CAS LX 502 Semantics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

CAS LX 502 Semantics Meaning as truth conditions CAS LX 502 ! We know the meaning of p if we know the conditions under which p is true. Semantics ! conditions under which p is true = which are the possible worlds in which p holds ! possible worlds = ways things might be 2a. Reference, Compositionality, ! The meaning of p: A specification of Logic possible worlds. 2.1-2.3 Recall the trick we can do How do we arrive at truth conditions? ! Homer stands. ! Homer stands. Marge stands. ! True iff Homer stands. ! True iff Homer stands. ! True iff Marge stands. Two parts of Homer stands The Homer part and the stands part ! Homer stands. Marge stands. ! Homer stands. ! We use the name Homer to ! Homer stands. Bart’s father stands. refer to that guy. ! Homer stands is true when that guy has the property that he stands (being upright on his feet). ! Other things/people can stand, and we feel that standing should be basically the same regardless of who we say holds that property. 1 Unsaturated propositions Unsaturated propositions ! A proposition with a “hole” in it is ! A proposition with a “hole” in it is called an unsaturated proposition. called an unsaturated proposition. ! It’s something that, once we fill in the ! Thus: hole, will be true or false (of a given possible world). ! true ! false ! Portner draws these like so: ! true ! false Unsaturated propositions Meaning is compositional ! Although perhaps we could come up ! It seems that there is something common with a better picture, the idea is that: across all the propositions we might express using Homer. ! Homer stands: the possible worlds in which ! And something in common across all the Homer stands propositions we might express using stands. ! Homer stands. Homer snores. Marge stands. ! Stands: (unsaturated) Given a referent x, the possible worlds in which x stands. ! Given that each word seems to have a consistent contribution to the meaning, (to ! true some extent) regardless of the sentence in ! Homer: ! false which it appears… Meaning is compositional Meaning is compositional ! We hypothesize this: ! And it really has to be compositional. We after all know what the world has to look like in order for a sentence to be true, even if we ! Meaning is compositional haven’t heard the sentence before—and The meaning of a sentence is formed have to compute the meaning. from the meanings of its parts, and the way in which they are arranged. ! So the project here is really: ! Understand the pieces of meaning ! Understand how they combine to form larger units of ! Homer strangles Bart. Bart strangles Homer. meaning 2 Where are we so far? Unsaturated propositions ! In the set of things that we’ve been ! We’ve added the idea of an considering as part of meaning: unsaturated proposition, which would be a proposition, but for the lack of an ! Possible world: A state of affairs. individual. ! One special possible world is the actual world, ! Given an individual, it would be a set w . 0 of possible worlds. ! Individuals: Referents, like Homer. ! It’s “waiting for an individual.” ! Propositions: Sets of possible worlds ! It, in a sense, turns individuals into sets ! In which the proposition is “true.” of possible worlds. Limiting our attention to wk Semantic type ! For simplicity in presentation, let’s stop ! The entire semantics that we are creating thinking about sets of possible worlds briefly, here depends on two types of things, and limit out focus to specific possible individuals and truth values. worlds. ! We can label individuals as being of type “e” (traditional, think “entity”), and truth ! One good candidate would be w , but it 0 values as being of type “t”. doesn’t have to be that one necessarily. ! If we do this, we can consider a proposition ! In these terms, names like Homer are of type to be either true or false. <e>, and sentences like Homer stands are of ! Though in the back of our minds, we know that this is type <t>. in a particular possible world. A formal system Functions of semantic types ! <e> is a basic type. ! A function transforms one thing into another. ! <t> is a basic type. ! We can define the squaring function as a function that takes a number and gives ! If " and # are types, <",#> is a type. back that number multiplied with itself ! <",#> is a function that takes something of ! Square(n) = n $ n type " and returns something of type #. ! This is a function from numbers to numbers. It takes a number, it gives back a number. ! <e,t> is a type. <<e,t>,<e,<e,t>>> is a type. ! <e,t,e> is not, nor is <<e,t>>. 