Quantum Mechanics, by Bas C. Van Fraassen. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Quantum Mechanics, by Bas C. Van Fraassen. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991 Book Reviews 539 Quantum Mechanics, by Bas C. van Fraassen. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991. Pp. xvi +541. £50.00. Bas van Fraassen's Quantum Mechanics represents the culmination of years of work, by one of the leading philosophers of science, on the foundational issues of nonrelativistic quantum mechanics; as such, it should be expected to be a big, Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/102/407/539/953696 by guest on 29 September 2021 rich, and challenging book. Quantum Mechanics is all of these and more. The subtitle of the book is "An Empiricist View", and could not be more appropriate. When van Fraassen leaves off exposition and takes up interpretation and philo- sophical analysis, he does so with the exclusive goal of showing how a construc- tive empiricist should (and often more importantly, should not) deal with interpretive and ontological issues in quantum mechanics ("QM" hereafter). After describing Quantum Mechanics in general terms, I will briefly discuss van Fraassen's "modal interpretation" of QM, and his views on EPR correlations and so-called "identical particles." The book is organized into four main sections. The first lays out van Fraassen's views about (in)determinism, symmetries, and probability. The second section, "The Empirical Basis of Q. ntum Theory", is incongruously titled, because in it van Fraassen discusses only one type of experiment, out of the vast range of phe- nomena supporting QM: the EPR correlation experiments. This section describes phenomena that violate Bell's inequalities, and what kinds of probability models can and cannot be compatible with such violations; one major conclusion of this section is that non-classical logic and/or probability theory are not demanded by such phenomena, though the study of quantum logics is valuable in its own right. The third section, "Mathematical Foundations", gives an extremely abstract and rigorous presentation of the basic elements of quantum theory, and how they fit together to yield the models of QM; half of this section is devoted to the difficult issues of composite systems and measurement interactions, grist for the philo- sophical problems of measurement and non-locality. The fourth and largest sec- tion has the philosophical meat of the book: discussions of some prominent "interpretations" of QM, and extensive treatment of the issues of the EPR corre- lations and the puzzles of identical particles. It is here that van Fraassen gives his views, in detail, of how an empiricist should approach the alleged philosophical problems of QM. I have mentioned that van Fraassen's presentation of QM and its interpretive issues is both abstract and rigorous; this is one of the book's great strengths, but also perhaps its greatest liability. Van Fraassen chose to present QM in terms of his own notational conventions, and his notation is both idiosyncratic and diffi- cult to master. In reading Quantum Mechanics, readers familiar with quantum mechanics from typical university physics courses will be at no significant advan- tage over readers with no physics background at all. Instead, readers with sub- stantial background in logic, probability theory, and formal mathematics, will have an easier time reading the book in detail. This raises the question of what the appropriate audience is for this book. It is written in a way that presupposes no prior knowledge of quantum mechanics, and so is in principle accessible to 540 Book Reviews any philosophers who can master the notational formalism. But in practice, phi- losophers not already working on the philosophy of QM will find the difficulty of Quantum Mechanics too great for the payoff in understanding of foundational issues. This is especially so since, given its abstractness of approach and unusual notation, Quantum Mechanics does not leave one prepared to move on to most Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/102/407/539/953696 by guest on 29 September 2021 other works in the philosophy of QM. For the professional philosopher of phys- ics, van Fraassen's book on the one hand offers much: penetrating and lucid crit- icism of the "standard interpretation(s)" of QM, a revised and thorough presentation of van Fraassen's own modal interpretation, and a trenchantly anti- metaphysical analysis of the central philosophical issues. On the other hand, the book omits some topics that are of increasing interest in the profession, such as Bohm-type hidden variable theories and foundational issues in relativistic quan- tum mechanics. The first section of Quantum Mechanics largely repeats material from his ear- lier book Laws and Symmetry, but is worth reading carefully, even for readers familiar with Laws and Symmetry, because it begins to introduce much of the notation used throughout