1 Arguments for the Existence of God Peter S. Williams (MA. Mphil

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 Arguments for the Existence of God Peter S. Williams (MA. Mphil Arguments for the existence of God Peter S. Williams (MA. MPhil). Arguments for God work by making explicit the existence of real connections between God and Creation , so that one is put in the position of having to choose between acknowledging the conclusion or rejecting either the validity of the argument or the truth of one of the relevant premises. An argument for God places God in one balance pan and some other aspect of reality in the other pan and tries to establish a link between them such that the weight of the evidence raises the case for belief. There is nothing that cannot be used as the launch-point for an argument for the existence of God because God is related to the whole of reality. For example, the moral argument tries to establish the existence of a connection between objective moral value and God’s existence. If one acknowledges that the argument is logically valid but nevertheless wish to deny the conclusion, one must deny the existence of objective moral value. It is now received wisdom that arguments for God are cumulative, or, at least, are best approached cumulatively; that is, the weight of evidence for God accumulates as one adds arguments to an overall case that doesn’t rest on any one argument. In other words, the more different links between God and reality one can uncover the more rounded a picture of God one can build up and the more certain one can be that the arguments point to God. The design argument doesn’t provide much if any evidence for the existence of a necessary being, whereas the cosmological argument doesn’t provide much if any evidence for an intelligent designer; but put the two arguments together and they compliment each other to show that the universe has a necessarily existent intelligent cause. The moral argument adds that the designer is good, and so on. The arguments are like strands in a rope. Another good way to describe the procedure is the court analogy. Isolated pieces of evidence may be insufficient on their own to warrant convicting someone ‘beyond reasonable doubt’, but taken together the evidence does warrant conviction. Likewise with the case for God. The cosmological argument does not prove the existence of God. Nor do individual design arguments. But put all those arguments together, and the court may have to decide that God exists. In fact, I am fairly confident that some theistic arguments can stand alone, in particular the argument from objective moral value and the arguments from desire and absurdity. Nevertheless, the more arguments one can amass, the more chance one has of convincing the honest seeker. All this said, I am also convinced (by William James) that arguments for God are not necessarily for belief in God to be rational. Suppose you judged the evidence each way to balance out (or suppose you are unable to judge the evidence), you wouldn’t be irrational in following a gut instinct either to believe or to disbelieve. Ontological Argument What do we mean by ‘God’? Anselm suggested that we must mean something like ‘the greatest possible being’. If we can think of someone better than God, then that better being, and not ‘God’, would deserve our worship. So God, as ‘the being who deserves our worship’, must be a being a greater than which is inconceivable or impossible. 1 Anselm used this definition of God to argue that God must exist. After all, said Anselm, it is greater to exist in reality outside my mind than it is to exist only as an idea in my mind. But God exists as an idea in my mind at least, and so, as the greatest possible being, God must exist in reality as well. This argument is generally distrusted because it feels like a trick, and indeed it is a trick, albeit a very impressive one. The problem is that God does not exist as an idea in my mind – the idea of ‘God’, a being who exists independently of my idea of Him, exists in my mind. Perhaps the argument shows that if I accept a certain definition of God I must think of God as existing in reality on pain of self-contradiction, but why accept the coherence of this definition of God? It’s what we must mean by ‘God’, but perhaps the very notion of ‘God’ is ultimately incoherent; so the atheist might suggest. Still, Anselm has given us an intuitively impressive definition of God, and that is useful. Better, his definition can be used to argue thus: by definition, the greatest possible being must be a being that exists necessarily, that is, one that must exist if it is possible that it exist (because necessary existence is greater than unnecessary, contingent existence). If one accepts that it is possible that God exists, one must therefore accept that God exists necessarily. In other words, if you want to deny the existence of God, you must hold that God’s existence is not merely contingently false, but necessarily false, i.e. impossible. One way you might do that is to argue that the very notion of ‘greater than’ is meaningless because value is subjective. Thus the very idea of God requires the cogency of objective values. The Conceptual Argument This argument was made famous by Rene Descartes. Like the Ontological argument, it uses the very idea of God, but it works not from the idea of God as such, but from the fact that we have such an idea in the first place. How is it that finite, imperfect beings possess the concept of an infinite, perfect being? It might be suggested that our idea of God, like the idea of a unicorn, is produced by human imagination. If God is a bit like a human father, only perfect, then God is an imaginative projection of fatherhood with the imperfections removed. This attempt to explain away our idea of God sounds well enough, until we ask how it is that we recognize imperfections as imperfections unworthy of ‘God’? As Descartes said: “Now all these characteristics are such that the more diligently I attend to them, the less do they appear capable of proceeding from me alone; hence. we must conclude that God necessarily exists.” 