3 Functions <e,t> functions ! A function doesn’t need to give back the ! An intransitive verb like stands can be same kind of thing it gets. Usually, the thing it viewed as a function from individuals to truth gives back depends on the thing it gets, but values. Given an individual x, it will return it doesn’t need to be of the same type. true if x is boring, or false if x is not boring. ! Change-machine($n-bill) = 4 $ n quarters. ! Stands(x) = true if x stands; false otherwise. ! This is a function from bills to quarters. ! This is a function from individuals (type <e>) to truth values (type <t>). That is, it has type <e,t>. Enter the % % argument [ return value ] ! There is a way to write functions that we will get some ! Change-machine($n-bill) = 4 $ n quarters. experience with as the semester progresses, using ! Change-machine = % $n-bill [ 4 $ n quarters ] lambda notation. Here’s a first introduction ! The structure of a function written in lambda notation is: % argument [ return value ] ! Square = % n [ n $ n ] ! So, for the meaning of stands, we might write this: ! Not very complicated, just a short way to write “that function f such that, given ! % x [ x stands (in wk) ] argument, returns return value.” ! Type <e,t> value % argument [ return value ] value % argument [ return value ] ! Square = % n [ n $ n ] ! Strictly speaking, there’s an intermediate step, ! Square(3) = 3 $ 3 = 9 which is written like so: ! Square(4) = 4 $ 4 = 16. ! Square = % n [ n $ n ] ! Square(3) = 3 % n [ n $ n ] = 3 $ 3 = 9 ! To evaluate a function, we take the value ! Square(4) = 4 % n [ n $ n ] = 4 $ 4 = 16. and substitute it in for the argument within the return value. If we give it a 3, and the ! What value % argument [ return value ] means is: argument is n, then we replace all of the ns Replace every instance of argument within return with 3s and evaluate the return value. value with value, then evaluate return value. ! This operation goes by the name lambda conversion. 4 value % argument [ return value ] Desiderata for a theory of meaning ! One last piece of terminology: Instances of ! A is synonymous with B argument within return value are said to be ! A has the same meaning as B variables that bound by the lambda operator. ! A entails B ! If A holds then B automatically holds ! Triple = % n [ 3 $ n ] ! A contradicts B ! A is inconsistent with B ! A presupposes B ! B is part of the assumed background against which A is said. ! A is a tautology ! A is automatically true, regardless of the facts Lambda operator ! A is a contradiction Bound variable ! A is automatically false, regardless of the facts Intuitions about logic Truth out there in the world ! If it’s Thursday, ER will be on at 10. ! A statement like It’s Thursday is either true It’s Thursday. (corresponding to the facts of the world) or it is false ER will be on at 10. (not corresponding to the facts of the world). Modus Ponens ! Same for the statement ER is on at 10. ! It turns out that modus ponens is a valid form of ! Logic is essentially the study of valid argumentation argument, no matter what statements we use. Let’s and inferences. just say we have a statement—we’ll call it p. The ! If the premises are true, the conclusion will be true. statement (proposition) p can be either true or false. And another one, we’ll call it q. Modus ponens An invalid argument ! So, whatever p and q are: ! Incidentally, some things are not valid arguments. Modus ponens and modus ! If p then q. tollens are. This is not: p. q. ! If it is Thursday, then ER is on at 10. It is not Thursday ! Granting the premises If p then q and *ER is not on at 10. p, we can conclude q. 5 Other forms of valid argument Other forms of valid argument ! If it is Thursday, then ER is on. ! Pat is watching TV or Pat is asleep. If ER is on, Pat will watch TV. Pat is not asleep. If it is Thursday, the Pat will watch TV. Pat is watching TV. Hypothetical syllogism Disjunctive syllogism ! If p then q. ! p or q. If q then r. ¬q. If p then r. p. Logical syntax Logical connectives ! A proposition, say p, has a truth value. In light of the ! We can combine propositions with facts of the world, it is either true or false. The conditions under which p is true is are called its truth connectives like and, or. In logical conditions. notation, “p and q” is written with the logical connective & (“and”): p & q; “p ! We can also create complex expressions by or q” is written with ' (“or”): p ' q. combining propositions. For example, ¬q. That’s true whenever q is false.