the book. A word about the relation between these books is in order. Laws and Symmetry was intended to advocate the semantic approach to the structure of theories, using the concept of symmetry as a partial replacement for the concept of law (while jettisoning the latter concept in its met- aphysical guises); and Quantum Mechanics was to illustrate the implementation of this approach, in a detailed way, in the interpretation of a central scientific the- ory. The two books do complement each other (and the earlier Scientific Image), but they have no trouble standing alone, and readers need not fear that they will need to read the earlier Laws and Symmetry in order to understand Quantum Mechanics. The interpretation that van Fraassen has developed over the last 20 years is the modal interpretation; it is a view that solves some of the puzzles of measurement, while introducing a curious kind of dualism into the description of nature. While van Fraassen claims to advocate the modal interpretation (specifically, the Copenhagen variant of it), it would be more accurate to say that he displays it. For in the end, van Fraassen makes no claim about the truth or probable truth of his interpretation. Instead, he describes his interpretation with clarity and preci- sion,- and says "here is one way that the world might be, if QM is true", and claims only the virtue of having increased our understanding of QM by giving us another consistent interpretation. Van Fraassen makes no claim that his interpretation is more likely to be true than the standard interpretation, or the Everitt interpreta- tion, ...; nor can he do so, given his own empiricism. The dualism introduced by the modal interpretation is a dualism of dynamic states of systems on the one hand, and the possession of values of observables by these systems (van Fraassen calls such possessions "events") on the other. Dynamic states are the traditional mixed and pure states in Hibert spaces of quan- tum mechanics; they evolve according to the Schrodinger equation in a determin- istic way, and undergo no "collapse of the wave packet" or "state-vector Book Reviews 541 reduction". But in addition to the dynamic state (and consistent with it), systems also often possess values of various observables, e.g., an electron may have spin up in a certain direction. Measurement interactions do not reveal anything new about dynamic states, but do reveal possessed values of the measured observ- ables. In times when no measurement is being performed, what values of observ- Downloaded from https://academic.oup.com/mind/article/102/407/539/953696 by guest on 29 September 2021 ables are actually possessed by a system is something that may change randomly, or chaotically, or not at all; QM tells us very little about this. What QM does do is tell us the probabilities for finding a given value for a measured observable, after a measurement; and no more. On this picture, QM is a complete description of one aspect of reality—dynamic states of systems—and a very incomplete description of another aspect, namely the actual values of observables possessed by systems. Van Fraassen describes the strange features of his modal interpreta- tion just as thoroughly as its more intuitive features; and even readers who come away from it with no feeling that it might be true cannot but agree with van Fraas- sen's claim that, by creating the modal interpretation, he has increased our under- standing of QM in an important way. The two most distinctive features of Quantum Mechanics, already seen above, are its anti-metaphysical approach to all issues, and its claim that engagement in the interpretive work in QM is valuable for the insights it can give into what the world may be like, if the theory is true. These features are also prominent in the discussions of the last three chapters, on the EPR correlations and on identical particles. On the issue of identical (or indistinguishable) particles, van Fraassen advocates resisting the metaphysical urge to explain the Bose-Einstein or Fermi- Dirac statistical behaviours of particles as arising from their non-existence or their "lack of identity". Instead, van Fraassen begins the work of carefully explor- ing the extent to which QM itself has the resources for individuating fundamental particles. He argues in the end that fermions can be individuated in the framework of QM, while bosons cannot; but this gives us no metaphysical truths about the existence or non-existence of fermions and bosons as individual entities. Both kinds of particles may lack individual identity, as field-theoretic models suggest; and both kinds may have identity, even bosons—though if the latter is to be the case, bosons must have properties outside the scope of QM that serve to individ- uate them without being empirically significant. On the issue of EPR correlations, van Fraassen argues, very simply, that the spooky "action at a distance" correlations do not need to be explained; they must simply be accepted.
