BOETHIUS NOSTER: Thierry of Chartres's ARITHMETICA

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

BOETHIUS NOSTER: Thierry of Chartres's ARITHMETICA BOETHIUS NOSTER: THIERRY OF CHARtres’s ARITHMETICA COMMENTARY AS A MISSING SOURCE OF NICHOLAS OF Cusa’s DE docta IGNORANTIA David ALBERTSON Abstract Nicholas of Cusa is known to have used several sources stemming from the twelfth-century master Thierry of Chartres in the composition of his treatise De docta ignorantia (1440). To date these works have included Thierry’s famous hexaemeral commentary, his three commentaries on Boethius’s De trinitate, and later anonymous works by Thierry’s readers. Given Irene Caiazzo’s recent discovery of Thierry’s commentary on Boethius’s De arithmetica, we can now evaluate the possibility that this work was another Cusan source before 1440. Numerous parallels in Books I and II of De docta ignorantia suggest that Cus- anus made use of Thierry’s Arithmetica commentary while adapting four Boethian concepts to theological ends: precise equality, primordial number, the quadrivial arts, and folding. This finding raises new questions about the status of the controversial Fundamentum naturae manuscript. After over a century of scholarship on Nicholas of Cusa’s De docta ignorantia, one might expect its fundamental mystery to have been solved. How did a busy lawyer with modest philosophical training compose such an original volume, far from the usual ways of the medieval schools, as Nicholas himself boasted? As Hans Gerhard Sen- ger has observed, “the fact that a 40-year-old suddenly came up with such a well thought-out and substantive philosophy is surprising.”1 1. H. G. SENGER, Die Philosophie des Nikolaus von Kues vor dem Jahre 1440: Unter- suchungen zur Entwicklung einer Philosophie in der Frühzeit des Nikolaus (1430-1440), Münster 1971, p. 7. See also H. G. SENGER, “‚in mari me ex Graecia redeunte, credo superno dono‘ – Vom Wissensfrust zur gelehrten Unwissenheit. Wie platzte 1437/1438 Recherches de Théologie et Philosophie médiévales 83(1), 143-199. doi: 10.2143/RTPM.83.1.3154587 © 2016 by Recherches de Théologie et Philosophie médiévales. All rights reserved. 003_98858_RTPM_2016-1.indb 143 16/06/16 10:34 144 D. ALBERTSON Martin Honecker has shown that the two years preceding the work’s completion in February 1440 were exceptionally busy for Cusanus. Only eight of those twenty-four months would have permitted him sufficient leisure to write.2 In order to explain the novelty of De docta ignorantia – unless we credit Cusanus’s claim of divine illumination – we must consider other sources that might have assisted its author.3 The ideas of Ps.-Dionysius, Meister Eckhart, and Ramon Llull all inform the agenda of De docta ignorantia, but their own words appear infrequently throughout the text. Senger has proposed that perhaps Nicholas’s early interest in calendrical calculations and astronomical instruments might explain his sudden turn to arithmetic and geom- etry in De docta ignorantia.4 Alongside these influences, one should also examine the complex body of source materials stemming from Thierry of Chartres (d. 1157), a well-regarded master in twelfth-century Paris. Thierry’s creative re- reading of the Boethian tradition led him to what we might call a Trinitarian theology of the quadrivium and therefore, if accidentally, to the first substantive Christian engagement with Neopythagoreanism. Unlike his other sources, Nicholas regularly cited these texts connected with Thierry of Chartres word for word. To date there are three catego- ries of such Chartrian sources. (1) As Pierre Duhem and Raymond der Knoten?,” in: A. SPEER – Ph. STEINKRÜGER (eds.), Knotenpunkt Byzanz. Wissensformen und kulturelle Wechselbeziehungen, Berlin 2012, pp. 481-495. 2. See M. HONECKER, “Die Entstehungszeit der ‘Docta ignorantia’ des Nikolaus von Cues,” in: Historisches Jahrbuch 60 (1940), pp. 124-141; and R. KLIbaNSKY, “Zur Geschichte der Überlieferung der Docta ignorantia des Nikolaus von Kues,” in: Nikolaus von Kues: Die belehrte Unwissenheit, Buch III, ed. P. WILPERT – H. G. SENGER, Hamburg 1977, pp. 216-219. 