Access to Electronic Thesis

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Access to Electronic Thesis Access to Electronic Thesis Author: Jessica F. Leech Thesis title: The Varieties of Modality: Kantian Prospects for a Relativist Account Qualification: PhD This electronic thesis is protected by the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. No reproduction is permitted without consent of the author. It is also protected by the Creative Commons Licence allowing Attributions-Non-commercial-No derivatives. If this electronic thesis has been edited by the author it will be indicated as such on the title page and in the text. The Varieties of Modality: Kantian Prospects for A Relativist Account Jessica F. Leech Thesis for Doctor of Letters \Cotutelle" between the University of Geneva and the University of Sheffield Department of Philosophy President: Kevin Mulligan (Geneva) Supervisors: Fabrice Correia (Geneva) and Bob Hale (Sheffield) July 2011 Abstract The aim of this thesis is to present and motivate the relative modality view, whereby at least the non-logical alethic kinds of modality are mere relative forms of logical modality. The first chapter is devoted to presenting the relative modality view in general, providing a correct formulation, and con- sidering some arguments for and against. The next chapter considers the particular challenges raised for the view by some essentialists. The third chapter turns to look at logical modality, the bedrock of the relative modal- ity view, and presents an example of an account of logical necessity which suits it well. I argue that logical necessity is that necessity implicated in a deductively valid argument, and hence that its source is to be found in an account of the laws of logic. I argue that the laws of logic are constitutive- normative laws of thought. The fourth chapter takes a more historical turn. Here I argue that Kant can be understood as advocating a relative modality view, in particular for what he calls \real modality". In the fifth and final chapter I will draw on the conclusions of the preceding chapters to present a Kantian relative account of metaphysical necessity. Metaphysical necessity is that which follows, as a matter of logical necessity, from conditions on our having any experience of an objective world. I argue why this Kant-inspired kind of relative necessity is well-suited to play the role of metaphysical ne- cessity, and consider how the view accommodates contemporary views about features of metaphysical necessity and its typical cases. 1 Acknowledgements First and foremost, I am grateful to Fabrice Correia and the University of Geneva for awarding me a doctoral student position on the research project \Theory of Essence", and to the Swiss National Science Foundation for funding the project, without which I may never have been able to pursue further study in philosophy. This project is part of the ~ιδo& Centre for Metaphysics at the University of Geneva. Thank you also to the Pro*Doc postgraduate school in philosophy, also funded by the Swiss National Sci- ence Foundation, which provided me with funds to attend conferences which have helped me greatly. Warm thanks also go to those at the University of Sheffield and the University of Geneva who made it possible for me to or- ganize a \cotutelle" between the two institutions. I have presented work which contributed to this thesis at seminars and workshops in Sheffield, Ab- erdeen, Leiden and Geneva. I would like to thank all of the organizers and participants of these events for their helpful contributions and comments. Thank you to Bob Stern and Katie Harrington for taking the time to read and give feedback on the Kant-based parts of the thesis. Thank you to Mark Textor for his unerring support and German-English translations. Finally, most thanks must go to my two supervisors, Fabrice Correia and Bob Hale. Both have been a constant source of support, inspiration and help. Each has contributed in their own unique way to teaching me how to be a better philosopher, and I have immensely enjoyed working with them both. 2 Contents Introduction 6 1 Relative Modality 10 1.1 Formulating Relative Modality . 10 1.1.1 Consequence and Conditionals . 10 1.1.2 Derivative Modality . 12 1.1.3 Logical Problems . 14 1.1.4 Adding a conjunct(disjunct) . 17 1.1.5 Quantifiers . 20 1.2 The Scope of an Account of Relative Modality . 26 1.2.1 Epistemic Modality . 26 1.2.2 Propositional Attitudes . 29 1.2.3 Inconsistent Conditions . 31 1.2.4 Relevant Logic . 33 1.3 Some Arguments For and Against . 37 1.3.1 The Argument from Linguistics . 