paper, we argue that the use of John Conway’s surreal numbers shall provide a firm mathematical foundation for transfinite decision theory. To that end, we prove a surreal representation theorem and show that our surreal decision theory respects dominance reasoning even in the infinite case. We apply our theory to bear on Pascal’s Wager and two objections against it: Mixed Strategies and Many Gods.After formulating the two objections in the framework of surreal utilities and probabilities, our theory correctly predicts that (1) the pure “Christian” strategy beats all mixed strategies, and (2) what one should do in a Pascalian decision problem depends on what one’s credence function is like. Our analysis therefore suggests that although Pascal’s Wager is mathematically coherent, it does not deliver what it purports to do, i.e. convince people that they should lead a Christian life regardless of how confident they are in theism and its alternatives. Nevin Climenhaga, University of Notre Dame Epistemic Probabilities: A Guide for the Perplexed The epistemic probability of A given B – notated P(A|B) – is the degree to which B supports, or makes plausible, A. In general, if P(A|B) = n, then someone with B as their evidence ought to be confident in A to degree n. A persistently difficult question in epistemology is how to determine the values of epistemic probabilities, so characterized. The project of answering this question has two parts: a formal part and a substantive part. The formal part breaks down the probabilities in question to their most “epistemically accessible” components, via identities like Bayes’ Theorem. The substantive part tells us how to calculate these “atomic” or “direct” probabilities. In this paper I undertake the formal part of this project. I argue that direct probabilities are ones given to propositions by their causes or explanations, and that given plausible assumptions about the structure of explanation, we can combine direct probabilities so characterized to obtain indirect probabilities. Dustin Crummet, University of Notre Dame Theodicy for Creeping Things Philosophers of religion, even those working on the problem of animal suffering, have largely ignored “lower
Recommended publications
  • The Argument from Desire
    THE ARGUMENT FROM DESIRE Robert Holyer In this essay I offer a reformulation and defense of the argument from desire as it is presented in the works of C. S. Lewis. Specifically, I try to answer the criticisms of the argument made by John Beversluis in his recent book C. S. Lewis and the Search for Rational Religion. However, my concern is not so much Lewis as it is the argument itself, which I argue is worthy of serious and more extended philosophical treatment. In his critical discussion of C. S. Lewis's case for Christianity, John Beversluis extracts from Lewis's writings something he calls the argument from desire. I Although Lewis himself never presented it as a philosophical argument, he did insinuate it at several points in his writings, especially in the autobiographical works, The Pilgrim's Regress and Surprised by Joy, and it was arguably the most important consideration in his own conversion. What Beversluis does is to present this facet of Lewis's development as a philosophical argument, which he then goes on to reject for both "logical and theological" reasons. In what follows I shall consider Lewis's argument only from a philosophical point of view. My intention is to reformulate and defend it, and this not primarily to vindicate Lewis from what I think are some superficial criticisms (though I hope that what I have to say will have this effect), but more importantly, because I think Lewis offers us in rough form an argument from religious experience that is both different from the one that is most commonly discussed and deserving of a more careful philosophical treatment than it receives from Beversluis.