3. NICHOLAS OF CUSA, “Epistola auctoris,” De docta ignorantia, III, 263, in: Nikolaus von Kues. Philosophisch-theologische Werke, Band 1: De docta ignorantia, ed. P. WILPERT – H. G. SENGER, Hamburg 1999, pp. 98-100: “Accipe nunc, pater metuende, quae iam dudum attingere variis doctrinarum viis concupivi, sed prius non potui, quousque in mari me ex Graecia redeunte, credo superno dono a patre luminum a quo omne datum opti- mum, ad hoc ductus sum, ut incomprehensibilia incomprehensibiliter amplecterer in docta ignorantia per transcensum veritatum incorruptibilium humaniter scibilium.” Cf. H. L. BOND, “Nicholas of Cusa from Constantinople to ‘Learned Ignorance’: The Historical Matrix for the Formation of De docta ignorantia,” in: G. CHRISTIANSON – T. M. IZBICKI (eds.), Nicholas of Cusa on Christ and the Church, Leiden 1996, pp. 135- 163; M. O’ROURKE BOYLE, “Cusanus at Sea: The Topicality of Illuminative Discourse,” in: Journal of Religion 71 (1991), pp. 180-191; and H. G. SENGER, “‚in mari me ex Graecia redeunte, credo superno dono‘.” 4. See H. G. SENGER, Die Philosophie des Nikolaus von Kues, pp. 106-129, 153-154. 003_98858_RTPM_2016-1.indb 144 16/06/16 10:34 BOETHIUS NOSTER … 145 Klibansky first discovered, several passages from Thierry’s own com- mentaries are peppered throughout De docta ignorantia as well as later texts like Idiota de mente (1450). Nikolaus Häring’s editions of Thier- ry’s hexaemeral commentary, Tractatus de sex dierum operibus, as well as his three successive commentaries on Boethius’s De trinitate, have allowed for more precise identifications, especially in the first book of De docta ignorantia.5 (2) Nicholas also borrowed from anonymous works by Thierry’s twelfth-century readers, above all, De septem septenis,6 a Hermetic tract long misattributed to John of Salisbury, and the stu- dent notes edited as Commentarius Victorinus.7 (3) Maarten Hoenen has presented compelling evidence that Cusanus drew upon a philo- sophical treatise recently found in the library of a fifteenth-century Dominican in Eichstätt. Hoenen argues that Cusanus inserted long portions of this anonymous work, Fundamentum naturae quod physicos ignorasse videtur, into Book II of De docta ignorantia.8 Thierry’s ideas are prominent in the treatise, but only because the author intends to refute them, a fact that Nicholas may have overlooked.9 That is to say: Nicholas seems to have jumbled together Thierry’s own works with those of his reception history. This medley of sources is fragmentary, sometimes confused, and occasionally contradictory, but the family resemblance is hard to miss. Even when stretched or upended by his medieval readers, Thierry’s signature doctrines remain unmistakeable. Nicholas must have noticed their similar parentage, and appreciated their collective force, for in Apologia doctae ignorantiae 5. See Commentaries on Boethius by Thierry of Chartres and His School, ed. N. M. HÄRING, Toronto 1971. 6. See De septem septenis, PL 199, cols. 945-964; cf. MS London, British Library, Harley 3969, fols. 206v-215v. On the state of the text, see C. NÉMETH, “Fabricating Philosophical Authority in the Twelfth Century: The Liber Egerimion and the De septem septenis,” in: S. KANGAS – M. KORPIOLA – T. AINONEN (eds.), Authorities in the Middle Ages: Influence, Legitimacy and Power in Medieval Society, Berlin 2013, pp. 75-76. 7. MS Paris, Bibliothèque nationale de France, Lat. 14489, fols. 67r-95v; cf. Com- mentarius Victorinus, ed. N. M. HÄRING, pp. 479-528. 8. See M. J. F. M. HOENEN, “‘Ista prius inaudita.’ Eine neuentdeckte Vorlage der De docta ignorantia und ihre Bedeutung für die frühe Philosophie des Nikolaus von Kues,” in: Medioevo: Rivista di storia della filosofia medievale 21 (1995), pp. 375-476. For the text of Fundamentum naturae quod videtur physicos ignorasse, MS Eichstätt Cod. st 687, fols. 4r-10r, see ibid., pp. 447-476. 9. See D. ALBERTSON, “A Late Medieval Reaction to Thierry of Chartres’s (d. 1157) Philosophy: The Anti-Platonist Argument of the Anonymous Fundamentum naturae,” in: Vivarium 50 (2012), pp. 53-84. 003_98858_RTPM_2016-1.indb 145 16/06/16 10:34 146 D. ALBERTSON (1449) he celebrated their common progenitor, an unnamed “Boethian commentator,” as “easily the most brilliant man of all those whom I have read” – and this after acknowledging his debts to Eckhart, Ps.