Socratic Method and Moral Motivation

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Socratic Method and Moral Motivation SOCRATIC METHOD AND MORAL MOTIVATION by Jacob Duane Stump A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © 2017 by Jacob Duane Stump Abstract SOCRATIC METHOD AND MORAL MOTIVATION Jacob Duane Stump Doctor of Philosophy Graduate Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2017 I argue for a new account of the role of philosophical argument in changing a person’s core values. As philosophers, we tend to think it is possible to cause someone to change his values by directing some piece of reasoning at him. But that is often naïve, as can be seen by the trajectory of many political disputes: one side takes an argument to be persuasive, and the other refuses to accept it. As it happens, this is the exact progression of many Platonic dialogues. Socrates argues that his interlocutor’s core values are mistaken, and his interlocutor, despite being unable to identify where, if anywhere, the argument goes astray, rejects its conclusion. Is, then, argument out of work when it comes to changing a person’s core values? Many scholars, including Martha Nussbaum, Gregory Vlastos, and Alexander Nehamas, hold that Plato believes as much. On the standard view, Plato thinks that philosophical argument is an ineffective way of reforming a person’s life, and he rejects Socrates’ project, as outlined in the Apology, of using philosophical argument to persuade his interlocutors to value wisdom more than money, honor, and everything else. ii Against this standard view, I argue that Plato offers a compelling account of how philosophical argument can be effective at transforming a person’s values. As has not been appreciated by other scholars, Socrates uses his methods of refutation and exhortation in most cases not to advocate wisdom’s overriding importance, but rather to motivate pursuing wisdom merely for its instrumental value, and this because it is the instrumental pursuit of wisdom that is meant to be transformative. Socrates’ overall strategy, then, is not unlike that of the professor who recruits a student to philosophy with the promise that it will improve her LSAT scores, all the while anticipating that, once the student experiences the thrill of abstract, intellectual inquiry, she will lose her legal ambitions and devote herself to philosophical studies. What justifies this strategy, in our eyes and Plato’s, is that, in some important contexts, including the choice of a way of life, the right reasons can come into view only after taking up some practice, and so the practice cannot be motivated by the right reasons until it is taken up on some other basis. iii Acknowledgements Many people have supported me, both personally and academically, and I am pleased to be able to thank them here. I am thankful to my parents, Kris and Connie, for their unfailing love and encouragement, and this even when, at 18, I decided to move to the other side of the world, knowing no one, with little more than a sketch of a plan. I am thankful to those who improved my ability to think: to Amanda, for believing in words; to Tobi, for contesting my beliefs; to Maxwell, for introducing me to film; to Mark, to whom this thesis is dedicated, for teaching me how to converse philosophically, for inspiring me still by his curiosity and courage; to Imogen, Jessica, and Phil, for improving my writing; to Jennifer, for her relentlessness and trust; and to my thesis committee—to Rachel above all, for more things than I can list, for always expecting better, for her confidence and generosity, for the line ‘the heart that has tired of Toronto has tired of the world,’ for modeling the practice of philosophy as good citizenry, for, more than anything, teaching me how to think and write about Plato; to Brad, for his morale-boosting and keen eye for detail; to James, for his wit and insights into fundamental concepts; to Tom, for his joviality, pressuring me to make precise my foggy thoughts, and thoughtful engagement with my project. I also want to thank here Sean Kelsey, my external examiner, for identifying spots in the thesis that needed clarifying; and Frisbee Sheffield, for her encouragement to think better about erōs. I am thankful to my friends: to David, Michael, Brett, Casey, and Jonathan, for always being there; to Seth, Josh, Adam, Royce, Michael R. and Michael P., for their joie de vivre and pursuit of excellence; to Larkin, Robbie, Willie, Sukaina, Daniel, and Valerie, for their camaraderie and goodness; to Irene