    [Show full text]
  • Volume 1 a Collection of Essays Presented at the First Frances White Ewbank Colloquium on C.S
    Inklings Forever Volume 1 A Collection of Essays Presented at the First Frances White Ewbank Colloquium on C.S. Lewis & Article 1 Friends 1997 Full Issue 1997 (Volume 1) Follow this and additional works at: https://pillars.taylor.edu/inklings_forever Part of the English Language and Literature Commons, History Commons, Philosophy Commons, and the Religion Commons Recommended Citation (1997) "Full Issue 1997 (Volume 1)," Inklings Forever: Vol. 1 , Article 1. Available at: https://pillars.taylor.edu/inklings_forever/vol1/iss1/1 This Full Issue is brought to you for free and open access by the Center for the Study of C.S. Lewis & Friends at Pillars at Taylor University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Inklings Forever by an authorized editor of Pillars at Taylor University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INKLINGS FOREVER A Collection of Essays Presented at tlte First FRANCES WHITE EWBANK COLLOQUIUM on C.S. LEWIS AND FRIENDS II ~ November 13-15, 1997 Taylor University Upland, Indiana ~'...... - · · .~ ·,.-: :( ·!' '- ~- '·' "'!h .. ....... .u; ~l ' ::-t • J. ..~ ,.. _r '· ,. 1' !. ' INKLINGS FOREVER A Collection of Essays Presented at the Fh"St FRANCES WHITE EWBANK COLLOQliTUM on C.S. LEWIS AND FRIENDS Novem.ber 13-15, 1997 Published by Taylor University's Lewis and J1nends Committee July1998 This collection is dedicated to Francis White Ewbank Lewis scholar, professor, and friend to students for over fifty years ACKNOWLEDGMENTS David Neuhauser, Professor Emeritus at Taylor and Chair of the Lewis and Friends Committee, had the vision, initiative, and fortitude to take the colloquium from dream to reality. Other committee members who helped in all phases of the colloquium include Faye Chechowich, David Dickey, Bonnie Houser, Dwight Jessup, Pam Jordan, Art White, and Daryl Yost.
    [Show full text]
  • Objective and Subjective Apologetical Approaches Regarding the Existence of God*
    AUC THEOLOGICA 2020 – Vol. 10, No. 1 Pag. 121–140 OBJECTIVE AND SUBJECTIVE APOLOGETICAL APPROACHES REGARDING THE EXISTENCE OF GOD* STUART NICOLSON ABSTRACT: Apologetics since the Second Vatican Council has somewhat changed to deal more with reaching the person and sowing seeds rather than winning the argument. The traditional objective arguments for the existence of God are today less effective, especially when approaching postmodern non-believers. Subjective approaches are far more effective, dealing with personal experience. Covering a wide range, Peter Kreeft offers twenty arguments for the existence of God, which can be grouped according to objective, subjective, and a transition group between these. By using different approaches and combinations of these, a consistent ‘wall’ of reasons for believing in God’s existence can be created by combining these arguments like building blocks. This paper considers the range of arguments, giv- ing summaries of the (semi-) subjective ones and commenting upon them with regards to their use, strengths, and weaknesses. It finds that as one purpose of apol- ogetics is to assist the unbeliever in coming to know God, ways of helping bring the subjective thinker to belief in God should be developed further, and Kreeft’s offering is a very useful resource for the Christian in explaining why it is reason- able to believe in God. Key words: Belief in God; Apologetics; Peter Kreeft; Objectivity; Subjectivity; Approaches; Arguments DOI: 10.14712/23363398.2020.47 Within the field of apologetics today, faced with the fluidity and subjectivity of postmodern thinking and its impact upon faith in the existence of God, it is no longer effective in many cases to present * This work was supported by GAJU [157/H/2016].
    [Show full text]
  • The Argument from Desire/Longing for the Existence of God
    The Argument from Desire/Longing for the Existence of God In his autobiography The Confessions , Saint Augustine (354-430) traces the steps in his life that led to his conversion to Christianity. In his youth, Augustine indulged in a life full of worldly pleasures. He searched for a deep sense of joy and satisfaction, although nothing could satisfy this desire. That is, nothing could satisfy his desire except a right relationship with God through Christianity. Other philosophers such as Blaise Pascal, Søren Kierkegaard, and C. S. Lewis have experienced the same type of longing for the divine that has only been satisfied by knowing God. As a result, some philosophers have argued that this sense of desiring to know God serves as evidence that God exists. The Premises of the Argument One way to make the argument from desire follows these premises: 1. All natural desires have a real, corresponding satisfaction. 2. Humans naturally desire something which cannot be met in this world. Therefore, 3. Some real object must exist beyond this world, which satisfies this human desire (which is God). The first premise can be supported from our own experience. We experience the desire to eat. This sense of hunger exists because it is something our bodies need to survive. Our sense of hunger exists as a way to ensure we survive. Similarly, we thirst when we need water, and we have a natural drive for sex. All of these natural desires point to a real fulfillment of those desires. They all point to a real object that satisfies them.