- Dionysius, and Proclus without such hyperbolic praise.10 Cusanus bor- rowed frequently from Thierry’s treasury: the schema of complicatio and explicatio; the mathematical model of the Trinity as unitas, aequal- itas, and conexio; the dialectic of unitas and alteritas; the system of four modes of being spanning from absolute necessity to absolute possibil- ity; and a theology of the divine Mind as the unique equality of beings. Each of these doctrines was once attributed to Cusanus, but in fact first belonged to the Parisian master. On the basis of Häring’s editions we can now understand the dynamic nature of Thierry’s influence. Not only can we detect diachronic change within Thierry’s own theology from the 1130s to 1150s; we can also measure Nicholas’s improving grasp of those ideas over his own writing career from the 1440s to 1460s. As Cusanus acquired increasing access to the full range of Char- trian sources, he had better purchase on how they could be harmonized and applied in his own century.11 A full appraisal of Nicholas of Cusa’s debts to Thierry of Chartres has been an obvious desideratum since the outset of the Heidelberg edition. For several reasons, that task has been deferred for decades. One recent complication has been the reluctance of some scholars to accept Hoenen’s controversial claims regarding the anonymous Fun- damentum naturae treatise. According to Hoenen, Nicholas layered sections of this treatise into Book II of De docta ignorantia and added his own expositions. Hoenen contends that some of Cusanus’s most famous concepts – God as absolute maximum, finitude as contractio – originated from this anonymous source.
Recommended publications
  • Augustine on Knowledge
    Augustine on Knowledge Divine Illumination as an Argument Against Scepticism ANITA VAN DER BOS RMA: RELIGION & CULTURE Rijksuniversiteit Groningen Research Master Thesis s2217473, April 2017 FIRST SUPERVISOR: dr. M. Van Dijk SECOND SUPERVISOR: dr. dr. F.L. Roig Lanzillotta 1 2 Content Augustine on Knowledge ........................................................................................................................ 1 Acknowledgements ................................................................................................................................ 4 Preface .................................................................................................................................................... 5 Abstract ................................................................................................................................................... 6 Introduction ............................................................................................................................................ 7 The life of Saint Augustine ................................................................................................................... 9 The influence of the Contra Academicos .......................................................................................... 13 Note on the quotations ........................................................................................................................ 14 1. Scepticism ........................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Divine Illumination As “Conditio Sine Qua Non” for True Knowledge in the Philosophy of St Augustine
    DIVINE ILLUMINATION AS “CONDITIO SINE QUA NON” FOR TRUE KNOWLEDGE IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF ST AUGUSTINE Emmanuel OGUNDELE, PhD Introduction St. Augustine in many aspects of his philosophy was preoccupied with the issue of knowledge. This knowledge in the true sense is rather impossible to reach without the divine light which shines on us, for 'in His divine light we see light.' The beaming of the illuminating light of the creator who lives in unassailable light on us makes knowledge possible. For Augustine, true knowledge comes from within, through Divine illumination and not from without. This is theme that will be explored in this article. St. Augustine was born in Tagaste in 354 A.D. of a pagan father by the name Patricius and a devout Christian mother, Monica. His baptism and conversion into Christianity was delayed and he was eventually baptised in 387. He did higher studies first at Madaura and later at Carthage. At this time, he was still committed to Manichaeism. He later started teaching Rhetoric in Carthage and eventually opened a school of Rhetoric in Rome. After a while, he abandoned Manichaeism and scepticism and embraced Platonism. He had a riotous youthful life in which he lost his way into a life of sensuality. In 384 AD, he moved to Milan where he 1 2 met Bishop Ambrose who eventually baptised him on his conversion in 387 AD. His mother died in 388 AD, the year in which he returned to his homeland. In 391, the people of Hippo where he was staying in order to convert a friend acclaimed him a priest and he was finally ordained a priest by Bishop Valerius.