37 1.3.2 Similarities and Differences . 40 1.3.3 The Argument from Unreality . 45 1.3.4 New Jersey Necessity . 47 1.3.5 Finean Counterexamples . 50 2 Essentialism and Relative Modality 56 2.1 Absolute Necessities . 56 2.2 Shalkowski's Critique . 62 2.2.1 Against Hale . 62 2.2.2 Against the Anti-Essentialist . 67 2.3 A Problem for Logical Necessity . 73 3 A Logical Basis for Relative Modality 76 3.1 The Search for Fundamental Modality . 76 3.2 What is Logical Necessity? . 78 3.2.1 Logical Necessity and Deductive Validity . 78 3.2.2 McFetridge on Belief in Logical Necessity . 80 3 3.2.3 Rumfitt on Logical Philonianism . 84 3.3 Laws of Thought . 87 3.3.1 The Strategy . 87 3.3.2 Introducing Laws of Thought . 88 3.3.3 Constitutive Laws . 91 3.3.4 Norms for Thought . 93 3.4 Logic and Rational Indubitability . 95 3.4.1 A Logocentric Predicament? . 95 3.4.2 McFetridge Again . 96 3.4.3 The Minimal Principle of Contradiction . 98 3.4.4 The Minimal Logical Toolkit . 102 3.4.5 Logic and the Web of Belief . 110 3.5 Constitutive-Normative Laws of Thought . 115 3.5.1 The Explanandum . 115 3.5.2 Alternative Explanations . 116 3.5.3 Constitutive Norms for Thought . 122 3.5.4 Necessity, Truth and Opting Out . 124 3.5.5 Different Logics . 133 3.5.6 The Essence of Thought? . 136 3.5.7 The Stream of Consciousness . 142 3.6 A Logical Basis for Relative Modality . 142 4 Kant and Modality 144 4.1 Kant and Modality: An Overview . 144 4.1.1 The Tables of Judgments and Categories . 144 4.1.2 Modal Categories and the Postulates . 148 4.1.3 The Concept of a Thing . 151 4.1.4 Relative Modality . 156 4.1.5 Possible Experience . 157 4.2 Possibility, Actuality and Necessity . 159 4.2.1 Possibility . 159 4.2.2 Actuality . 163 4.2.3 Necessity . 168 4.3 The Main Theses . 171 4.3.1 Real and Logical Predicates . 171 4.3.2 The Relative Modality Thesis . 176 4.3.3 The Categories and \Kantian Modality" . 183 4.3.4 Mind-Dependence . 192 4.4 Real Modality and Logical Modality . 197 4.4.1 Real and Logical Possibility . 197 4.4.2 Logical Necessity . 202 4.5 Abstract Objects and Mathematics . 204 4 5 Metaphysical Necessity: A Relative and Kantian Account 208 5.1 Different Options . 212 5.1.1 Possible worlds . 213 5.1.2 The Principles of Possibility . 215 5.1.3 Essentialism . 218 5.1.4 Deflationism . 221 5.2 A Kantian Relative Modality View . 224 5.2.1 Conditions on Experience . 225 5.2.2 Metaphysical Necessity? . 233 5.2.3 Metaphysical Necessity and Logical Necessity . 237 5.3 Further Issues . 241 5.3.1 Mathematical Necessity and Mathematical Truth . 241 5.3.2 De Re Necessity . 243 5.3.3 The Necessary A Posteriori . 247 5.4 Typical Cases . 250 5.4.1 Kantian Cases and Mathematical Truths . 250 5.4.2 Identity . 251 5.4.3 Essentiality Theses . 255 5.5 The Case for Kantian Metaphysical Necessity . 257 Bibliography 261 5 Introduction There is a surfeit of questions to be asked about possibility and necessity. One family of questions concerns different kinds of modality, including ques- tions such as: How many different kinds of modality are there? Are some of those kinds of modality definable in terms of/reducible to other kinds? Is one kind of necessity absolute, i.e. at least as strong as every other kind of necessity? Are some kinds of modality simply incommensurable? In the following, I hope to begin addressing some of these questions. I plan to motivate and develop an account of modality according to which at least the standard alethic modalities (metaphysical, mathematical, natural, etc.), if not further kinds of modality (epistemic, deontic), are relative forms of logical modality. A different kind of question concerns the very nature of possibility and necessity. Such issues will have an important role to play in a fully-developed account of relative modality. If an account can be given of the (non-logical) alethic modalities in terms of logical modality, then an investigation into the source and nature of logical modality should potentially provide an account of the source and nature of all alethic modalities. If the relative modality account can be extended further to other, non-alethic modalities, then such an investigation would have the potential to get to the heart of modality tout court. My discussion of relative modality will be set against a background agenda to potentially provide an alternative to certain popular accounts of the nature of modality. For one, my aim is to try to give an account of modality which does not make use of the notion of a possible world. To properly argue against any possible worlds account of the nature of modality would be a hefty project in itself, so I will limit myself to a few remarks.