    [Show full text]
  • 12 Arguments for the Existence of God
    12 Arguments for the Existence of God Author Caner Taslaman Translated by Selçuk AKTÜRK Cosmo Publishing Cosmo Publishing Company UNITED STATES OF AMERICA ISBN: All rights reserved, including the rights of reproduction in whole or in part of any form. CONTENT Preface 1 Introduction 2 PART I ARGUMENTS FROM THE UNIVERSE 9 1. The Kalam Cosmological Argument 10 2. Argument from the Existence of Laws 18 3. Argument from the Discoverability of the Universe 24 4. Argument from the Potentiality of the Universe 32 5. Argument from the Fine Tunings of the Physical Laws and Constants 39 6. Argument from the Fine Tuning of Physical Phenomena 46 7. Argument from Life’s Design 52 PART II ARGUMENTS FROM HUMAN NATURE 65 8. Argument from Natural Desires 66 9. Argument from Innate Morality 76 10. Argument from Reason 85 11. Argument from Will 93 12. Argument from Consciousness and Self 104 Epilogue 121 12 Arguments for the Existence of God Preface Claims of obsoleteness for presenting arguments for the existence of God, or that these arguments now belong to the dusty shelves of history; stemming often from Hume, Kant or Marxist philosophies, from New Atheism, from positivism or from religious cults belittling human reason… I contend that these claims are naïve, and they do not stand on consistent grounds. I present details of my contention organized into twelve arguments. Some of the arguments are also presented in greater depth in my other works. Judgment on whether God exists or not has a profound impact on our perception of ourselves, our beloved ones, the earth and the entire universe.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Religion
    Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Religion INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY: PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION BEAU BRANSON, MARCUS WILLIAM HUNT, TIMOTHY D KNEPPER, ROBERT SLOAN LEE, STEVEN STEYL, HANS VAN EYGHEN, BEAU BRANSON (BOOK EDITOR), AND CHRISTINA HENDRICKS (SERIES EDITOR) Rebus Community Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Religion by Beau Branson, Marcus William Hunt, Timothy D Knepper, Robert Sloan Lee, Steven Steyl, Hans Van Eyghen, Beau Branson (Book Editor), and Christina Hendricks (Series Editor) is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted. DEDICATION To Roger Branson — the best dad I ever had. For all the sacrifices I know ouy made. And for all the ones I don’t. CONTENTS What is an Open Textbook? ix Christina Hendricks How to Access and Use the Books xi Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Series xiii Christina Hendricks Praise for the Book xvi Acknowledgements xviii Beau Branson and Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Book 1 Beau Branson 1. The Intertwining of Philosophy and Religion in the Western Tradition 7 Beau Branson 2. Reasons to Believe – Theoretical Arguments 18 Marcus William Hunt 3. Non-Standard Arguments for God’s Existence 30 Robert Sloan Lee 4. Reasons Not to Believe 49 Steven Steyl 5. Debunking Arguments against Theistic Belief 62 Hans Van Eyghen 6. From Philosophy of (Mono)theism to Philosophy of Religions 74 Timothy D Knepper Glossary 87 About the Contributors 91 Feedback and Suggestions 94 Adoption Form 95 Licensing and Attribution Information 96 Review Statement 98 Accessibility Assessment 99 Version History 101 WHAT IS AN OPEN TEXTBOOK? CHRISTINA HENDRICKS An open textbook is like a commercial textbook, except: (1) it is publicly available online free of charge (and at low-cost in print), and (2) it has an open license that allows others to reuse it, download and revise it, and redistribute it.