and Laura, for their insights; to Erin, for seeing things in me that I couldn’t see in myself, for the happiest and prettiest times; and to Mingus and the members of SQWISH, for their examples of kindness and empathy. Many more are left unnamed here: my thanks are also to you. iv I am thankful to my sister, Ashley, for her cheerfulness, enthusiasm for life, and friendship. Many adventures await. I am thankful to my extended family: to Bill, for his resolve and love of music; to Joyce, for her mischievousness and aphorisms; to Richard, for his encouragement from a young age to take seriously and pursue a life of learning; to Shelda, for her kindheartedness and handwritten letters; to Ken, Stephanie, Mike, Ronda, Kevin, Peggy, Kim, Chance, Luke, Dannie, Geoff, Cathy, Austin, Garrett, Ethan, and Ava, for all the good times. Finally, I am thankful to the benefactors of the Connaught International Scholarship and Robinson Graduate Fellowship in Ancient Philosophy, for their generous financial support and belief in the value of learning and research. v Contents Abbreviations vii Introduction 1 1. Socrates’ Project of Conversion 22 1.1 Uses of epimeleisthai 25 1.1.1 Taking care 25 1.1.2 Taking an interest 26 1.1.3 Valuing 28 1.1.4 Complex unity 28 1.1.5 Complications 34 1.2 Epimeleisthai in the Apology 35 1.2.1 Radical change 38 1.2.2 Lasting change 42 1.3 Life of philosophy 46 2. Socratic Refutation 52 2.1 Background 53 2.1.1 Ignorance and motivation 55 2.2 Template of refutation in the Apology 58 2.2.1 Ephebic oath 61 2.2.2 Initial advantages 63 2.3 Role-based epistemic duties 67 2.3.1 Apology 67 2.3.2 Euthyphro 69 2.3.3 Charmides 70 2.3.4 Hippias Major 71 2.3.5 Laches 72 2.3.6 Protagoras 73 2.3.7 Hippias Minor 75 2.3.8 Euthydemus 76 2.3.9 Gorgias 76 2.4 Motivational benefit of negative emotions 80 2.4.1 Shame and anger 80 2.4.2 A finely-tuned method 84 vi 3. Erotic Psychology 86 3.1 Erōs as obstacle 87 3.1.1 Inherited notion of erōs 89 3.1.2 Plato’s use of erōs 91 3.1.3 philo-x and erōs 94 3.2 Formal object of erōs 98 3.2.1 Symposium 204d-205d 101 3.2.2 Ruling desires, episodic erōs, and desire for the good 106 3.2.3 Cognitive desire 112 4. Motivated Reasoning 114 4.1 Ruling desires at large 116 4.2 Lovers follow beloveds 118 4.3 Ruling desires and intransigence 120 4.3.1 Callicles 120 4.3.2 Polus 123 4.3.3 Thrasymachus 127 4.3.4 Special cases 129 4.4 Erōs-driven reasoning 130 4.5 Ruling desires and bodyguard beliefs 136 4.5.1 Tyrant 137 4.5.2 Democrat 138 4.6 Complementary pictures 141 4.6.1 Is erōs-driven reasoning defensible? 142 4.7 Direct vs. indirect approaches 145 5. Socratic Exhortation 147 5.1 A “crisis” for Socratic method? 151 5.2 The prototype of Socratic exhortation: Euthydemus 278d-282d 154 5.3 Socrates’ exhortation of Alcibiades 155 5.3.1 Apotreptic of Alcibiades 157 5.3.2 Protreptic of Alcibiades 161 5.4 Socratic exhortation in the Lysis 163 5.4.1 Apotreptic of Hippothales 165 5.4.2 Exhortation of Lysis 167 5.4.3 Apotreptic of Lysis 167 5.4.4 Protreptic of Lysis 169 5.4.5 Protreptic of Hippothales 170 vii 5.5 Socrates’ exhortation of Phaedrus 173 5.5.1 Apotreptic of Phaedrus 176 5.5.2 Protreptic of Phaedrus 177 5.5.3 Socrates’ prayer revisited 179 5.5.4 Complete success? 181 5.6 Again, a finely-tuned method 183 6. Transformative Philosophy 185 6.1 Setup 185 6.2 Content as catalyst 189 6.2.1 Resistance 192 6.2.2 Repetition 194 6.3 Pleasure as catalyst 198 6.3.1 Pleasure of philosophy 200 6.3.2 Widely applicable 205 6.3.3 A complication 206 6.4 Conclusion 207 Bibliography 209 viii Abbreviations Alc. Alcibiades Ap. Apology Chrm. Charmides Cr. Crito Euthd. Euthydemus Eu. Euthyphro G. Gorgias Hi.Ma. Hippias Major Hi.Mi. Hippias Minor Ion Ion La. Laches Ly. Lysis M. Meno Phd. Phaedo Phdr. Phaedrus Phil. Philebus Prt. Protagoras Rep. Republic Smp. Symposium Tht. Theaetetus Thg. Theages ix Introduction What if someone has not been properly brought up?... [It is a] massively implausible implication that someone who has not been properly brought up— someone who has slipped through the net, so to speak—can be induced into seeing things straight by directing some piece of reasoning at him. On the contrary, reasoning aimed at generating new motivations will surely stand a chance of working only if it appeals to something in the audience’s existing motivational make-up… and the trouble with someone who has in some radical way slipped through the net is that there may be no such point of leverage for reasoning aimed at generating the motivations that are characteristic of someone who has been properly brought up.