Recommended publications
  • Leibniz and the Necessity of the Best Possible World
    This is a preprint of an article whose final and definitive form will be published in the Australasian Journal of Philosophy; the Australasian Journal of Philosophy is available online at: http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals/. LEIBNIZ AND THE NECESSITY OF THE BEST POSSIBLE WORLD Martin Pickup Leibniz has long faced a challenge about the coherence of the distinction between necessary and contingent truths in his philosophy. In this paper, I propose and examine a new way to save genuine contingency within a Leibnizian framework. I conclude that it succeeds in formally solving the problem, but at unbearable cost. I present Leibniz’s challenge by considering God’s choice of the best possible world (Sect. 2). God necessarily exists and necessarily chooses to actualise the best possible world. The actual world therefore could not be different, for if it were different it would be a distinct and inferior world and hence would not be created. In Sect. 3 I defend Leibniz from this challenge. I argue that while it is necessary for God to choose to create the best possible world, it is not necessary for any world to be the best possible. This is because the criterion for judging perfection can itself be contingent. Different criteria will judge different worlds as the best. Thus it is necessary for God to create the best, but not necessary which is the best. Distinguishing between possible worlds in Leibniz’s sense and in the modern sense allows a fuller exposition of this position. There are worries that can arise with the claim that the criterion of perfection is contingent.
    [Show full text]
  • 7.1 Rules of Implication I
    Natural Deduction is a method for deriving the conclusion of valid arguments expressed in the symbolism of propositional logic. The method consists of using sets of Rules of Inference (valid argument forms) to derive either a conclusion or a series of intermediate conclusions that link the premises of an argument with the stated conclusion. The First Four Rules of Inference: ◦ Modus Ponens (MP): p q p q ◦ Modus Tollens (MT): p q ~q ~p ◦ Pure Hypothetical Syllogism (HS): p q q r p r ◦ Disjunctive Syllogism (DS): p v q ~p q Common strategies for constructing a proof involving the first four rules: ◦ Always begin by attempting to find the conclusion in the premises. If the conclusion is not present in its entirely in the premises, look at the main operator of the conclusion. This will provide a clue as to how the conclusion should be derived. ◦ If the conclusion contains a letter that appears in the consequent of a conditional statement in the premises, consider obtaining that letter via modus ponens. ◦ If the conclusion contains a negated letter and that letter appears in the antecedent of a conditional statement in the premises, consider obtaining the negated letter via modus tollens. ◦ If the conclusion is a conditional statement, consider obtaining it via pure hypothetical syllogism. ◦ If the conclusion contains a letter that appears in a disjunctive statement in the premises, consider obtaining that letter via disjunctive syllogism. Four Additional Rules of Inference: ◦ Constructive Dilemma (CD): (p q) • (r s) p v r q v s ◦ Simplification (Simp): p • q p ◦ Conjunction (Conj): p q p • q ◦ Addition (Add): p p v q Common Misapplications Common strategies involving the additional rules of inference: ◦ If the conclusion contains a letter that appears in a conjunctive statement in the premises, consider obtaining that letter via simplification.
    [Show full text]
  • A General Framework for the Semantics of Type Theory
    A General Framework for the Semantics of Type Theory Taichi Uemura November 14, 2019 Abstract We propose an abstract notion of a type theory to unify the semantics of various type theories including Martin-L¨oftype theory, two-level type theory and cubical type theory. We establish basic results in the semantics of type theory: every type theory has a bi-initial model; every model of a type theory has its internal language; the category of theories over a type theory is bi-equivalent to a full sub-2-category of the 2-category of models of the type theory. 1 Introduction One of the key steps in the semantics of type theory and logic is to estab- lish a correspondence between theories and models. Every theory generates a model called its syntactic model, and every model has a theory called its internal language. Classical examples are: simply typed λ-calculi and cartesian closed categories (Lambek and Scott 1986); extensional Martin-L¨oftheories and locally cartesian closed categories (Seely 1984); first-order theories and hyperdoctrines (Seely 1983); higher-order theories and elementary toposes (Lambek and Scott 1986). Recently, homotopy type theory (The Univalent Foundations Program 2013) is expected to provide an internal language for what should be called \el- ementary (1; 1)-toposes". As a first step, Kapulkin and Szumio (2019) showed that there is an equivalence between dependent type theories with intensional identity types and finitely complete (1; 1)-categories. As there exist correspondences between theories and models for almost all arXiv:1904.04097v2 [math.CT] 13 Nov 2019 type theories and logics, it is natural to ask if one can define a general notion of a type theory or logic and establish correspondences between theories and models uniformly.