    [Show full text]
  • 20 Arguments for the Existence Of
    Twenty Arguments for the Existence of God 1. The Argument from Change [An Aspect of the Cosmological Argument] • The universe is filled with changing things; as far as we know, the entire universe is changing. • All change needs an outside force to actualize it. • Therefore, there is some force outside (in addition to) the universe, some real being transcendent to the universe. This being we call “God.” 2. The Argument from Efficient Causality [An Aspect of the Cosmological Argument] • All things that exist are the result of some cause. • There must be something uncaused, something on which all things that need an efficient cause of being are dependent. This being we call “God.” • The idea that something can be caused by nothing is absurd. 3. The Argument from Time and Contingency • The universe is filled with things that do not need to exist; their existence is not necessary. • There must be something in the universe which must exist; some absolute necessary being. This necessary being we call “God.” 4. The Argument from Degrees of Perfection • The existence of degrees of perfection means that there is a perfect ideal. • The concept of a perfect ideal applies not only to material things and properties, but also to being. • There exists an absolutely Perfect Being, whom we call “God.” 5. The Argument from Design [Teleological Argument] • The universe displays a staggering amount of design. • This design is the result of either chance or intelligence. • Chance is a completely inadequate explanation for design; therefore it must be designed by a Supreme Intelligence. This Supreme Intelligence we call “God.” 6.
    [Show full text]
  • The Argument from Desire
    The Argument From Desire 1. Every natural, innate desire in us corresponds to some real object that can satisfy that desire. 2. But there exists in us a desire which nothing in time, nothing on earth, no creature can satisfy. 3. Therefore there must exist something more than time, earth and creatures, which can satisfy this desire. 4. This something is what people call "God" and "life with God forever." The first premise implies a distinction of desires into two kinds: innate and externally conditioned, or natural and artificial. We naturally desire things like food, drink, sex, sleep, knowledge, friendship and beauty; and we naturally shun things like starvation, loneliness, ignorance and ugliness. We also desire (but not innately or naturally) things like sports cars, political office, flying through the air like Superman, the land of Oz and a Red Sox world championship. Now there are differences between these two kinds of desires. We do not, for example, for the most part, recognize corresponding states of deprivation for the second, the artificial, desires, as we do for the first. There is no word like "Ozlessness" parallel to "sleeplessness." But more importantly, the natural desires come from within, from our nature, while the artificial ones come from without, from society, advertising or fiction. This second difference is the reason for a third difference: the natural desires are found in all of us, but the artificial ones vary from person to person. The existence of the artificial desires does not necessarily mean that the desired objects exist. Some do; some don't.
    [Show full text]
  • Complete Dissertation
    VU Research Portal The Philosophical Christianity of C.S. Lewis: Its Sources, Content and Formation Barkman, A.J. 2009 document version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication in VU Research Portal citation for published version (APA) Barkman, A. J. (2009). The Philosophical Christianity of C.S. Lewis: Its Sources, Content and Formation. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. E-mail address: [email protected] Download date: 25. Sep. 2021 VRIJE UNIVERSITEIT The Philosophical Christianity of C. S. Lewis: Its Sources, Content and Formation ACADEMISCH PROEFSCHRIFT ter verkrijging van de graad Doctor aan de Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam, op gezag van de rector magnificus prof.dr. L.M. Bouter, in het openbaar te verdedigen ten overstaan van de promotiecommissie van de faculteit der Wijsbegeerte op vrijdag 12 juni 2009 om 13.45 uur in het auditorium van de universiteit, De Boelelaan 1105 door Adam James Barkman geboren te Winnipeg, Canada promotor: prof.dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Basic Apologetics Course Set I: Reasons for Faith
    Basic Apologetics Course Set I: Reasons for Faith How to Use This Study Guide While individuals can certainly learn from this course, you will get 4. When the group meets, plan for two hours in order to view the maximum value from the Basic Apologetics Course by using the the video lecture and then discuss the study questions, draw- following approach: ing on insights from the recommended reading. If you find that you cannot cover the material in two hours, consider 1. Convene a group of four to six others who are interested in scheduling a follow-on meeting to complete your processing. studying apologetics and are willing to commit themselves to In some cases, it may be more practical to ask group members meeting regularly for discussion and processing. (The small to view the lecture on the C.S. Lewis Institute web site prior size of the group allows more time for each person to take to meeting in order to allow more time for discussion. part in the discussion.) 5. When you meet, seek to clearly understand the study ma- 2. Each member of the group should commit themselves to terial but avoid the temptation to focus exclusively on the pray regularly that God will help them to understand truth intellectual dimension. Also seek to understand why people and share it with grace, love and humility. hold such views and look for ways to engage them with truth in a gentle, humble and respectful manner. The purpose of 3. In preparation for the regular meeting, everyone should apologetics is not only to strengthen our own faith but also complete the recommended reading for the lecture.