1 It will not do to say that ‘God’ is an imaginary perfect being extrapolated from real imperfect beings without explaining how imperfect humans came to recognize imperfection as such: “the idea of infinite perfection is already presupposed in our thinking about all these things and judging them imperfect.” 2 The idea of perfection cannot be the result of a process which presupposes it! So from where do we get this idea of perfection? True, we recognize degrees of relative perfection - this man is a better father than that - but this implies that we possess a standard of perfection to employ in making such evaluations. Therefore, it would seem that the concept of a perfect being is innate to the human mind: 1 Rene Descartes, Meditations , (Cambridge, 1931). 2 Peter Kreeft & Ronald Tacelli, Handbook of Christian Apologetics , (Monarch, 1995), p69. 2 “I should not have the idea of an infinite substance – since I am finite – if it had not proceeded from some substance which was veritably infinite. For how would it be possible that I should know. that I am not quite perfect, unless I had within me some idea of a Being more perfect than myself, in comparison with which I should recognize the deficiencies of my nature?” 3 Cosmological Argument If anything exists its existence is either dependent upon the existence of one or more things beyond itself, or not. If not, it is an independent thing. Things are either dependent or independent, there is no third option. It is impossible for everything to be dependent, for there is nothing outside everything to depend upon. Therefore, if something exists, there must exist an independent thing. But something certainly does exist, “I think therefore I am”; so at least one independent thing certainly exists. This conclusion, I claim, is absolutely certain, but not very informative. This argument can also be cashed out in terms of necessary and contingent existence. We can add that you and I are apparently dependent things, that every physical thing is apparently dependent, which narrows our options with regards to identifying the independent thing. However, the atheist will want to identify the independent thing with the universe itself. Still, the cosmological dependency argument provides, as Dallas Willard puts it, a “logical space” for God in “an ontologically haunted universe”. If God exists He would certainly be an independent thing, whereas the atheist’s claim that the universe itself is independent seems to be worked out after the fact to avoid the inference to God. There is no necessity to think that the universe is independent (one can think of it as dependent upon God), whereas it is necessary to conceive of God as independent (anything dependent can’t be the greatest possible being). Arguments from Objective Value (Morality and Beauty) Objective moral and aesthetic judgements require objective standards of goodness and beauty that, it is argued, can only be found in the nature of God, who must therefore exist if objective moral and aesthetic truths exist. If such arguments are correct, not only does the existence of God imply the existence of objective value, the existence of objective value implies the existence of God. For morality: 1) only persons can prescribe behaviour, 2) only persons can obligate behaviour and 3) only a mind can contain a moral ideal.
Recommended publications
  • Eastern Regional Meeting of the Society of Christian Philosophers Concurrent Paper Abstracts
    Eastern Regional Meeting of the Society of Christian Philosophers Concurrent Paper Abstracts Majid Amini, Virginia State University From Absolute to Maximal God: Would that Solve the Problem? The classical monotheistic concept of God has been bedeviled by a plethora of logical and metaphysical paradoxes. Recently there have been a number of attempts claiming that by reforming the traditional concept of God as an omniscient, omnipotent and omnibenevolent being to a concept of God as the being with maximal consistent set of knowledge, power and benevolence, the monotheistic concept of God can be rescued from contradictions and thereby reinstating a viable version of Anselmian theism. By focusing on omnipotence specifically, the purpose of this paper is therefore twofold: (1) to show the logical impossibility of maintaining an absolute or infinite conception of divine attributes, and (2) to show that even a maximal conception of divine attributes is plagued with the problem of uniqueness of God and a variant of the paradox of omnipotence thus indicating that such reformulations are still beset with dilemmas and paradoxes. Greg Bassham, King’s College A Critique of C. S. Lewis’s Argument from Desire In various places, C. S. Lewis offers an argument for God and/or a heavenly afterlife that is now widely called the argument from desire. Lewis appears to give at least two versions of the argument, one inductive and the other deductive. Both versions focus on a special form of spiritual or transcendental longing that Lewis calls “Joy.” The gist of his deductive argument is this: Joy is an innate, natural desire.