Recommended publications
  • Socratic Dialogue: Teaching Patients to Become Their Own Cognitive Therapist
    National Crime Victims Center > Socratic Method > Socratic Dialogue Print This Page Socratic Dialogue: Teaching Patients to Become Their Own Cognitive Therapist “The unexamined life is not worth living.” Socrates (469 BC – 399 BC) Socratic dialogue is a foundational skill used by CPT therapists to help patients examine their lives, challenge maladaptive thoughts, address stuckpoints, and develop critical thinking skills. Socratic dialogue is derived from the work of the Greek philosopher, Socrates, who developed what is now called the Socratic method of teaching. In traditional education, the teacher is presumed to know more than the student, and the role of the teacher is to transmit the teacher’s knowledge to the student. In contrast, Socrates believed that the role of the teacher should not be to tell students what the “truth” is but to help them discover the truth themselves through a collaborative process of asking questions. By asking a series of questions designed to get the student to identify logical contradictions in their positions and/or evidence that does not support their thoughts, the Socratic method is designed to help the student discover the “truth” for themselves as opposed to being told what the “truth” is by the teacher. Socrates also thought this teaching method was superior because it teaches students the skill of critical thinking, a skill they can use throughout their lives. Another advantage of this method is that students are more likely to value knowledge if they discover it themselves than if someone tells them about it. In CPT, the purpose of Socratic questioning by the therapist is to prompt the patient to examine the accuracy of maladaptive thoughts that are causing psychological distress.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Euthydemus
    PLATO’S EUTHYDEMUS: A STUDY ON THE RELATIONS BETWEEN LOGIC AND EDUCATION Plato’s Euthydemus is an unlucky dialogue. Few dealt with it in its own right, not just as part of a wider discussion of Plato, and fewer still saw in it more than a topic of sophistic fallacies. Some, of course, paid attention to the constructive sections of the dialogue, but only rarely do we come across a real attempt to unify its different aspects.1 In this paper I propose to show how, in the Euthydemus, Plato tries to distinguish between the Socratic and the Sophistic conceptions of education, by tracing them to their roots in the opposing views of the Sophists — and especially those of the second generation — and of Socrates about truth and about the role of logic. And although the eristic techniques of Euthydemus and Dionysodorus are obviously fallacious, they turn out to be developments of Protagoras’ views and follow from philosophical positions worthy of serious examination. The Euthydemus is a caricature, to be sure. But, as all good caricature, it has a serious intent. It sketches the degeneration of the Sophistic approach to education, in some of its aspects. More important­ ly, it distinguishes Socratic education from the methods and effects of its Sophistic counterpart. Euthydemus and Dionysodorus, the two sophist brothers, are reminis­ cent of the great Sophists of the Protagoras in more than one way. They are polymaths like Hippias, and at one time or another have taught a variety of arts, from forensic rhetoric to armed combat. Also, they have Prodicus’ penchant for linguistic analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Induction in the Socratic Tradition John P
    Induction in the Socratic Tradition John P. McCaskey Stanford University Abstract: Aristotle said that induction (epagǀgƝ) is a proceeding from particulars to a universal, and the definition has been conventional ever since. But there is an ambiguity here. Induction in the Scholastic and the (so-called) Humean tradition has presumed that Aristotle meant going from particular statements to universal statements. But the alternate view, namely that Aristotle meant going from particular things to universal ideas, prevailed all through antiquity and then again from the time of Francis Bacon until the mid-nineteenth century. Recent scholarship is so steeped in the first-mentioned tradition that we have virtually forgotten the other. In this essay McCaskey seeks to recover that alternate tradition, a tradition whose leading theoreticians were William Whewell, Francis Bacon, Socrates, and in fact Aristotle himself. The examination is both historical and philosophical. The first part of the essay fills out the history. The latter part examines the most mature of the philosophies in the Socratic tradition, specifically Bacon’s and Whewell’s. After tracing out this tradition, McCaskey shows how this alternate view of induction is indeed employed in science, as exemplified by several instances taken from actual scientific practice. In this manner, McCaskey proposes to us that the Humean problem of induction is merely an artifact of a bad conception of induction and that a return to the Socratic conception might be warranted. Introduction Aristotle said that induction (epagǀgƝ) is a proceeding from particulars to a universal, and the definition has been conventional ever since. But there is an ambiguity here.