Recommended publications
  • Why Essentialism Requires Two Senses of Necessity’, Ratio 19 (2006): 77–91
    Please cite the official published version of this article: ‘Why Essentialism Requires Two Senses of Necessity’, Ratio 19 (2006): 77–91. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9329.2006.00310.x WHY ESSENTIALISM REQUIRES TWO SENSES OF NECESSITY1 Stephen K. McLeod Abstract I set up a dilemma, concerning metaphysical modality de re, for the essentialist opponent of a ‘two senses’ view of necessity. I focus specifically on Frank Jackson’s two- dimensional account in his From Metaphysics to Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998). I set out the background to Jackson’s conception of conceptual analysis and his rejection of a two senses view. I proceed to outline two purportedly objective (as opposed to epistemic) differences between metaphysical and logical necessity. I conclude that since one of these differences must hold and since each requires the adoption of a two senses view of necessity, essentialism is not consistent with the rejection of a two senses view. I. Terminological Preliminaries The essentialist holds that some but not all of a concrete object’s properties are had necessarily and that necessary properties include properties that are, unlike the property 1 Thanks to John Divers, audiences at the Open University Regional Centre, Leeds and the University of Glasgow and an anonymous referee for comments. 2 of being such that logical and mathematical truths hold, non-trivially necessary. It is a necessary condition on a property’s being essential to an object that it is had of necessity. In the case of concrete objects, some such properties are discoverable by partly empirical means.
    [Show full text]
  • On Categories and a Posteriori Necessity: a Phenomenological Echo
    © 2012 The Author Metaphilosophy © 2012 Metaphilosophy LLC and Blackwell Publishing Ltd Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK, and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 43, Nos. 1–2, January 2012 0026-1068 ON CATEGORIES AND A POSTERIORI NECESSITY: A PHENOMENOLOGICAL ECHO M. J. GARCIA-ENCINAS Abstract: This article argues for two related theses. First, it defends a general thesis: any kind of necessity, including metaphysical necessity, can only be known a priori. Second, however, it also argues that the sort of a priori involved in modal metaphysical knowledge is not related to imagination or any sort of so-called epistemic possibility. Imagination is neither a proof of possibility nor a limit to necessity. Rather, modal metaphysical knowledge is built on intuition of philo- sophical categories and the structures they form. Keywords: a priori, categories, intuition, metaphysical necessity. Fantasy abandoned by reason produces impossible monsters. —Francisco de Goya (1746–1828), The Caprices, plate 43, The Sleep of Reason Produces Monsters 1. Introduction Statements of fact are necessarily true when their truth-maker facts cannot but be the case. Statements of fact are contingently true when their truth-maker facts might not have been the case. I shall argue that modal knowledge, that is, knowledge that a (true/false) statement is necessarily/ contingently true, must be a priori knowledge, even if knowledge that the statement is true or false can be a posteriori. In particular, justified accept- ance of necessary facts requires a priori modal insight concerning some category which they instantiate. In this introduction, the first part of the article, I maintain that Kripke claimed that the knowledge that a statement has its truth-value as a matter of necessity/contingency is a priori founded—even when knowl- edge of its truth/falsehood is a posteriori.
    [Show full text]
  • The Transience of Possibility Reina Hayaki
    Forthcoming in the European Journal of Analytic Philosophy (2006). The Transience of Possibility Reina Hayaki ABSTRACT. The standard view of metaphysical necessity is that it is truth in all possible worlds, and therefore that the correct modal logic for metaphysical necessity is S5, in models of which all worlds are accessible from each other. I argue that S5 cannot be the correct logic for metaphysical necessity because accessibility is not symmetric: there are possible worlds that are accessible from ours but from which our world is not accessible. There are (or could be) some individuals who, if they had not existed, could not have existed. Once the possibility of such individuals is lost, it is gone forever. 1. Truth in all possible worlds? It is now widely (though not universally) accepted that metaphysical necessity is to be distinguished from logical necessity. A proposition is logically necessary if it is a theorem of logic. The notion of logical necessity is not without its problems. When we say “a theorem of logic”, which logic is appropriate for this definition? Should we use mere first-order logic, or something more powerful? (Are axioms of second-order logic logically necessary truths?) What if the relevant logic is not complete, so that some true sentences are not theorems? Are all mathematical truths logically necessary? Or, given the apparent failure of efforts to reduce mathematics to logic, should we say that some 1 mathematical propositions are not logically necessary but perhaps “mathematically necessary”, relative to a particular system of mathematics? How should we adjudicate wrangling between adherents of mutually incompatible logics, such as classical and non- classical logics? Regardless of how we answer these questions, the notion of logical necessity is at heart a syntactic one.