    [Show full text]
  • The Argument from Desire
    THE ARGUMENT FROM DESIRE Robert Holyer In this essay I offer a reformulation and defense of the argument from desire as it is presented in the works of C. S. Lewis. Specifically, I try to answer the criticisms of the argument made by John Beversluis in his recent book C. S. Lewis and the Search for Rational Religion. However, my concern is not so much Lewis as it is the argument itself, which I argue is worthy of serious and more extended philosophical treatment. In his critical discussion of C. S. Lewis's case for Christianity, John Beversluis extracts from Lewis's writings something he calls the argument from desire. I Although Lewis himself never presented it as a philosophical argument, he did insinuate it at several points in his writings, especially in the autobiographical works, The Pilgrim's Regress and Surprised by Joy, and it was arguably the most important consideration in his own conversion. What Beversluis does is to present this facet of Lewis's development as a philosophical argument, which he then goes on to reject for both "logical and theological" reasons. In what follows I shall consider Lewis's argument only from a philosophical point of view. My intention is to reformulate and defend it, and this not primarily to vindicate Lewis from what I think are some superficial criticisms (though I hope that what I have to say will have this effect), but more importantly, because I think Lewis offers us in rough form an argument from religious experience that is both different from the one that is most commonly discussed and deserving of a more careful philosophical treatment than it receives from Beversluis.
    [Show full text]
  • Is Plato a Perfect Idealist?
    IOSR Journal Of Humanities And Social Science (IOSR-JHSS) Volume 19, Issue 3, Ver. V (Mar. 2014), PP 22-25 e-ISSN: 2279-0837, p-ISSN: 2279-0845. www.iosrjournals.org Is Plato a Perfect Idealist? Dr. Shanjendu Nath M. A., M. Phil., Ph.D. Associate Professor Rabindrasadan Girls’ College, Karimganj, Assam, India. Abstract: Idealism is a philosophy that emphasizes on mind. According to this theory, mind is primary and objective world is nothing but an idea of our mind. Thus this theory believes that the primary thing that exists is spiritual and material world is secondary. This theory effectively begins with the thought of Greek philosopher Plato. But it is Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) who used the term ‘idealism’ when he referred Plato in his philosophy. Plato in his book ‘The Republic’ very clearly stated many aspects of thought and all these he discussed from the idealistic point of view. According to Plato, objective world is not a real world. It is the world of Ideas which is real. This world of Ideas is imperishable, immutable and eternal. These ideas do not exist in our mind or in the mind of God but exist by itself and independent of any mind. He also said that among the Ideas, the Idea of Good is the supreme Idea. These eternal ideas are not perceived by our sense organs but by our rational self. Thus Plato believes the existence of two worlds – material world and the world of Ideas. In this article I shall try to explore Plato’s idealism, its origin, locus etc.
    [Show full text]
  • The Metaphysical Doctrine of Creation
    The Metaphysical Doctrine of Creation THOMAS V. MORRIS The majestic introduction to the book of Genesis proclaims that1 In the beginning, God created the heavens and the earth. This is the key to a distinctively theistic perspective on reality. This one statement captures the heart of a theistic world-view: We live in a created universe. For centuries, theists have held that the most important truth about our world is that it is a created world. And it is no exaggeration to add that one of the most important truths about God is that He is the creator of this world. Aquinas once expressed the core of the doctrine of creation quite suc- cinctly with the single sentence: Anything that exists in any way must necessarily have its origin fromGod.2 The philosophical view which is here so crisply and simply conveyed, I shall refer to as the metaphysical doctrine of creation . I understand it as a thesis about the metaphysical or ontological dependence of all things distinct from God on God as their source of being, the ultimate cause of their existence. As a philosophical thesis, the metaphysical doctrine of creation is not to be thought of as necessarily allied to, or as in competition with, any particu- lar scientific theory of physical cosmology or biological development. A few years ago, many religious people enthusiastically welcomed and loudly en- dorsed what is popularly known as the Big Bang Theory of Physical Cosmol- ogy. The physical event which was postulated to have issued in an almost inconceivable, explosive origination of our current cosmos was widely bap- tized as a scientific acknowledgement of the act of divine creation.