    [Show full text]
  • This Thesis Has Been Submitted in Fulfilment of the Requirements for a Postgraduate Degree (E.G
    This thesis has been submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for a postgraduate degree (e.g. PhD, MPhil, DClinPsychol) at the University of Edinburgh. Please note the following terms and conditions of use: • This work is protected by copyright and other intellectual property rights, which are retained by the thesis author, unless otherwise stated. • A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge. • This thesis cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author. • The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author. • When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given. Writing animals, speaking animals: the displacement and placement of the animal in medieval literature. Submitted for the degree of PhD University of Edinburgh 2003 David Moses ACKNOWLEDGMENTS DEDICATION To my parents for their unwavering love, and for daring us to believe that all things are possible. To my wife Clare, and sons James and Ethan for making it all worthwhile. To my sister Caroline for believing that it does matter. To my beloved dog Flash, who is missed so much: 'In that day I will make a covenant with the beasts of the field, with the birds of the air ... I will betroth you to Me forever; Yes I will betroth you to Me in righteousness and justice, in lovingkindness and mercy' (Hosea 2. 18- 19).
    [Show full text]
  • Augustine and the Art of Ruling in the Carolingian Imperial Period
    Augustine and the Art of Ruling in the Carolingian Imperial Period This volume is an investigation of how Augustine was received in the Carolingian period, and the elements of his thought which had an impact on Carolingian ideas of ‘state’, rulership and ethics. It focuses on Alcuin of York and Hincmar of Rheims, authors and political advisers to Charlemagne and to Charles the Bald, respectively. It examines how they used Augustinian political thought and ethics, as manifested in the De civitate Dei, to give more weight to their advice. A comparative approach sheds light on the differences between Charlemagne’s reign and that of his grandson. It scrutinizes Alcuin’s and Hincmar’s discussions of empire, rulership and the moral conduct of political agents during which both drew on the De civitate Dei, although each came away with a different understanding. By means of a philological–historical approach, the book offers a deeper reading and treats the Latin texts as political discourses defined by content and language. Sophia Moesch is currently an SNSF-funded postdoctoral fellow at the University of Oxford, working on a project entitled ‘Developing Principles of Good Govern- ance: Latin and Greek Political Advice during the Carolingian and Macedonian Reforms’. She completed her PhD in History at King’s College London. Augustine and the Art of Ruling in the Carolingian Imperial Period Political Discourse in Alcuin of York and Hincmar of Rheims Sophia Moesch First published 2020 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN and by Routledge 52 Vanderbilt Avenue, New York, NY 10017 Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business Published with the support of the Swiss National Science Foundation.