    [Show full text]
  • Ither Metaphysical Necessity?
    This is a repository copy of W(h)ither Metaphysical Necessity?. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/131388/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Divers, J orcid.org/0000-0002-1286-6587 (2018) W(h)ither Metaphysical Necessity? Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 92 (1). pp. 1-25. ISSN 0309-7013 https://doi.org/10.1093/arisup/aky008 (c) 2018 The Aristotelian Society This is a pre-copyedited, author-produced PDF of an article accepted for publication in Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume xcii following peer review. The version of record Divers, J (2018) W(h)ither Metaphysical Necessity? Aristotelean Society Supplementary Volume, 92 (1). pp. 1-25. ISSN 0309-7013 is available online at: https://doi.org/10.1093/arisup/aky008. Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ W(H)ITHER METAPHYSICAL NECESSITY? By John Divers G20, Michael Sadler Building, University of Leeds, Leeds LS2 9JT Abstract I argue that a pragmatic scepticism about metaphysical modality is a perfectly reasonable position to maintain.
    [Show full text]
  • "Metaphysical" Possibility Revisited
    Justin Clarke-Doane Columbia University “Metaphysical” Possibility Revisited Metaphysical Possibility: That alethic, non-deontic, modality whose necessities are supposed to include the likes of conceptual truths, (pure) mathematical truths, truths of fundamental ontology (such as that there are, or are not, propositions, properties, or possible worlds), mereological truths, identity truths, explanatorily basic normative truths, and grounding truths. o Sider: “We are told that logic…is metaphysically necessary. We are told that laws of nature are not….[I]t is metaphysically necessary that “nothing can be in two places at once”, and so on. This conception falls…short of a full criterion. But a thin conception is not in itself problematic. For when a notion is taken to be fundamental, one often assumes that the facts involving the notion will outrun one's conception [2011, 266].” It is widely agreed that the intelligibility of metaphysical modality has been vindicated. o Quine: “I do not myself make sense…of metaphysical necessity [1990, 224].” o Williamson: “[M]etaphysical modality is only one member of the extended family of objective modalities. Arguments for scepticism about metaphysical modality tend [implausibly] to generalize to other objective modalities [2016, 462].” But even if metaphysical modality is intelligible, it could lack much metaphysical significance. I will argue that this is the case, and will conclude with an alternative conception of possibility. Extant “Deflationist” Critiques Sidelle [1989] & Unger [2014]: “Twin Earth” thought experiments just concern the meaning of a word. We all agree what worlds there are. We just disagree about how to describe them. Problem: This critique is quite limited.
    [Show full text]
  • Causal Necessity in Aristotle (Final Version)
    Causal Necessity in Aristotle Nathanael Stein [to appear in the British Journal for the History of Philosophy] 1. Introduction Recent discussions of causation have seen a revival of several concepts after a period in which Humean and neo-Humean views and critiques had rendered them suspect: causal powers, dispositions, and causal necessitation.1 Along these lines, for example, some theorists appeal to causal powers as genuine features of objects which enable them to act on other things, while others explicate the idea of causal determination by appealing to and defending the idea of causal necessitation.2 In general, the redeployments of these concepts figure in attempts to understand the relation of causation as one in which causes determine or bring about their effects in virtue of their intrinsic 1 The notion of causal necessity, for example, has been defended by several theorists: the so-called Dretske- Tooley-Armstrong (Dretske (1977), Tooley (1977), Armstrong (1983)) theory of natural laws posits nomological (as distinct from metaphysical) necessitation relations between universals, while Shoemaker (1998) argues that causal necessity simply is a kind of metaphysical necessity, one which is rooted in the causal powers of certain properties. Powers and dispositions, once widely ridiculed as explanatorily vacuous, have been defended by Harré (1970), Shoemaker (1980), Cartwright (1994), Heil (2005), and Martin (1994), among others. These views contrast with so-called counterfactual analyses of causation, the most well-known of which is that of David Lewis (1973), (1994), and (2000), attempt to account for causation without appealing to causal necessitation, often citing Hume as the reason for their doing so, as Lewis does.