    [Show full text]
  • On Considering a Possible World As Actual
    ON CONSIDERING A POSSIBLE WORLD AS ACTUAL Robert Stalnaker “Hell is paved with primary intensions” English proverb1 1. Introduction In Naming and Necessity2, Saul Kripke presented some striking examples that convinced many philosophers that there are truths that are both necessary and a posteriori, and also truths that are both contingent and a priori. The classic examples of the former are identity statements containing proper names (Hesperus = Phosphorus) and statements about the nature of natural kinds (Gold has atomic number 79). Realistic examples of the second kind of statement are harder to come by - perhaps there are none - but once one sees the idea it is easy to construct artificial examples. The most famous example is based on Gareth Evans’s descriptive name “Julius.”3 “Julius” is, by stipulation, a proper name of the person (whoever he might be) who invented the zip. So the statement “Julius invented the zip” can be known a priori to be true, but since the description is used to fix the reference rather than to give the meaning , of the name, the fact that Julius invented the zip is a contingent fact. Someone other than Julius (the person we in fact named) might have invented the zip, and if some else had invented it instead, it would not have been true that Julius invented the zip. The divergence of the two distinctions was surprising, but the examples are simple and relatively transparent. Kripke’s exposition pointed the way to an abstract description of the phenomena that made it clear, on one level at least, what is going on.
    [Show full text]
  • Reasoning with Ambiguity
    Noname manuscript No. (will be inserted by the editor) Reasoning with Ambiguity Christian Wurm the date of receipt and acceptance should be inserted later Abstract We treat the problem of reasoning with ambiguous propositions. Even though ambiguity is obviously problematic for reasoning, it is no less ob- vious that ambiguous propositions entail other propositions (both ambiguous and unambiguous), and are entailed by other propositions. This article gives a formal analysis of the underlying mechanisms, both from an algebraic and a logical point of view. The main result can be summarized as follows: sound (and complete) reasoning with ambiguity requires a distinction between equivalence on the one and congruence on the other side: the fact that α entails β does not imply β can be substituted for α in all contexts preserving truth. With- out this distinction, we will always run into paradoxical results. We present the (cut-free) sequent calculus ALcf , which we conjecture implements sound and complete propositional reasoning with ambiguity, and provide it with a language-theoretic semantics, where letters represent unambiguous meanings and concatenation represents ambiguity. Keywords Ambiguity, reasoning, proof theory, algebra, Computational Linguistics Acknowledgements Thanks to Timm Lichte, Roland Eibers, Roussanka Loukanova and Gerhard Schurz for helpful discussions; also I want to thank two anonymous reviewers for their many excellent remarks! 1 Introduction This article gives an extensive treatment of reasoning with ambiguity, more precisely with ambiguous propositions. We approach the problem from an Universit¨atD¨usseldorf,Germany Universit¨atsstr.1 40225 D¨usseldorf Germany E-mail: [email protected] 2 Christian Wurm algebraic and a logical perspective and show some interesting surprising results on both ends, which lead up to some interesting philosophical questions, which we address in a preliminary fashion.
    [Show full text]
  • A Computer-Verified Monadic Functional Implementation of the Integral
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Theoretical Computer Science 411 (2010) 3386–3402 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Theoretical Computer Science journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/tcs A computer-verified monadic functional implementation of the integral Russell O'Connor, Bas Spitters ∗ Radboud University Nijmegen, Netherlands article info a b s t r a c t Article history: We provide a computer-verified exact monadic functional implementation of the Riemann Received 10 September 2008 integral in type theory. Together with previous work by O'Connor, this may be seen as Received in revised form 13 January 2010 the beginning of the realization of Bishop's vision to use constructive mathematics as a Accepted 23 May 2010 programming language for exact analysis. Communicated by G.D. Plotkin ' 2010 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: Type theory Functional programming Exact real analysis Monads 1. Introduction Integration is one of the fundamental techniques in numerical computation. However, its implementation using floating- point numbers requires continuous effort on the part of the user in order to ensure that the results are correct. This burden can be shifted away from the end-user by providing a library of exact analysis in which the computer handles the error estimates. For high assurance we use computer-verified proofs that the implementation is actually correct; see [21] for an overview. It has long been suggested that, by using constructive mathematics, exact analysis and provable correctness can be unified [7,8]. Constructive mathematics provides a high-level framework for specifying computations (Section 2.1).