    [Show full text]
  • Life with Augustine
    Life with Augustine ...a course in his spirit and guidance for daily living By Edmond A. Maher ii Life with Augustine © 2002 Augustinian Press Australia Sydney, Australia. Acknowledgements: The author wishes to acknowledge and thank the following people: ► the Augustinian Province of Our Mother of Good Counsel, Australia, for support- ing this project, with special mention of Pat Fahey osa, Kevin Burman osa, Pat Codd osa and Peter Jones osa ► Laurence Mooney osa for assistance in editing ► Michael Morahan osa for formatting this 2nd Edition ► John Coles, Peter Gagan, Dr. Frank McGrath fms (Brisbane CEO), Benet Fonck ofm, Peter Keogh sfo for sharing their vast experience in adult education ► John Rotelle osa, for granting us permission to use his English translation of Tarcisius van Bavel’s work Augustine (full bibliography within) and for his scholarly advice Megan Atkins for her formatting suggestions in the 1st Edition, that have carried over into this the 2nd ► those generous people who have completed the 1st Edition and suggested valuable improvements, especially Kath Neehouse and friends at Villanova College, Brisbane Foreword 1 Dear Participant Saint Augustine of Hippo is a figure in our history who has appealed to the curiosity and imagination of many generations. He is well known for being both sinner and saint, for being a bishop yet also a fellow pilgrim on the journey to God. One of the most popular and attractive persons across many centuries, his influence on the church has continued to our current day. He is also renowned for his influ- ence in philosophy and psychology and even (in an indirect way) art, music and architecture.
    [Show full text]
  • Iamblichus and Julian''s ''Third Demiurge'': a Proposition
    Iamblichus and Julian”s ”Third Demiurge”: A Proposition Adrien Lecerf To cite this version: Adrien Lecerf. Iamblichus and Julian”s ”Third Demiurge”: A Proposition . Eugene Afonasin; John M. Dillon; John F. Finamore. Iamblichus and the Foundations of Late Platonism, 13, BRILL, p. 177-201, 2012, Ancient Mediterranean and Medieval Texts and Contexts. Studies in Platonism, Neoplatonism, and the Platonic Tradition, 10.1163/9789004230118_012. hal-02931399 HAL Id: hal-02931399 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02931399 Submitted on 6 Sep 2020 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Iamblichus and Julian‟s “Third Demiurge”: A Proposition Adrien Lecerf Ecole Normale Supérieure, Paris, France [email protected] ABSTRACT. In the Emperor Julian's Oration To the Mother of the Gods, a philosophical interpretation of the myth of Cybele and Attis, reference is made to an enigmatic "third Demiurge". Contrary to a common opinion identifying him to the visible Helios (the Sun), or to tempting identifications to Amelius' and Theodorus of Asine's three Demiurges, I suggest that a better idea would be to compare Julian's text to Proclus' system of Demiurges (as exposed and explained in a Jan Opsomer article, "La démiurgie des jeunes dieux selon Proclus", Les Etudes Classiques, 71, 2003, pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Martyred for the Church
    Wissenschaftliche Untersuchungen zum Neuen Testament · 2. Reihe Herausgeber / Editor Jörg Frey (Zürich) Mitherausgeber/Associate Editors Markus Bockmuehl (Oxford) · James A. Kelhoffer (Uppsala) Tobias Nicklas (Regensburg) · J. Ross Wagner (Durham, NC) 471 Justin Buol Martyred for the Church Memorializations of the Effective Deaths of Bishop Martyrs in the Second Century CE Mohr Siebeck Justin Buol, born 1983; 2005 BA in Biblical and Theological Studies, Bethel University; 2007 MA in New Testament, Trinity Evangelical Divinity School; 2009 MA in Classical and Near Eastern Studies, University of Minnesota; 2017 PhD in Christianity and Judaism in Antiquity, University of Notre Dame; currently an adjunct professor at Bethel University. ISBN 978-3-16-156389-8 / eISBN 978-3-16-156390-4 DOI 10.1628/978-3-16-156390-4 ISSN 0340-9570 / eISSN 2568-7484 (Wissenschaftliche Untersuchungen zum Neuen Testament, 2. Reihe) The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliographie; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de. © 2018 Mohr Siebeck Tübingen, Germany. www.mohrsiebeck.com This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that permitted by copyright law) without the publisher’s written permission. This applies particularly to repro- ductions, translations and storage and processing in electronic systems. The book was printed by Laupp & Göbel in Gomaringen on non-aging paper and bound by Buchbinderei Nädele in Nehren. Printed in Germany. Preface This monograph represents a revised version of my doctoral dissertation. It has been updated to take into account additional scholarly literature, bring in new argumentation, and shorten some sections for relevance.