    [Show full text]
  • Volume 1 a Collection of Essays Presented at the First Frances White Ewbank Colloquium on C.S
    Inklings Forever Volume 1 A Collection of Essays Presented at the First Frances White Ewbank Colloquium on C.S. Lewis & Article 1 Friends 1997 Full Issue 1997 (Volume 1) Follow this and additional works at: https://pillars.taylor.edu/inklings_forever Part of the English Language and Literature Commons, History Commons, Philosophy Commons, and the Religion Commons Recommended Citation (1997) "Full Issue 1997 (Volume 1)," Inklings Forever: Vol. 1 , Article 1. Available at: https://pillars.taylor.edu/inklings_forever/vol1/iss1/1 This Full Issue is brought to you for free and open access by the Center for the Study of C.S. Lewis & Friends at Pillars at Taylor University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Inklings Forever by an authorized editor of Pillars at Taylor University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INKLINGS FOREVER A Collection of Essays Presented at tlte First FRANCES WHITE EWBANK COLLOQUIUM on C.S. LEWIS AND FRIENDS II ~ November 13-15, 1997 Taylor University Upland, Indiana ~'...... - · · .~ ·,.-: :( ·!' '- ~- '·' "'!h .. ....... .u; ~l ' ::-t • J. ..~ ,.. _r '· ,. 1' !. ' INKLINGS FOREVER A Collection of Essays Presented at the Fh"St FRANCES WHITE EWBANK COLLOQliTUM on C.S. LEWIS AND FRIENDS Novem.ber 13-15, 1997 Published by Taylor University's Lewis and J1nends Committee July1998 This collection is dedicated to Francis White Ewbank Lewis scholar, professor, and friend to students for over fifty years ACKNOWLEDGMENTS David Neuhauser, Professor Emeritus at Taylor and Chair of the Lewis and Friends Committee, had the vision, initiative, and fortitude to take the colloquium from dream to reality. Other committee members who helped in all phases of the colloquium include Faye Chechowich, David Dickey, Bonnie Houser, Dwight Jessup, Pam Jordan, Art White, and Daryl Yost.
    [Show full text]
  • The Emergent, Self-Explaining Universe of Paul Davies – a Summary and Christian Response
    S & CB (2012), 24, 33–53 0954–4194 PAUL HIMES The Emergent, Self-explaining Universe of Paul Davies – a Summary and christian Response Physicist Paul Davies has emerged as one of the most popular scientists of the twenty-first century, despite his critique of the scientific establishment and its perceived failure to account for the origins and rational nature of the universe. Davies argues that the scientific consensus on cosmology rests on faith, both in its failure to provide an ultimate explanation for the origin of the universe and in its blind acceptance of its rational laws. As an alternative, Davies postulates an ‘emergent’ universe which contains the cause of its own existence and which renders unnecessary any sort of a personal deity. Yet Davies’s alternative falls short of providing a satisfactory cosmic explanation. Davies himself cannot adequately account for the principle of backward causation which creates his universe, and thus his paradigm still relies on a transcendent principle that remains unexplained. Furthermore, Davies’s objections against a personal god can be answered on philosophical grounds. Thus Davies’s hypothesis does not provide a superior alternative to the Christian view of God. key words: Paul Davies, physics, universe, emergent, self-causation, quantum mechanics, cosmology, time, teleology, cosmological argument, fine-tuning introduction Douglas Adams’ classic Hitchhiker’s Guide to the Galaxy tells the story of an advanced civilisation that builds a magnificent supercomputer for the sole purpose of providing the ultimate answer to the meaning of ‘life, the universe, and everything’. After millions of years of calculation, the an- swer, much to the confusion and frustration of the advanced civilisation, turns out to be ‘42’.1 Physicist Paul C.