    [Show full text]
  • The Parallel Architecture and Its Place in Cognitive Science
    978–0–19–954400–4 Heine-main-drv Heine-Narrog (Typeset by Spi, Chennai) 645 of 778 April 8, 2009 21:55 chapter 23 .............................................................................................................. THE PARALLEL ARCHITECTURE AND ITS PLACE IN COGNITIVE SCIENCE .............................................................................................................. ray jackendoff It has become fashionable recently to speak of linguistic inquiry as biolinguistics, an attempt to frame questions of linguistic theory in terms of the place of lan- guage in a biological context. The Minimalist Program (Chomsky 1995; 2001)is of course the most prominent stream of research in this paradigm. However, an alternative stream within the paradigm, the Parallel Architecture, has been devel- oping in my own work over the past 30 years; it includes two important sub- components, Conceptual Structure and Simpler Syntax (Jackendoff2002; 2007b; Culicover and Jackendoff 2005). This chapter will show how the Parallel Architec- ture is in many ways a more promising realization of biolinguistic goals than the Minimalist Program and that, more than the Minimalist Program, it is conducive to integration with both the rest of linguistic theory and the rest of cognitive science. 978–0–19–954400–4 Heine-main-drv Heine-Narrog (Typeset by Spi, Chennai) 646 of 778 April 8, 2009 21:55 646 ray jackendoff 23.1 Parallel architectures, broadly conceived .........................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Saving the Square of Opposition∗
    HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC, 2021 https://doi.org/10.1080/01445340.2020.1865782 Saving the Square of Opposition∗ PIETER A. M. SEUREN Max Planck Institute for Psycholinguistics, Nijmegen, the Netherlands Received 19 April 2020 Accepted 15 December 2020 Contrary to received opinion, the Aristotelian Square of Opposition (square) is logically sound, differing from standard modern predicate logic (SMPL) only in that it restricts the universe U of cognitively constructible situations by banning null predicates, making it less unnatural than SMPL. U-restriction strengthens the logic without making it unsound. It also invites a cognitive approach to logic. Humans are endowed with a cogni- tive predicate logic (CPL), which checks the process of cognitive modelling (world construal) for consistency. The square is considered a first approximation to CPL, with a cognitive set-theoretic semantics. Not being cognitively real, the null set Ø is eliminated from the semantics of CPL. Still rudimentary in Aristotle’s On Interpretation (Int), the square was implicitly completed in his Prior Analytics (PrAn), thereby introducing U-restriction. Abelard’s reconstruction of the logic of Int is logically and historically correct; the loca (Leak- ing O-Corner Analysis) interpretation of the square, defended by some modern logicians, is logically faulty and historically untenable. Generally, U-restriction, not redefining the universal quantifier, as in Abelard and loca, is the correct path to a reconstruction of CPL. Valuation Space modelling is used to compute
    [Show full text]
  • Edinburgh Research Explorer
    Edinburgh Research Explorer Propositions as Types Citation for published version: Wadler, P 2015, 'Propositions as Types', Communications of the ACM, vol. 58, no. 12, pp. 75-84. https://doi.org/10.1145/2699407 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1145/2699407 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Peer reviewed version Published In: Communications of the ACM General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact [email protected] providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 28. Sep. 2021 Propositions as Types ∗ Philip Wadler University of Edinburgh [email protected] 1. Introduction cluding Agda, Automath, Coq, Epigram, F#,F?, Haskell, LF, ML, Powerful insights arise from linking two fields of study previously NuPRL, Scala, Singularity, and Trellys. thought separate. Examples include Descartes’s coordinates, which Propositions as Types is a notion with mystery. Why should it links geometry to algebra, Planck’s Quantum Theory, which links be the case that intuitionistic natural deduction, as developed by particles to waves, and Shannon’s Information Theory, which links Gentzen in the 1930s, and simply-typed lambda calculus, as devel- thermodynamics to communication.
