Modelling Selectional Super-Flexibility⋆

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Modelling Selectional Super-Flexibility⋆ Modelling Selectional Super-Flexibility? Kristina Liefke Department of Philosophy, Ruhr University Bochum, Germany [email protected] Abstract The selectional flexibility of some attitude verbs (e.g. know) between declarative and interrogative complements is a core topic in con- temporary formal semantics. Despite this focus, little attention has been paid to verbs (e.g. see, remember, observe) that embed an even wider vari- ety of complements (incl. subject-controlled gerundive clauses and con- crete object-denoting DPs). Since the familiar types of some of these com- plements resist an embedding in the type for questions [= sets of proposi- tions], these verbs challenge Theiler et al.'s (2018) uniform interpretation strategy for the complements of declarative/interrogative-neutral verbs. Our paper answers this challenge by interpreting the complements of selectionally super-flexible verbs like remember in a generalized type for questions, viz. as parametrized centered questions. The resulting seman- tics captures the intuitive entailment pattern of these verbs. Keywords: Responsive verbs · Experiential attitude verbs · Comple- mentation · Cross-categorial entailment · Inquisitive semantics. 1 Introduction Responsive verbs, i.e. verbs like know that are selectionally flexible between de- clarative (e.g. (1a)) and interrogative clauses (e.g. (1b); see [11, 17]), have been at the center of much recent work in formal semantics (see e.g. [8, 36, 37, 41, 42, 44]). (1) a. that Mary was wearing a crazy hat (declarative clause) John knows b. whether Mary was wearing a crazy hat (interrogative) Responsive verbs are particularly interesting since their flexibility cannot be attributed to an ambiguity between a declarative- and an interrogative-embedding use. Such attribution is excluded by the fact that declaratives can be coordinated with interrogatives in the complements of these verbs (see (2); ff. [12, p. 93]): (2) John knows [that Mary was wearing a crazy hat] and [whether she bought it at the party supply store] Interest in responsive verbs is further fuelled by the observation that their de- clarative and interrogative complements can stand in semantic inclusion relations (see (3) [for uni-directional inclusion] and (4) [for mutual inclusion]): ? I thank my anonymous reviewers for SALT 31 for valuable comments on the abstract of this paper. The paper has profited from discussions with Floris Roelofsen, Frank Sode, Markus Werning, and Ede Zimmermann. The research for this paper is suppor- ted by the German Research Foundation (via Ede Zimmermann's grant ZI 683/13-1). 2 K. Liefke (3) a. John knows [that Mary was wearing a crazy hat (when she arrived)] ) b. John knows [whether Mary was wearing a crazy hat :::] (4) a. #John knows [whether Mary was wearing a crazy hat] and [that she was wearing a rainbow squid hat] (redundant) ≡ b. John knows [that Mary was wearing a rainbow squid hat] The validity of entailments like (3) is typically ascribed to the observation that the information content of the interrogative clause in (3b) (i.e. `Mary was or was not wearing a crazy hat') is contained in the content of the declarative in (3a). The redundancy { and attendant markedness { of (4a) is due to the fact that the true answer to the question denoted by the first conjunct in the complement of (4a) (`Mary was wearing a crazy hat') is already informationally contained in the content of the second conjunct in (4a), where rainbow squid hats are crazy hats. The informational relations between embedded declaratives and interroga- tives pose an important empirical constraint on any adequate semantics for resp- onsive verbs. However, a suitable account of this constraint is challenged by the fact that declaratives and interrogatives are typically associated with objects of a different semantic type: while declaratives are commonly interpreted as proposi- tions (analyzed as [characteristic functions of] sets of possible worlds, type1 (s; t); see [16, 26]), interrogatives are interpreted as questions (analyzed as [characteris- tic functions of] sets of propositions, type ((s; t); t); see [7, 13, 16]). The different types of declaratives and interrogatives block an easy2 analysis of the relation be- tween the complements in (3a) and (3b) as set-theoretic inclusion and disable the familiar interpretation of natural language and in (2) and (4a) as set intersection. To answer the above challenge, Theiler et al. [36] propose that declaratives and interrogatives are uniformly interpreted in the type for questions, ((s; t); t). In this type, the common denotations of declaratives can be