Recommended publications
  • Denying a Dualism: Goodman's Repudiation of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 28, 2004, 226-238. Denying a Dualism: Goodman’s Repudiation of the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction Catherine Z. Elgin The analytic synthetic/distinction forms the backbone of much modern Western philosophy. It underwrites a conception of the relation of representations to reality which affords an understanding of cognition. Its repudiation thus requires a fundamental reconception and perhaps a radical revision of philosophy. Many philosophers believe that the repudiation of the analytic/synthetic distinction and kindred dualisms constitutes a major loss, possibly even an irrecoverable loss, for philosophy. Nelson Goodman thinks otherwise. He believes that it liberates philosophy from unwarranted restrictions, creating opportunities for the development of powerful new approaches to and reconceptions of seemingly intractable problems. In this article I want to sketch some of the consequences of Goodman’s reconception. My focus is not on Goodman’s reasons for denying the dualism, but on some of the ways its absence affects his position. I do not contend that the Goodman obsessed over the issue. I have no reason to think that the repudiation of the distinction was a central factor in his intellectual life. But by considering the function that the analytic/synthetic distinction has performed in traditional philosophy, and appreciating what is lost and gained in repudiating it, we gain insight into Goodman’s contributions. I begin then by reviewing the distinction and the conception of philosophy it supports. The analytic/synthetic distinction is a distinction between truths that depend entirely on meaning and truths that depend on both meaning and fact. In the early modern period, it was cast as a distinction between relations of ideas and matters of fact.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophical Logic 2018 Course Description (Tentative) January 15, 2018
    Philosophical Logic 2018 Course description (tentative) January 15, 2018 Valentin Goranko Introduction This 7.5 hp course is mainly intended for students in philosophy and is generally accessible to a broad audience with basic background on formal classical logic and general appreciation of philosophical aspects of logic. Practical information The course will be given in English. It will comprise 18 two-hour long sessions combining lectures and exercises, grouped in 2 sessions per week over 9 teaching weeks. The weekly pairs of 2-hour time slots (incl. short breaks) allocated for these sessions, will be on Mondays during 10.00-12.00 and 13.00-15.00, except for the first lecture. The course will begin on Wednesday, April 4, 2018 (Week 14) at 10.00 am in D220, S¨odra huset, hus D. Lecturer's info: Name: Valentin Goranko Email: [email protected] Homepage: http://www2.philosophy.su.se/goranko Course webpage: http://www2.philosophy.su.se/goranko/Courses2018/PhilLogic-2018.html Prerequisites The course will be accessible to a broad audience with introductory background on classical formal logic. Some basic knowledge of modal logics would be an advantage but not a prerequisite. Brief description Philosophical logic studies a variety of non-classical logical systems intended to formalise and reason about various philosophical concepts and ideas. They include a broad family of modal logics, as well as many- valued, intuitionistic, relevant, conditional, non-monotonic, para-consistent, etc. logics. Modal logics extend classical logic with additional intensional logical operators, reflecting different modes of truth, including alethic, epistemic, doxastic, temporal, deontic, agentive, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla
    DOCUMENT RESUME ED 086 604 SO 006 822 AUTHOR Norris, Jack A., Jr. TITLE Introduction to Philosophy. Social Studies--Language Arts: 6414.16. INSTITUTION Dade County Public Schools, Miami, Fla. PUB DATE 72 NOTE 20p.; Authorized Course of Instruction for the Quinmester Program EDRS PRICE MF-$0.65 HC-$3.29 DESCRIPTORS Course Objectives; Curriculum Guides; Grade 10; Grade 11; Grade 12; *Language Arts; Learnin4 Activities; *Logic; Non Western Civilization; *Philosophy; Resource Guides; Secondary Grades; *Social Studies; *Social Studies Units; Western Civilization IDENTIFIERS *Quinmester Program ABSTRACT Western and non - western philosophers and their ideas are introduced to 10th through 12th grade students in this general social studies Quinmester course designed to be used as a preparation for in-depth study of the various schools of philosophical thought. By acquainting students with the questions and categories of philosophy, a point of departure for further study is developed. Through suggested learning activities the meaning of philosopky is defined. The Socratic, deductive, inductive, intuitive and eclectic approaches to philosophical thought are examined, as are three general areas of philosophy, metaphysics, epistemology,and axiology. Logical reasoning is applied to major philosophical questions. This course is arranged, as are other quinmester courses, with sections on broad goals, course content, activities, and materials. A related document is ED 071 937.(KSM) FILMED FROM BEST AVAILABLE COPY U S DEPARTMENT EDUCATION OF HEALTH. NAT10N41