    [Show full text]
  • CAUSAL and METAPHYSICAL NECESSITY 61 Possibility
    CAUSAL AND METAPHYSICAL View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk NECESSITY brought to you by CORE provided by PhilPapers BY SYDNEY SHOEMAKER Abstract: Any property has two sorts of causal features: “forward-looking” ones, having to do with what its instantiation can contribute to causing, and “backward-looking” ones, having to do with how its instantiation can be caused. Such features of a property are essential to it, and properties sharing all of their causal features are identical. Causal necessity is thus a special case of metaphysical necessity. Appeals to imaginability have no more force against this view than they do against the Kripkean view that statements like “Gold is an element” are metaphysically necessary. 1. There was a time, within the memory of some of us, when it was widely accepted that there are just two kinds of necessity. There was logical necessity, which was generally construed as including the necessity of analytic truths. This was assumed to be something to which we have an a priori access. And there was causal necessity, to which our only access is empirical. Since the dominant views about causality then current were Humean in inspiration, there was some question as to how so-called causal necessity, the distinctive status of causal laws and their consequences, deserved the name of “necessity” at all. But that was what it was frequently called. Since then the boat has been radically rocked, first by Quine and then by Kripke. The intended effects of their attacks on the traditional view were of course very different.
    [Show full text]
  • How to Make Possibility Safe for Empiricists Abstract 1. Introduction
    Draft commenced August 31, 2020. Version of October 16, 26, November 4, 2020; January 12, February 21, March 1, 2021. Typo corrections, August 26, 2021 How to Make Possibility Safe for Empiricists John D. Norton1 Department of History and Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh http://www.pitt.edu/~jdnorton Abstract What is possible, according to the empiricist conception, is what our evidence positively allows; and what is necessary is what it compels. These notions, along with logical possibility, are the only defensible notions of possibility and necessity. In so far as nomic and metaphysical possibilities are defensible, they fall within empirical possibility. These empirical conceptions are incompatible with traditional possible world semantics. Empirically necessary propositions cannot be defined as those true in all possible worlds. There can be empirical possibilities without empirical necessities. The duality of possibility and necessity can be degenerate and can even be falsified. 1. Introduction What are “small-e” empiricist2 philosophers of science, like me, to make of possibilities? They are central to science. Our best theories of gravity and stellar structure tell us that it is 1 My thanks to Yemima Ben-Menahem, Jeremy Butterfield, Patrick Dürr, Carl Hoefer, Edouard Machery, Brian McLoone, James Norton, Matt Parker, Bryan Roberts, Margot Strohminger and Jim Woodward for helpful discussion. They bear no responsibility for the content of this paper other than for failing to talk me out of it. 2 A “small-e” empiricist holds that we can only learn contingent truths of the world from experiences of the world. A “big-E” Empiricist holds the stronger view that these experiences are all we can learn.
    [Show full text]
  • Necessity and Contingency in Leibniz. G
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 1-1-1974 Necessity and contingency in Leibniz. G. W. Fitch University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1 Recommended Citation Fitch, G. W., "Necessity and contingency in Leibniz." (1974). Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014. 2083. https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_1/2083 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations 1896 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. NECESSITY AND CONTINGENCY IN LEIBNIZ A Dissertation Presented By GREGORY WERNER FITCH Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY September 1974 Philosophy (c) Gregory Werner Fitch 1974 All Rights Reserved iii NECESSITY AND CONTINGENCY IN LEIBNIZ A Dissertation By GREGORY WERNER FITCH Approved as to style and content by: clJLl -i Robert C. Sle'igh'Jr., Ph.D., Chairman of Committee Vere C. Chappell, Ph.D., Member /) t Fred A. Feldman, Ph.D. , Member % U* r rank W. Heny, Ph.D. Member \14ajL C, Vere C. Chappell, Ph.D., Department Head Department of Philosophy September 1974 Necessity and Contingency in Leibniz (September 1974) Gregory W. Fitch, B.A. , Western Washington State College M.A, , University of Massachusetts Directed by: Robert C. Sleigh Jr., Ph.D. Among the objections raised against Leibniz's metaphysical views, the problem of contingency is one of the most crucial and difficult problems Leibniz faced.