    [Show full text]
  • Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations Spring 2010 Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Jason Skirry University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Skirry, Jason, "Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection" (2010). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 179. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Abstract This dissertation presents a unified interpretation of Malebranche’s philosophical system that is based on his Augustinian theory of the mind’s perfection, which consists in maximizing the mind’s ability to successfully access, comprehend, and follow God’s Order through practices that purify and cognitively enhance the mind’s attention. I argue that the mind’s perfection figures centrally in Malebranche’s philosophy and is the main hub that connects and reconciles the three fundamental principles of his system, namely, his occasionalism, divine illumination, and freedom. To demonstrate this, I first present, in chapter one, Malebranche’s philosophy within the historical and intellectual context of his membership in the French Oratory, arguing that the Oratory’s particular brand of Augustinianism, initiated by Cardinal Bérulle and propagated by Oratorians such as Andre Martin, is at the core of his philosophy and informs his theory of perfection. Next, in chapter two, I explicate Augustine’s own theory of perfection in order to provide an outline, and a basis of comparison, for Malebranche’s own theory of perfection.
    [Show full text]
  • Numenius and the Hellenistic Sources of the Central Christian Doctrine
    ! Numenius and the Hellenistic Sources ! of the Central Christian Doctrine Marian Hillar Center for Philosophy and Socinian Studies Houston, TX 77004 Paper published in A Journal from the Radical Reformation. A testimony to Biblical Unitarianism. Vol. 14, No.! 1, Spring 2007, pp. 3-31. Quis obsecro, nisi penitus amens logomachias has sine risu toleraret? Nec in Thalmud, nec in Alchoran, sunt tam horrendae blasfemiae. Haec nos hactenus audire ita sumus alsuefacti, ut nihil miremur. Futurae vero generationes stupenda haec iudicabunt. Stupenda sunt vere, plusquam ea daemonum inventa, quae Valentinianis tribuit Irenaeus. I implore you, who in his sane mind could tolerate such logomachias without bursting into laughter? Not in the Talmud, nor in the Qu’ran can one find such horrendous blasphemies. But we are accustomed to hear them to the point that nothing astonishes us. Future generations will judge them obscure. Indeed, they are obscure, much more than the diabolic inventions which Irenaeus attributed to the Valentinians. ! Michael Servetus Christianismi Restitutio, De Trinitate, lib. I. p. 46. Si locum mihi aliquem ostendas, quo verbum illud filius olim vocetur, fatebor me victum. Christianismi Restitutio, If you show me a single passage in which the Son was called the Word, I will give up. Michael Servetus, Christianismi Restitutio, De Trinitate, lib. III p. 108. ! Abstract This paper attempts to explain the sources of the central Christian doctrine about the nature of deity. We can trace a continuous line of thought from the Greek philosophy to the development of the doctrine of the Trinity. The first Christian doctrine was developed by Justin Martyr (114-165 C.E.).