    [Show full text]
  • Objective and Subjective Apologetical Approaches Regarding the Existence of God*
    AUC THEOLOGICA 2020 – Vol. 10, No. 1 Pag. 121–140 OBJECTIVE AND SUBJECTIVE APOLOGETICAL APPROACHES REGARDING THE EXISTENCE OF GOD* STUART NICOLSON ABSTRACT: Apologetics since the Second Vatican Council has somewhat changed to deal more with reaching the person and sowing seeds rather than winning the argument. The traditional objective arguments for the existence of God are today less effective, especially when approaching postmodern non-believers. Subjective approaches are far more effective, dealing with personal experience. Covering a wide range, Peter Kreeft offers twenty arguments for the existence of God, which can be grouped according to objective, subjective, and a transition group between these. By using different approaches and combinations of these, a consistent ‘wall’ of reasons for believing in God’s existence can be created by combining these arguments like building blocks. This paper considers the range of arguments, giv- ing summaries of the (semi-) subjective ones and commenting upon them with regards to their use, strengths, and weaknesses. It finds that as one purpose of apol- ogetics is to assist the unbeliever in coming to know God, ways of helping bring the subjective thinker to belief in God should be developed further, and Kreeft’s offering is a very useful resource for the Christian in explaining why it is reason- able to believe in God. Key words: Belief in God; Apologetics; Peter Kreeft; Objectivity; Subjectivity; Approaches; Arguments DOI: 10.14712/23363398.2020.47 Within the field of apologetics today, faced with the fluidity and subjectivity of postmodern thinking and its impact upon faith in the existence of God, it is no longer effective in many cases to present * This work was supported by GAJU [157/H/2016].
    [Show full text]
  • The Quantum God: an Investigation of the Image of God from Quantum Science
    The Quantum God: An Investigation of the Image of God from Quantum Science By Meaghean H. Richardson A Thesis Submitted to Saint Mary’s University, Halifax, Nova Scotia in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts in Theology and Religious Studies June, 2015, Halifax, Nova Scotia Copyright Meaghean H. Richardson, 2015. Approved: Dr. Anne Marie Dalton Supervisor Approved: Dr. Mary Hale Reader Approved: Dr. Magi Abdul-Masih Examiner Date: June 5, 2015 2 ABSTRACT The Quantum God: An Investigation of the Image of God from Quantum Science By Meaghean H. Richardson This thesis is an investigation of the image of God arising from understandings of quantum science and argues that it enhances ideas about God. It considers the significance of religious interpretations of quantum science and briefly examines the case of Christian theology and God’s actions in the world. The nature of quantum phenomena requires the use of imagery likened to that used in many mystical and religious traditions. Using a multivalued approach, I give equitable consideration to multiple scientific and theological interpretations to describe the God-concept presented by sources writing on the mystical implications of quantum science. The quantum demands an intellectual and academic openness, requiring the use of resources outside of science, and pushes for a holistic approach and a transition to a postmodern paradigm. Therefore, the quantum is said to be a re-enchanting force, calling for a re-evaluation of the spiritual dimension in our overall understanding of reality. June 5, 2015 3 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I must first thank my parents for their support of every kind while I chase my dreams.
    [Show full text]
  • The Argument from Desire/Longing for the Existence of God
    The Argument from Desire/Longing for the Existence of God In his autobiography The Confessions , Saint Augustine (354-430) traces the steps in his life that led to his conversion to Christianity. In his youth, Augustine indulged in a life full of worldly pleasures. He searched for a deep sense of joy and satisfaction, although nothing could satisfy this desire. That is, nothing could satisfy his desire except a right relationship with God through Christianity. Other philosophers such as Blaise Pascal, Søren Kierkegaard, and C. S. Lewis have experienced the same type of longing for the divine that has only been satisfied by knowing God. As a result, some philosophers have argued that this sense of desiring to know God serves as evidence that God exists. The Premises of the Argument One way to make the argument from desire follows these premises: 1. All natural desires have a real, corresponding satisfaction. 2. Humans naturally desire something which cannot be met in this world. Therefore, 3. Some real object must exist beyond this world, which satisfies this human desire (which is God). The first premise can be supported from our own experience. We experience the desire to eat. This sense of hunger exists because it is something our bodies need to survive. Our sense of hunger exists as a way to ensure we survive. Similarly, we thirst when we need water, and we have a natural drive for sex. All of these natural desires point to a real fulfillment of those desires. They all point to a real object that satisfies them.