    [Show full text]
  • Applying the Socratic Method to the Problem Solving Process
    American Journal of Business Education – August 2009 Volume 2, Number 5 Socratic Problem-Solving In The Business World Evan Peterson, University Of Detroit Mercy, USA ABSTRACT Accurate and effective decision-making is one of the most essential skills necessary for organizational success. The problem-solving process provides a systematic means of effectively recognizing, analyzing, and solving a dilemma. The key element in this process is critical analysis of the situation, which can be executed by a taking a Socratic approach to the situation. Applying the Socratic Method to the problem-solving model ensures a well-rounded and versatile analysis. Keywords: Problem-solving process, decision- making, critical analysis, Socratic Method INTRODUCTION he sheer complexity of today’s business organization is rivaled only by the complexity of the business environment in which it operates. The permutation of complexity and exacting time constraints companies and individuals face in making vital decisions involving thousands of people Tand millions of dollars can seem more daunting than storming the beaches of Normandy. However, all hope is not lost. The anxiety, along with the blood, sweat, and tears that come along with difficult decision-making can be reduced by having a clear, time-tested plan of attack that can be applied to the problem situation. The problem-solving model is one such plan of attack, for it provides a framework that an individual decision-maker or group of decision-makers can follow to reach a feasible solution to the problem. Situational analysis is the bread and butter of the problem-solving model, for it goes hand-in-hand with each step of the model.
    [Show full text]
  • THE SOCRATIC METHOD AS an APPROACH in TEACHING SOCIAL STUDIES: a LITERATURE REVIEW Mary Grace Ann S
    GSJ: Volume 8, Issue 12, December 2020 ISSN 2320-9186 770 GSJ: Volume 8, Issue 12, December 2020, Online: ISSN 2320-9186 www.globalscientificjournal.com THE SOCRATIC METHOD AS AN APPROACH IN TEACHING SOCIAL STUDIES: A LITERATURE REVIEW Mary Grace Ann S. Maigue Senior High School Teacher, Our Lady of Peace School Antipolo City, Rizal, Philippines [email protected] ABSTRACT Enhancing the critical thinking skills of students is one of the principal goals of many educational institutions. This paper presents various articles discussing the general features of the Socratic Method in improving the critical thinking skills of students. Specifically, this study focuses on the importance of incorporating Socratic questioning in teaching Social Studies. The primary resources of this paper were taken from international journals. Related studies reveal that when teachers use Socratic questioning, students examine and probe their thoughts by making them explicit thus allowing them to develop and evaluate their thinking while overtly expressing their ideas. This in turn, is the paramount objective targeted by the Socratic Method, a student with an enriched critical mind. Keywords: Critical Thinking, Socratic Method of Teaching, Social Studies GSJ© 2020 www.globalscientificjournal.com GSJ: Volume 8, Issue 12, December 2020 ISSN 2320-9186 771 INTRODUCTION Critical thinking as the primary cognitive skill is one of the targeted areas that education is prompted to nourish. With this skill, we are able to process information given to us with the aid of our senses and to think profoundly such information. Poor critical thinking necessitates risks such as weak decision-making, repeated mistakes, inappropriate assumptions, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • The Stoics and the Practical: a Roman Reply to Aristotle
    DePaul University Via Sapientiae College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences 8-2013 The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle Robin Weiss DePaul University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd Recommended Citation Weiss, Robin, "The Stoics and the practical: a Roman reply to Aristotle" (2013). College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations. 143. https://via.library.depaul.edu/etd/143 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences at Via Sapientiae. It has been accepted for inclusion in College of Liberal Arts & Social Sciences Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Via Sapientiae. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE STOICS AND THE PRACTICAL: A ROMAN REPLY TO ARISTOTLE A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy August, 2013 BY Robin Weiss Department of Philosophy College of Liberal Arts and Social Sciences DePaul University Chicago, IL - TABLE OF CONTENTS - Introduction……………………..............................................................................................................p.i Chapter One: Practical Knowledge and its Others Technê and Natural Philosophy…………………………….....……..……………………………….....p. 1 Virtue and technical expertise conflated – subsequently distinguished in Plato – ethical knowledge contrasted with that of nature in