    [Show full text]
  • Frege's Theory of Sense
    Frege’s theory of sense Jeff Speaks August 25, 2011 1. Three arguments that there must be more to meaning than reference ............................1 1.1. Frege’s puzzle about identity sentences 1.2. Understanding and knowledge of reference 1.3. Opaque contexts 2. The theoretical roles of senses .........................................................................................4 2.1. Frege’s criterion for distinctness of sense 2.2. Sense determines reference, but not the reverse 2.3. Indirect reference 2.4. Sense, force, and the theory of speech acts 3. What are senses? .............................................................................................................6 We have now seen how a theory of reference — a theory that assigns to each expression of the language a reference, which is what it contributes to determining the truth or falsity of sentences in which it occurs — might look for a fragment of English. (The fragment of English includes proper names, n-place predicates, and quantifiers.) We now turn to Frege’s reasons for thinking that a theory of reference must be supplemented with a theory of sense. 1. THREE ARGUMENTS THAT THERE MUST BE MORE TO MEANING THAN REFERENCE 1.1. Frege’s puzzle about identity sentences As Frege says at the outset of “On sense and reference,” identity “gives rise to challenging questions which are not altogether easy to answer.” The puzzle raised by identity sentences is that, if, even though “the morning star” and “the evening star” have the same reference — the planet Venus — the sentences [1] The morning star is the morning star. [2] The morning star is the evening star. seem quite different. They seem, as Frege says, to differ in “cognitive value.” [1] is trivial and a priori; whereas [2] seems a posteriori, and could express a valuable extension of knowledge — it, unlike [1], seems to express an astronomical discovery which took substantial empirical work to make.
    [Show full text]
  • A Multi-Modal Analysis of Anaphora and Ellipsis
    University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics Volume 5 Issue 2 Current Work in Linguistics Article 2 1998 A Multi-Modal Analysis of Anaphora and Ellipsis Gerhard Jaeger Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl Recommended Citation Jaeger, Gerhard (1998) "A Multi-Modal Analysis of Anaphora and Ellipsis," University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics: Vol. 5 : Iss. 2 , Article 2. Available at: https://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl/vol5/iss2/2 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl/vol5/iss2/2 For more information, please contact [email protected]. A Multi-Modal Analysis of Anaphora and Ellipsis This working paper is available in University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics: https://repository.upenn.edu/pwpl/vol5/iss2/2 A Multi-Modal Analysis of Anaphora and Ellipsis Gerhard J¨ager 1. Introduction The aim of the present paper is to outline a unified account of anaphora and ellipsis phenomena within the framework of Type Logical Categorial Gram- mar.1 There is at least one conceptual and one empirical reason to pursue such a goal. Firstly, both phenomena are characterized by the fact that they re-use semantic resources that are also used elsewhere. This issue is discussed in detail in section 2. Secondly, they show a striking similarity in displaying the characteristic ambiguity between strict and sloppy readings. This supports the assumption that in fact the same mechanisms are at work in both cases. (1) a. John washed his car, and Bill did, too. b. John washed his car, and Bill waxed it.
    [Show full text]
  • Traditional Logic II Text (2Nd Ed
    Table of Contents A Note to the Teacher ............................................................................................... v Further Study of Simple Syllogisms Chapter 1: Figure in Syllogisms ............................................................................................... 1 Chapter 2: Mood in Syllogisms ................................................................................................. 5 Chapter 3: Reducing Syllogisms to the First Figure ............................................................... 11 Chapter 4: Indirect Reduction of Syllogisms .......................................................................... 19 Arguments in Ordinary Language Chapter 5: Translating Ordinary Sentences into Logical Statements ..................................... 25 Chapter 6: Enthymemes ......................................................................................................... 33 Hypothetical Syllogisms Chapter 7: Conditional Syllogisms ......................................................................................... 39 Chapter 8: Disjunctive Syllogisms ......................................................................................... 49 Chapter 9: Conjunctive Syllogisms ......................................................................................... 57 Complex Syllogisms Chapter 10: Polysyllogisms & Aristotelian Sorites .................................................................. 63 Chapter 11: Goclenian & Conditional Sorites ........................................................................
    [Show full text]