    [Show full text]
  • Curriculum Vitae
    BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN Curriculum Vitae Last updated 3/6/2019 I. Personal and Academic History .................................................................................................................... 1 List of Degrees Earned ........................................................................................................................................................ 1 Title of Ph.D. Thesis ........................................................................................................................................................... 1 Positions held ..................................................................................................................................................................... 1 Invited lectures and lecture series ........................................................................................................................................ 1 List of Honors, Prizes ......................................................................................................................................................... 4 Research Grants .................................................................................................................................................................. 4 Non-Academic Publications ................................................................................................................................................ 5 II. Professional Activities .................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Analytic-Synthetic Distinction and the Classical Model of Science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege
    Synthese (2010) 174:237–261 DOI 10.1007/s11229-008-9420-9 The analytic-synthetic distinction and the classical model of science: Kant, Bolzano and Frege Willem R. de Jong Received: 10 April 2007 / Revised: 24 July 2007 / Accepted: 1 April 2008 / Published online: 8 November 2008 © The Author(s) 2008. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract This paper concentrates on some aspects of the history of the analytic- synthetic distinction from Kant to Bolzano and Frege. This history evinces con- siderable continuity but also some important discontinuities. The analytic-synthetic distinction has to be seen in the first place in relation to a science, i.e. an ordered system of cognition. Looking especially to the place and role of logic it will be argued that Kant, Bolzano and Frege each developed the analytic-synthetic distinction within the same conception of scientific rationality, that is, within the Classical Model of Science: scientific knowledge as cognitio ex principiis. But as we will see, the way the distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments or propositions functions within this model turns out to differ considerably between them. Keywords Analytic-synthetic · Science · Logic · Kant · Bolzano · Frege 1 Introduction As is well known, the critical Kant is the first to apply the analytic-synthetic distinction to such things as judgments, sentences or propositions. For Kant this distinction is not only important in his repudiation of traditional, so-called dogmatic, metaphysics, but it is also crucial in his inquiry into (the possibility of) metaphysics as a rational science. Namely, this distinction should be “indispensable with regard to the critique of human understanding, and therefore deserves to be classical in it” (Kant 1783, p.
    [Show full text]
  • 2 Tracing the Development of Structural Realism
    1 2 TRACING THE DEVELOPMENT OF STRUCTURAL REALISM Ioannis Votsis 1. Introduction This chapter traces the development of structural realism within the scientific realism debate and the wider current of structuralism that has swept the philosophy of the natural sciences in the twentieth century. 1 The primary aim is to make perspicuous the many manifestations of structural realism and their underlying claims. Among other things, I will compare structural realism’s various manifestations in order to throw more light onto the relations between them. At the end of the chapter, I will identify the main objections raised against the epistemic form of structural realism. This last task will pave the way for the evaluation of the structural realist answer to the main epistemological question, an evaluation that will be central to the rest of this dissertation. Generally construed, structuralism is a point of view that emphasises the importance of relations. It takes the structure, i.e. the nexus of relations, of a given domain of interest to be the foremost goal of research and holds that an understanding of the subject matter has to be, and most successfully is, achieved in structural terms. The following quote from Redhead (2001a) nicely conveys this intuition: “Informally a structure is a system of related elements, and structuralism is a point of view which focuses attention on the relations between the elements as distinct from the elements themselves”(74). This vision has shaped research programmes in fields as diverse as mathematics, linguistics, literary criticism, aesthetics, anthropology, psychology, and philosophy of science. It is the last-mentioned that I am concerned with in this chapter.