    [Show full text]
  • Socratic Dialogue As Collegial Reasoning1
    © Society for Philosophy in Practice 2011 http://www.practical-philosophy.org.uk/ Socratic Dialogue as Collegial Reasoning1 Stan Van Hooft Introduction There has been a great deal of work in the last few years in which philosophers have sought to make their expertise as philosophers available to the world of business and of the professions. The most notable example would be bioethics but business, policing, social work, nursing, and the public sector are just some of the other areas to which philosophy has sought to make itself relevant in recent times. With due allowance for many exceptions, it would be true to say that the predominant way in which philosophy has sought to contribute to these fields is by seeking to research, discover, and apply principles of one kind or another. Once again, the best illustration comes from bioethics in which the four principles of respect for autonomy, nonmaleficence, beneficence and justice are the backbone of the approach to ethical dilemmas that have been taught in most schools and applied in most clinics. Textbooks in other fields of applied ethics are similarly based upon the strategy of defining and then applying principles to practice. ‚Principlism‛ in ethics seems to be the paradigm position in the field of applied philosophy. One consequence of this is that, insofar as they are in the profession of defining and clarifying principles, philosophers can claim expertise which they can then apply to various professional fields as paid consultants. The relationship between the philosopher and the professional becomes one of expert to client and the professional is placed into the role of one who does not know what he needs to know in order to make the ethically sound decisions that a situation might call for, while the philosopher is the one who has the expertise and who offers guidance.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Philosophy
    An Introduction to Philosophy W. Russ Payne Bellevue College Copyright (cc by nc 4.0) 2015 W. Russ Payne Permission is granted to copy, distribute and/or modify this document with attribution under the terms of Creative Commons: Attribution Noncommercial 4.0 International or any later version of this license. A copy of the license is found at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/4.0/ 1 Contents Introduction ………………………………………………. 3 Chapter 1: What Philosophy Is ………………………….. 5 Chapter 2: How to do Philosophy ………………….……. 11 Chapter 3: Ancient Philosophy ………………….………. 23 Chapter 4: Rationalism ………….………………….……. 38 Chapter 5: Empiricism …………………………………… 50 Chapter 6: Philosophy of Science ………………….…..… 58 Chapter 7: Philosophy of Mind …………………….……. 72 Chapter 8: Love and Happiness …………………….……. 79 Chapter 9: Meta Ethics …………………………………… 94 Chapter 10: Right Action ……………………...…………. 108 Chapter 11: Social Justice …………………………...…… 120 2 Introduction The goal of this text is to present philosophy to newcomers as a living discipline with historical roots. While a few early chapters are historically organized, my goal in the historical chapters is to trace a developmental progression of thought that introduces basic philosophical methods and frames issues that remain relevant today. Later chapters are topically organized. These include philosophy of science and philosophy of mind, areas where philosophy has shown dramatic recent progress. This text concludes with four chapters on ethics, broadly construed. I cover traditional theories of right action in the third of these. Students are first invited first to think about what is good for themselves and their relationships in a chapter of love and happiness. Next a few meta-ethical issues are considered; namely, whether they are moral truths and if so what makes them so.