represented through the type-shifter λp(s;t)λq(s;t)(8ws)[q(w) ! p(w)] that sends sets of worlds p to their powersets P(p), i.e. to downward-closed sets of propositions (see [7, 8, 36]). The downward closure of these sets effects that, if these sets include p, they also include every informationally stronger proposition/set of worlds q, where q ⊂ p.3 The results of this type-shift meet the type-requirement (viz. type-identity) on entailment and coordination, and capture the intuitive relations between de- clarative and interrogative complements (see [8, 33]). Consequently, they readily account for the data in (3) and (4). My simplified account of this data (in (6), (7)) 1 To distinguish centered propositions from properties (see below), I here use multiary function types (see [30, 38]). The latter are types of the form (α1× :::×αn) ! αn+1 that are associated with functions from n-tuples of objects of the types α1, :::, αn to objects of type αn+1. Following Tich´y[38], I write (α1 × ::: × αn) ! αn+1 as (α1 : : : αn; αn+1) and identify the type (α) with α. 2 Arguably, one can enable this analysis by coding propositions as questions (see [40]). However, Theiler et al. argue (in [36, p. 413], [37]) that this move fails to explain the selectional restrictions on non-responsive verbs (e.g. the anti-rogativity of believe). 3 This differs from Alternative Semantics [13], Possibility Semantics [8], and Uegaki's [40] semantics, which identify questions with the maximal elements in these sets (cal- led alternatives). For reasons against this move, the reader is refereed to [7, 8, 33]. Modelling Selectional Super-Flexibility 3 uses the semantics for know in (5), where know := λT ((s;t);t): 9q 2 T [q(w)]: λws e 0 w 0 0 λz : 9p 2 T [p(w) ^ (8w : DOXz (w ) ! p(w ))] (see [40, p. 631]). For better read- ability, the semantic complement of know is highlighted in (6) and (7):4 ((s;t);t) s e (5) know = λT λw λz [knoww(T )(z)] J K 0 0 (6) a. knoww λp 8w : p(w ) ! (9x: crazy-hatw0 (x) ^ wearw0 (x)(m)) (j) 0 0 0 b.( 8T )(8w)(8z)[knoww(T )(z) ! (8T :T ⊆ T ! knoww(T )(z))] 0 0 ) c. knoww λp.(8w : p(w ) ! (9x: crazy-hatw0 (x) ^ wearw0 (x)(m))) _ 0 0 (8w : p(w ) !:(9x: crazy-hatw0 (x) ^ wearw0 (x)(m))) (j) 0 0 (7) a. knoww λp. ((8w : p(w ) ! (9x: crazy-hatw0 (x) ^ wearw0 (x)(m))) _ 0 0 (8w : p(w ) !:(9x: crazy-hatw0 (x) ^ wearw0 (x)(m)))) ^ 00 00 (8w : p(w ) ! (9x: squid-hatw00 (x) ^ wearw00 (x)(m))) (j) b.( 8x)(8w)[squid-hatw(x) ! crazy-hatw(x)] 0 0 , c. knoww λp 8w : p(w ) ! (9x: squid-hatw0 (x) ^ wearw0 (x)(m)) (j ) In particular, (6) models the entailment in (3) through the inclusion of Pfw0 j 9x: 0 crazy-hatw0 (x)^wearw0 (x)(m)g (see (6a)) in the union of P fw j 9x: crazy-hatw0 0 (x)^wearw0 (x)(m)g and P fw j :9x: crazy-hatw0 (x)^wearw0 (x)(m)g (see (6c)). 2 The Challenge from Experiential Attitude Verbs Its merits notwithstanding, Theiler et al.'s semantics fails to capture the selec- tional flexibility of a particular, but salient, subclass of responsive verbs: veridical experiential attitude verbs (see [14, 35]). The latter are verbs like see, remember, and observe that also combine with direct object DPs (e.g. (8e)) and with subject- controlled and non-controlled gerundive clauses (e.g. (8d, c); see [1, 14, 44]): (8) 8 a. that Mary was wearing a crazy hat( s; t); generally:((ss; t) > > b. whether Mary was wearing a crazy hat(( s; t); t) Ron <> remembers c. Mary wearing a crazy hat( s; t) or v (event) > d. PRO wearing a crazy hat( (se; t) > : e. a / Mary's crazy hat( (s; ((s;(e; t)); t)) Like the complements of know in (3) and (4), the complements of the different occurrences of remember from (8) stand in semantic/informational inclusion rela- tions to each other. These relations are exemplified in (9) to (11). They include { next to the familiar relations between declarative and interrogative complements (see (9)) { the entailment from gerundive small clauses to that-clauses (e.g. (10); as argued by [31, 43]) and to concrete object-denoting DPs (e.g. (11); see [2, 35]): (9) a. Ron remembers [that Mary was wearing a rainbow squid hat] ) b. Ron remembers [whether Mary was wearing a crazy hat] 4 For simplicity, we neglect tense and aspect of the matrix verb. 4 K. Liefke (10) a. Ron remembers [i. PRO / ii. Mary wearing a crazy hat] 6( ) b. Ron remembers [that there was a crazy hat (which i. he himself / ii. Mary was wearing)] (11) a. Ron remembers [i. PRO / ii. Mary wearing a crazy hat] 6( ) b. Ron remembers [a crazy hat] The modelling of the above relations is impeded by the observation that some of the above complements (viz. the red-marked ones in (8)) resist an interpre- tation as questions. This holds especially for concrete object-denoting DPs (see (8e)) and for subject-controlled complements (see (8d)).