    [Show full text]
  • Leibniz on Contingency and Freedom: a Molinism Friendly Account
    Leibniz on Contingency and Freedom: A Molinism Friendly Account Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Juan Garcia, MA Graduate Program in Philosophy The Ohio State University 2018 Dissertation Committee: Tamar Rudavsky, Advisor Julia Jorati, Advisor Lisa Downing William Taschek © 2018 by Juan Garcia All rights reserved. Abstract: Some philosophical ideas, like metals, reveal their most interesting qualities when stretched. As I see it, the intelligibility and plausibility of the concept of contingency, as a condition for freedom, is stretched significantly by three of Leibniz’s major philosophical commitments: i) a robust version of the principle of sufficient reason; ii) strong theological commitments like divine foreknowledge and robust providence; and iii) Leibniz’s distinctive thesis of complete individual concepts – the doctrine that every substance has an individual concept which includes predicates denoting everything that will ever happen to it. Many interpreters think that these Leibnizian commitments stretch contingency to the breaking point: Leibniz cannot retain a genuine type of contingency. In this dissertation, I argue that these interpreters are mistaken and that Leibniz can accommodate a plausible type of contingency. Two important steps in reaching this conclusion are the following. First, I identify a kind of explanation of rational action according to which the explanans does not necessitate the explanandum. Second, I develop an account that makes sense of individual concepts including contingent truths as contingent. This account both sheds new light on some of Leibniz’s central views on contingency and freedom, and expands our substantive understanding of contingency as a condition for freedom.
    [Show full text]
  • Logical Combinatorialism
    Logical Combinatorialism Andrew Bacon* July 13, 2020 Abstract In explaining the notion of a fundamental property or relation, metaphysicians will often draw an analogy with languages. The fundamental properties and relations stand to reality as the primitive predicates and relations stand to a language: the smallest set of vocabulary God would need in order to write the `book of the world'. In this paper I attempt to make good on this metaphor. In order to do this I introduce a modality that, put informally, stands to propositions as logical truth stands to sentences. The resulting theory, formulated in higher-order logic, also vindicates the Humean idea that fundamental properties and relations are freely recombinable and a variant of the structural idea that propositions can be decomposed into their fundamental constituents via logical operations. Indeed, it is seen that, although these ideas are seemingly distinct, they are not independent, and fall out of a natural and general theory about the granularity of reality. Metaphysicians often theorize in terms of the notion of a property or relation being fundamental. When it comes to spelling out what this means, metaphors abound. According to one gloss, the fundamental properties and relations are the primitive constants in the language of reality, from which all other properties and relations can be defined; they are the vocabulary God would need in order to write the `book of the world' (Sider (2011)). The metaphor of reality as a language is one that is hard to make precise, and, taken too literally, has been shown to be subject to paradoxes.1 I take this as a warning to proceed cautiously, by codifying our metaphysics in a precise formal language where possible | in this case, higher-order logic | and employing model theoretic techniques to check for consistency.
    [Show full text]
  • Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume's Treatise
    Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume’s Treatise Miren Boehm Abstract: Hume appeals to different kinds of certainties and necessities in the Treatise. He contrasts the certainty that arises from intuition and demonstrative reasoning with the certainty that arises from causal reasoning. He denies that the causal maxim is absolutely or metaphysically necessary, but he nonetheless takes the causal maxim and ‘proofs’ to be necessary. The focus of this paper is the certainty and necessity involved in Hume’s concept of knowledge. I defend the view that intuitive certainty, in particular, is certainty of the invariability or necessity of relations between ideas. Against David Owen and Helen Beebee, I argue that the certainty involved in intuition depends on the activity of the mind. I argue, further, that understanding this activity helps us understand more clearly one of Hume’s most important theses, namely that experience is the source of a distinct kind of certainty and of necessity. Hume acknowledges that the general maxim in philosophy: “whatever begins to exist, must have a cause of existence” is “suppos’d to be founded on intuition, and to be one of those maxims, which […] ’tis impossible for men in their hearts really to doubt of” (T 1.3.3.1).1 But he maintains that, if we examine the maxim by his “idea of knowledge,” “we shall discover in it no mark of any such intuitive certainty; but on the contrary shall find, that ‘tis of a nature quite foreign to that species of 1. David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, ed.
    [Show full text]