    [Show full text]
  • 12 Arguments for the Existence of God
    12 Arguments for the Existence of God Author Caner Taslaman Translated by Selçuk AKTÜRK Cosmo Publishing Cosmo Publishing Company UNITED STATES OF AMERICA ISBN: All rights reserved, including the rights of reproduction in whole or in part of any form. CONTENT Preface 1 Introduction 2 PART I ARGUMENTS FROM THE UNIVERSE 9 1. The Kalam Cosmological Argument 10 2. Argument from the Existence of Laws 18 3. Argument from the Discoverability of the Universe 24 4. Argument from the Potentiality of the Universe 32 5. Argument from the Fine Tunings of the Physical Laws and Constants 39 6. Argument from the Fine Tuning of Physical Phenomena 46 7. Argument from Life’s Design 52 PART II ARGUMENTS FROM HUMAN NATURE 65 8. Argument from Natural Desires 66 9. Argument from Innate Morality 76 10. Argument from Reason 85 11. Argument from Will 93 12. Argument from Consciousness and Self 104 Epilogue 121 12 Arguments for the Existence of God Preface Claims of obsoleteness for presenting arguments for the existence of God, or that these arguments now belong to the dusty shelves of history; stemming often from Hume, Kant or Marxist philosophies, from New Atheism, from positivism or from religious cults belittling human reason… I contend that these claims are naïve, and they do not stand on consistent grounds. I present details of my contention organized into twelve arguments. Some of the arguments are also presented in greater depth in my other works. Judgment on whether God exists or not has a profound impact on our perception of ourselves, our beloved ones, the earth and the entire universe.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Religion
    Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Religion INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY: PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION BEAU BRANSON, MARCUS WILLIAM HUNT, TIMOTHY D KNEPPER, ROBERT SLOAN LEE, STEVEN STEYL, HANS VAN EYGHEN, BEAU BRANSON (BOOK EDITOR), AND CHRISTINA HENDRICKS (SERIES EDITOR) Rebus Community Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Religion by Beau Branson, Marcus William Hunt, Timothy D Knepper, Robert Sloan Lee, Steven Steyl, Hans Van Eyghen, Beau Branson (Book Editor), and Christina Hendricks (Series Editor) is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted. DEDICATION To Roger Branson — the best dad I ever had. For all the sacrifices I know ouy made. And for all the ones I don’t. CONTENTS What is an Open Textbook? ix Christina Hendricks How to Access and Use the Books xi Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Series xiii Christina Hendricks Praise for the Book xvi Acknowledgements xviii Beau Branson and Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Book 1 Beau Branson 1. The Intertwining of Philosophy and Religion in the Western Tradition 7 Beau Branson 2. Reasons to Believe – Theoretical Arguments 18 Marcus William Hunt 3. Non-Standard Arguments for God’s Existence 30 Robert Sloan Lee 4. Reasons Not to Believe 49 Steven Steyl 5. Debunking Arguments against Theistic Belief 62 Hans Van Eyghen 6. From Philosophy of (Mono)theism to Philosophy of Religions 74 Timothy D Knepper Glossary 87 About the Contributors 91 Feedback and Suggestions 94 Adoption Form 95 Licensing and Attribution Information 96 Review Statement 98 Accessibility Assessment 99 Version History 101 WHAT IS AN OPEN TEXTBOOK? CHRISTINA HENDRICKS An open textbook is like a commercial textbook, except: (1) it is publicly available online free of charge (and at low-cost in print), and (2) it has an open license that allows others to reuse it, download and revise it, and redistribute it.
    [Show full text]
  • 20 Arguments for the Existence Of
    Twenty Arguments for the Existence of God 1. The Argument from Change [An Aspect of the Cosmological Argument] • The universe is filled with changing things; as far as we know, the entire universe is changing. • All change needs an outside force to actualize it. • Therefore, there is some force outside (in addition to) the universe, some real being transcendent to the universe. This being we call “God.” 2. The Argument from Efficient Causality [An Aspect of the Cosmological Argument] • All things that exist are the result of some cause. • There must be something uncaused, something on which all things that need an efficient cause of being are dependent. This being we call “God.” • The idea that something can be caused by nothing is absurd. 3. The Argument from Time and Contingency • The universe is filled with things that do not need to exist; their existence is not necessary. • There must be something in the universe which must exist; some absolute necessary being. This necessary being we call “God.” 4. The Argument from Degrees of Perfection • The existence of degrees of perfection means that there is a perfect ideal. • The concept of a perfect ideal applies not only to material things and properties, but also to being. • There exists an absolutely Perfect Being, whom we call “God.” 5. The Argument from Design [Teleological Argument] • The universe displays a staggering amount of design. • This design is the result of either chance or intelligence. • Chance is a completely inadequate explanation for design; therefore it must be designed by a Supreme Intelligence. This Supreme Intelligence we call “God.” 6.
    [Show full text]