    [Show full text]
  • Jorge J. E. Gracia
    . Jorge J. E. Gracia PERSONAL INFORMATION Father: Dr. Ignacio J. L. de la C. Gracia Dubié Mother: Leonila M. Otero Muñoz Married to Norma E. Silva Casabé in 1966 Daughters: Leticia Isabel and Clarisa Raquel Grandchildren: James M. Griffin, Clarisa E. Griffin, Sofia G. Taberski, and Eva L. Taberski Office Addresses: Department of Philosophy, University at Buffalo 123 Park Hall, Buffalo, NY 14260-4150 Phone: (716) 645-2444; FAX (716) 645-6139 Department of Comparative Literature, University at Buffalo 631 Clemens Hall, Buffalo, NY 14260-4610 Phone: (716) 645-2066; FAX (716) 645-5979 Home Address: 420 Berryman Dr. Amherst, NY 14226 Phone: (716) 835-5747 EDUCATION High School Bachiller en Ciencias and Bachiller en Letras, with highest honors, St. Thomas Military Academy, La Habana, 1960 College/University B.A. in Philosophy, with honors, Wheaton College, 1965 M.A. in Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1966 M.S.L. in Philosophy, magna cum laude, Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, 1970 Ph.D. in Medieval Philosophy, University of Toronto, 1971 Other Studies One year of graduate study and research at the Institut d'Estudis Catalans, Barcelona, 1969-70 One year of study at the School of Architecture, Universidad de La Habana, 1960-61 One year of study at the Escuela de Artes Plásticas de San Alejandro, La Habana, 1960-61 Doctoral Dissertation "Francesc Eiximenis's Terç del Crestià: Edition and Study of Sources," Toronto, 1971, 576 pp. Dissertation Committee: J. Gulsoy, A. Maurer, E. Synan AREAS OF SPECIALIZATION IN PHILOSOPHY Systematic:
    [Show full text]
  • Divine Omnipotence in Descartes' Philosophy
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works All Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects Dissertations, Theses, and Capstone Projects 6-2014 Divine Omnipotence In Descartes' Philosophy Alfredo Rodriguez Graduate Center, City University of New York How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/gc_etds/274 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] DIVINE OMNIPOTENCE IN DESCARTES’ PHILOSOPHY BY ALFREDO RODRIGUEZ A master's thesis submitted to the Graduate Faculty in Liberal Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts, The City University of New York 2014 © 2014 Alfredo Rodriguez All Rights Reserved ii This manuscript has been read and accepted for the Graduate Faculty in Liberal Studies in satisfaction of the requirement for the degree of Master of Arts. Professor Douglas Lackey Date Thesis Adviser Professor Matthew K. Gold Date Executive Officer THE CITY UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK iii Abstract Divine Omnipotence in Descartes’ Philosophy by Alfredo Rodriguez Adviser: Professor Douglas Lackey The present thesis explores various aspects of Rene Descartes’ doctrine of divine omnipotence within the context of his overall philosophy and with reference to his medieval heritage. This thesis shows that, contrary to his multiple and explicit statements that God’s power cannot be limited in any way, Descartes took a more nuanced position on divine omnipotence that incorporated aspects of the widely accepted medieval position that God’s goodness is a constraint on his power.
    [Show full text]
  • Neoplatonic Asclepius: Science and Religion at the Crossroads of Aristotelian Biology, Hippocratic Medicine and Platonic Theurgy
    Studia Antiqua et Archaeologica 23(2): 333–349 Neoplatonic Asclepius: Science and religion at the crossroads of Aristotelian biology, Hippocratic medicine and Platonic theurgy Eugene AFONASIN1 Abstract. In the first part of the paper, I will briefly discuss certain peculiarities of the medical profession in antiquity. In his Philosophical History (fr. 80–84 Athanassiadi) Damascius narrates about a philosopher, named Asclepiodotus, whose interests ranged from Platonic philosophy to Aristotelian natural sciences. Asclepiodotus’ instructor in medical matters, a son of a doctor from the island of Rhodos, Iacobus, is pictured by Damascius as an exemplary figure (fr. 84), who, unlike many of his contemporaries, always tested the opinions of others and gained a reputation of an extremely successful physician, although the methods of treatment, ascribed to him by Damascius, are highly reminiscent of those presented as the Pythagorean by Iamblichus (On the Pythagorean way of life 244). In this respect both Iacobus and Asclepiodotus are conformed to the best standards of medical ethics, and pass the test set by Galen in his “On examination by which the best physicians are recognized”, except perhaps by the fact that they preferred to base their activities on such authorities as Aristotle and the Methodist Soranus rather than on a list of the “dogmatists” proposed by Galen. In the second part of the paper, dedicated to the cult of Asclepius in Late Antiquity, I will look at various kinds of evidence taken from the Neoplatonic philosophers. Having discussed first the principal philosophical interpretations of Asclepius found in Apuleius, Aelianus, Macrobius, Julian, Porphyry, Iamblichus, Proclus, Damascius, etc., we turn to Proclus’ attitude to Athena and Asclepius as reflected in Marinus’ Vita Procli and finally discuss the cult of Eshmun as found in Damascius.
    [Show full text]