    [Show full text]
  • Description Logics—Basics, Applications, and More
    Description Logics|Basics, Applications, and More Ian Horrocks Information Management Group University of Manchester, UK Ulrike Sattler Teaching and Research Area for Theoretical Computer Science RWTH Aachen, Germany RWTH Aachen 1 Germany Overview of the Tutorial • History and Basics: Syntax, Semantics, ABoxes, Tboxes, Inference Problems and their interrelationship, and Relationship with other (logical) formalisms • Applications of DLs: ER-diagrams with i.com demo, ontologies, etc. including system demonstration • Reasoning Procedures: simple tableaux and why they work • Reasoning Procedures II: more complex tableaux, non-standard inference prob- lems • Complexity issues • Implementing/Optimising DL systems RWTH Aachen 2 Germany Description Logics • family of logic-based knowledge representation formalisms well-suited for the representation of and reasoning about ➠ terminological knowledge ➠ configurations ➠ ontologies ➠ database schemata { schema design, evolution, and query optimisation { source integration in heterogeneous databases/data warehouses { conceptual modelling of multidimensional aggregation ➠ : : : • descendents of semantics networks, frame-based systems, and KL-ONE • aka terminological KR systems, concept languages, etc. RWTH Aachen 3 Germany Architecture of a Standard DL System Knowledge Base I N Terminology F E I R Father = Man u 9 has child.>... N E T Human = Mammal. u Biped . N E Description C R E F Logic A Concrete Situation S C Y E John:Human u Father S John has child Bill . T . E M RWTH Aachen 4 Germany Introduction
    [Show full text]
  • Models, Perspectives, and Scientific Realism
    MODELS, PERSPECTIVES, AND SCIENTIFIC REALISM: ON RONALD GIERE'S PERSPECTIVAL REALISM A thesis submitted to Kent State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts by Brian R. Huth May, 2014 Thesis written by Brian R. Huth B.A., Kent State University 2012 M.A., Kent State University 2014 Approved by Frank X. Ryan, Advisor Linda Williams, Chair, Department of Philosophy James L. Blank, Dean, College of Arts and Sciences ii TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS................................................................................................. iv INTRODUCTION............................................................................................................... 1 CHAPTER I. FROM THE RECEIVED VIEW TO THE MODEL-THEORETIC VIEW........................................................................................................... 7 Section 1.1.................................................................................................... 9 Section 1.2.................................................................................................... 16 II. RONALD GIERE'S CONSTRUCTIVISM AND PERSPECTIVAL REALISM.................................................................................................... 25 Section 2.1.................................................................................................... 25 Section 2.2.................................................................................................... 31 Section 2.3...................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • The Pragmatics of Explanation: Remarks on Van Fraassen's Theory of Why-Questions1
    The Pragmatics of explanation: Remarks on van Fraassen’s theory of why-questions1 A Pragmática da explicação: Comentários sobre a teoria das questões-por-quê de van Fraassen Renato Cesar Cani Universidade Federal do Paraná – UFPR/CAPES – Brasil [email protected] Abstract: In this article, my aim is to analyze Bas van Fraassen’s pragmatic solution to two of the traditional problems concerning scientific explanation, namely, rejection and asymmetry. According to his view, an explanation is an answer to some request for information. The emergence of a question, as well as the evaluation of the explanations adduced, depends on considerations about contextual factors. In addition, I will evaluate the pertinence of objections raised by Philip Kitcher and Wesley Salmon against van Fraassen’s account. I will argue that their charge is not sound, for it actually misunderstands the role played by context in van Fraassen’s account. Although Salmon’s and Kitcher’s realist commitments motivate the point made by them, I will hold that a pragmatic account of explanation does not commit one to an anti-realist approach to science. Keywords: Pragmatics of Explanation. Bas van Fraassen. Why-questions. Asymmetry. Realism. Resumo: Neste artigo, meu objetivo é analisar a solução pragmática oferecida por Bas van Fraassen a dois dos tradicionais problemas da explicação científica, quais sejam, o da rejeição e o da assimetria. Em sua visão, uma explicação é uma resposta a alguma demanda por informação. O surgimento de uma questão, bem como a avaliação das possíveis explicações, depende de fatores contextuais. Além disso, avaliarei a pertinência das objeções de Philip Kitcher e Wesley Salmon contra a concepção de van Fraassen.