    [Show full text]
  • Socratic Method’ in the Developmental Stages of Philosophy
    International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Research International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Research ISSN: 2455-2070; Impact Factor: RJIF 5.22 Received: 23-10-2020; Accepted: 08-11-2020; Published: 25-11-2020 www.socialsciencejournal.in Volume 6; Issue 6; 2020; Page No. 72-75 The role of the ‘Socratic method’ in the developmental stages of philosophy Pulenthiran Nesan M. Phil Student, Post graduate Institute of Humanities and Social sciences, University of Peradeniya, Peradeniya, Sri Lanka Abstract This study aims to uncover man-centered ideas by Socrates through his method (Socratic) in the course of his inquiry, free from the research of the philosophy of nature. The problem with this study is how Socrates was able to make a proper investigate into man and his life, despite the influence of his earlier thinking. What is the meaning of life? Hypotheses such as the practical application of discipline in life are put forward. Information related to this subject is derived from reports, texts, etc. of a previous study, and the study uses descriptive analysis. Greek philosophy, delighted with Ionian thought, led to the next stage of development as the Sophist thinking. It was these Sophists who first proposed the concept of man. Socrates' philosophy, which developed after them, further clarified the study of man and established a new system of philosophy. His method of dialogue, which transcends precedents, revealed the solid foundations of man, and his method was passed on to the next generation by the direct student Plato and others, such as Aristotle. It also had great influence on philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • The Socratic Method in the Age of Trauma
    THE SOCRATIC METHOD IN THE AGE OF TRAUMA Jeannie Suk Gersen When I was a young girl, the careers I dreamed of — as a prima ballerina or piano virtuoso — involved performing before an audience. But even in my childhood ambitions of life on stage, no desire of mine involved speaking. My Korean immigrant family prized reading and the arts, but not oral expression or verbal assertiveness — perhaps even less so for girls. Education was the highest familial value, but a posture of learning anything worthwhile seemed to go together with not speak- ing. My incipient tendency to raise questions and arguments was treated as disrespect or hubris, to be stamped out, sometimes through punish- ment. As a result, and surely also due to natural shyness, I had an almost mute relation to the world. It was 1L year at Harvard Law School that changed my default mode from “silent” to “speak.” Having always been a student who said nothing and preferred a library to a classroom, I was terrified and scandalized as professors called on classmates daily to engage in back-and-forth dia- logues of reasons and arguments in response to questions, on subjects of which we knew little and on which we had no business expounding. What happened as I repeatedly faced my unwelcome turn, heard my voice, and got through with many stumbles was a revelation that changed my life. A light switched on. Soon, I was even volunteering to engage in this dialogue, and I was thinking more intensely, independently, and enjoyably than I ever had before.
    [Show full text]
  • Dialogue Between Confucius and Socrates: Norms of Rhetorical Constructs in Their Dialogical Form and Dialogic Imagination
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses Graduate School 1998 Dialogue Between Confucius and Socrates: Norms of Rhetorical Constructs in Their Dialogical Form and Dialogic Imagination. Bin Xie Louisiana State University and Agricultural & Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses Recommended Citation Xie, Bin, "Dialogue Between Confucius and Socrates: Norms of Rhetorical Constructs in Their Dialogical Form and Dialogic Imagination." (1998). LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses. 6717. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_disstheses/6717 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Historical Dissertations and Theses by an authorized administrator of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter free, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorized copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e.g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand comer and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps.
    [Show full text]
  • Socratic Reductionism in Ethics
    Socratic Reductionism in Ethics Nicholas Smyth, Fordham University Genealogy is the study of the ways in which concepts, ideas, values and norms have emerged, persisted, and developed over time. Recently, philosophers have begun to argue that the method is of great importance for analytic philosophy, which has traditionally shown some resistance to historical inquiry.i Arguably, genealogy can be particularly fruitful in ethics, where there is notably wide cultural and historical variation across conceptual schemes. To understand where our ethical concepts come from is to gain insight into their social function(s), as well as to envision ways in which they might be improved, revised, or perhaps even eliminated. One of the more striking claims in the genre was made by Bernard Williams, and I shall take it as my point of departure in this paper. Williams argued that modern life in certain Western countries was characterized by the increasing prominence of certain forms of reflection, and that this reflectiveness has actually resulted in the declining influence of thick ethical concepts (such as courage and honesty), which, he claimed were de-prioritized in favor of the use of thin concepts (such as good and right). Williams suggested that the growing influence of reductionist moral theories was a sign that thinner concepts were acquiring more and more currency (Williams, 1986, p. 163). While these claims can certainly seem both puzzling and ambitious, in what follows, I’ll argue that Plato’s ‘Socratic’ dialogues actually contain a genealogical key to the nature and origin of the process Williams describes. In attempting to explain why we use the concepts we do, there is no more profitable figure than that of Socrates, who has exerted enormous influence over the methodological self-image of Western philosophers.
    [Show full text]