    [Show full text]
  • Argument from Desire
    A Beginner’s Guide to the Theistic Argument from Desire Peter S. Williams UK based philosopher and apologist Peter S. Williams (MA, MPhil) is Assistant Professor in Communication and Worldviews at Gimlekollen School of Journalism and Communication, NLA University College, Norway. His publications include: Getting at Jesus: A Comprehensive Critique of Neo-Atheist Nonsense about the Jesus of History (Wipf & Stock, 2019) & A Faithful Guide to Philosophy: A Christian Introduction to the Love of Wisdom, reprint edition (Wipf & Stock, 2019). See www.peterswilliams.com The theistic “argument from desire” (AFD) is a family of arguments that move from an analysis of human desire to the conclusion that God exists (or that something like “eternal life in relationship with God” is the true human telos, goal or purpose). This argument was popularized in the twentieth century by C.S. Lewis, who sought to understand an “unsatisfied desire which is itself more desirable than any other satisfaction,” a mystical experience to which he gave the technical label “Joy”1 (and which writers in the German Romantic tradition called Sehnsucht): the bitter-sweet experience of feeling draw to a transcendent and innately desirable “something more” beyond one’s worldly grasp. This experience is occasioned but not satisfied by various worldly “triggers” that are somewhat person-relative, but often have to do with beauty and/or natural grandeur (i.e. what the Romantics called “the sublime”). Lewis produced the pre-eminent literary engagement with Sehnsucht in English, contemplating “Joy” in works of allegory, apologetics, autobiography and theology, and evoking “Joy” in his fiction. He wasn’t the first to explore this theme, which can be found in the Jewish scriptures (Psalm 42 opens with the declaration that: “As the deer pants for pants for streams of water, so my soul pants for you, my God.” Ecclesiastes can be read as a meditation upon this theme2).
    [Show full text]
  • Calvin Theological Seminary the Mythos of Sin: C. S. Lewis
    CALVIN THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY THE MYTHOS OF SIN: C. S. LEWIS, THE GENESIS FALL, AND THE MODERN MOOD A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF CALVIN THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY BY JEREMY G GRINNELL GRAND RAPIDS, MICHIGAN MAY 2011 CALVIN THEOLOGICAL SEMINARY 3233 Burton SE • Grand Rapids, Michigan • 49546-4301 800388-6034 fax: 616957-8621 [email protected] www.calvinseminary.edu This dissertation entitled THE MYTHOS OF SIN: C.S. LEWIS, THE GENESIS FALL, AND THE MODERN MOOD written by JEREMY G. GRINNELL and submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy has been accepted by the faculty of Calvin Theological Seminary upon the recommendation of the undersigned readers: .i:»: Cornelius Plantinga, Jr., Ph.D. Ron~~ Calvin P. Van Reken, Ph.D. {il!;\ Alan JacobS~ David M. Rylaarsda ,Ph.D. Date Acting Vice President for Academic Affairs Copyright © 2011 by Jeremy G Grinnell All rights reserved To, for, and mostly because of Denise Could God Himself create such lovely things as I have dreamed? Answers Hope, “Whence then came thy dream?” —George MacDonald, Lilith CONTENTS ABSTRACT ...................................................................................................................... vii INTRODUCTION .............................................................................................................. 1 The Nature of the Project ............................................................................ 4 Method of the Exploration
    [Show full text]