    [Show full text]
  • Empiricism, Stances, and the Problem of Voluntarism
    Swarthmore College Works Philosophy Faculty Works Philosophy 1-1-2011 Empiricism, Stances, And The Problem Of Voluntarism Peter Baumann Swarthmore College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://works.swarthmore.edu/fac-philosophy Part of the Philosophy Commons Let us know how access to these works benefits ouy Recommended Citation Peter Baumann. (2011). "Empiricism, Stances, And The Problem Of Voluntarism". Synthese. Volume 178, Issue 1. 27-36. DOI: 10.1007/s11229-009-9519-7 https://works.swarthmore.edu/fac-philosophy/13 This work is brought to you for free by Swarthmore College Libraries' Works. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of Works. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Empiricism, Stances and the Problem of Voluntarism Peter Baumann Synthese 178, 2011, 207-224 Empiricism can be very roughly characterized as the view that our knowledge about the world is based on sensory experience. Our knowledge about the world is "based" on sensory experience in the sense that we could not know what we know without relying on sense experience. This leaves open the possibility that sense experience is only necessary but not sufficient for the knowledge based upon it1-as long as the non-empirical elements are not themselves sufficient for the relevant piece of knowledge.2 The basing relation is not just a genetic one but also a justificatory one: Sense experience does not only lead to beliefs which happen to count as knowledge but also qualifies them as knowledge. In his important book The Empirical Stance Bas van Fraassen characterizes traditional empiricism at one point in a more negative way-as involving the rejection of "metaphysical" explanations which proceed by postulating the existence of something not 1 "But although all our cognition commences with experience, yet it does not on that account all arise from experience." (Kant, CpR, B1).
    [Show full text]
  • Willard Van Orman Quine: the Analytic/Synthetic Distinction
    Willard Van Orman Quine: The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction Willard Van Orman Quine was one of the most well-known American “analytic” philosophers of the twentieth century. He made significant contributions to many areas of philosophy, including philosophy of language, logic, epistemology, philosophy of science, and philosophy of mind/psychology (behaviorism). However, he is best known for his rejection of the analytic/synthetic distinction. Technically, this is the distinction between statements true in virtue of the meanings of their terms (like “a bachelor is an unmarried man”) and statements whose truth is a function not simply of the meanings of terms, but of the way the world is (such as, “That bachelor is wearing a grey suit”). Although a contentious thesis, analyticity has been a popular explanation, especially among empiricists, both for the necessity of necessary truths and for the a priori knowability of some truths. Thus, in some contexts “analytic truth,” “necessary truth,” and “a priori truth” have been used interchangeably, and the analytic/synthetic distinction has been treated as equivalent to the distinctions between necessary and contingent truths, and between a priori and a posteriori (or empirical) truths. Empirical truths can be known only by empirical verification, rather than by “unpacking” the meanings of the terms involved, and are usually thought to be contingent. Quine wrestled with the analytic/synthetic distinction for years, but he did not make his thoughts public until 1950, when he delivered his paper, “The Two Dogmas of Empiricism” at a meeting of the American Philosophical Association. In this paper, Quine argues that all attempts to define and understand analyticity are circular.
    [Show full text]
  • A Fuzzy Description Logic
    From: AAAI-98 Proceedings. Copyright © 1998, AAAI (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. A Fuzzy Description Logic Umberto Straccia I.E.I - C.N.R. Via S. Maria, 46 I-56126 Pisa (PI) ITALY [email protected] Abstract is such a concept: we may say that an individual tom is an instance of the concept Tall only to a certain degree Description Logics (DLs, for short) allow reasoning n ∈ [0, 1] depending on tom’s height. about individuals and concepts, i.e. set of individuals with common properties. Typically, DLs are limited to Fuzzy logic directly deals with the notion of vague- dealing with crisp, well dened concepts. That is, con- ness and imprecision using fuzzy predicates. Therefore, cepts for which the problem whether an individual is it oers an appealing foundation for a generalisation of an instance of it is a yes/no question. More often than DLs in order to dealing with such vague concepts. not, the concepts encountered in the real world do not The aim of this work is to present a general fuzzy DL, have a precisely dened criteria of membership: we which combines fuzzy logic with DLs. In particular we may say that an individual is an instance of a concept will extend DLs by allowing expressions of the form only to a certain degree, depending on the individual’s hC(a) ni (n ∈ [0, 1]), e.g. hTall(tom) .7i, with intended properties. Concepts of this kind are rather vague than precise. As fuzzy logic directly deals with the notion of meaning “the membership degree of individual a being vagueness and imprecision, it oers an appealing foun- an instance of concept C is at least n”.
    [Show full text]