Recommended publications
  • Degrees As Kinds Vs. Degrees As Numbers: Evidence from Equatives1 Linmin ZHANG — NYU Shanghai
    Degrees as kinds vs. degrees as numbers: Evidence from equatives1 Linmin ZHANG — NYU Shanghai Abstract. Within formal semantics, there are two views with regard to the ontological status of degrees: the ‘degree-as-number’ view (e.g., Seuren, 1973; Hellan, 1981; von Stechow, 1984) and the ‘degree-as-kind’ view (e.g., Anderson and Morzycki, 2015). Based on (i) empirical distinctions between comparatives and equatives and (ii) Stevens’s (1946) theory on the four levels of measurements, I argue that both views are motivated and needed in accounting for measurement- and comparison-related meanings in natural language. Specifically, I argue that since the semantics of comparatives potentially involves measurable differences, comparatives need to be analyzed based on scales with units, on which degrees are like (real) numbers. In contrast, since equatives are typically used to convey the non-existence of differences, equa- tives can be based on scales without units, on which degrees can be considered kinds. Keywords: (Gradable) adjectives, Comparatives, Equatives, Similatives, Levels of measure- ments, Measurements, Comparisons, Kinds, Degrees, Dimensions, Scales, Units, Differences. 1. Introduction The notion of degrees plays a fundamental conceptual role in understanding measurements and comparisons. Within the literature of formal semantics, there are two major competing views with regard to the ontological status of degrees. For simplicity, I refer to these two ontologies as the ‘degree-as-number’ view and the ‘degree-as-kind’ view in this paper. Under the more canonical ‘degree-as-number’ view, degrees are considered primitive objects (of type d). Degrees are points on abstract totally ordered scales (see Seuren, 1973; Hellan, 1981; von Stechow, 1984; Heim, 1985; Kennedy, 1999).
    [Show full text]
  • A Theory of Names and True Intensionality*
    A Theory of Names and True Intensionality? Reinhard Muskens Tilburg Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science [email protected] http://let.uvt.nl/general/people/rmuskens/ Abstract. Standard approaches to proper names, based on Kripke's views, hold that the semantic values of expressions are (set-theoretic) functions from possible worlds to extensions and that names are rigid designators, i.e. that their values are constant functions from worlds to entities. The difficulties with these approaches are well-known and in this paper we develop an alternative. Based on earlier work on a higher order logic that is truly intensional in the sense that it does not validate the axiom scheme of Extensionality, we develop a simple theory of names in which Kripke's intuitions concerning rigidity are accounted for, but the more unpalatable consequences of standard implementations of his theory are avoided. The logic uses Frege's distinction between sense and reference and while it accepts the rigidity of names it rejects the view that names have direct reference. Names have constant denotations across possible worlds, but the semantic value of a name is not determined by its denotation. Keywords: names, axiom of extensionality, true intensionality, rigid designation 1 Introduction Standard approaches to proper names, based on Kripke (1971, 1972), make the following three assumptions. (a) The semantic values of expressions are (possibly partial) functions from pos- sible worlds to extensions. (b) These functions are identified with their graphs, as in set theory. (c) Names are rigid designators, i.e. their extensions are world-independent. In particular, the semantic values of names are taken to be constant functions from worlds to entities, possibly undefined for some worlds.
    [Show full text]
  • EISS 12 Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 12
    EISS 12 Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 12 Edited by Christopher Pinon 2019 CSSP Paris http://www.cssp.cnrs.fr/eiss12/ ISSN 1769-7158 Contents Preface iv Anne Abeillé & Shrita Hassamal 1–30 Sluicing in Mauritian: A Fragment-Based Analysis Aixiu An & Anne Abeillé 31–60 Number Agreement in French Binomials Micky Daniels & Yael Greenberg 61–89 Extreme Adjectives in Comparative Structures and even Emilie Destruel & Joseph P. De Veaugh-Geiss 91–120 (Non-)Exhaustivity in French c’est-Clefts Regine Eckardt & Andrea Beltrama 121–155 Evidentials and Questions Yanwei Jin & Jean-Pierre Koenig 157–186 Expletive Negation in English, French, and Mandarin: A Semantic and Language Production Model Fabienne Martin & Zsófia Gyarmathy 187–216 A Finer-grained Typology of Perfective Operators Vítor Míguez 217–246 On (Un)certainty: The Semantic Evolution of Galician seguramente Emanuel Quadros 247–276 The Semantics of Possessive Noun Phrases and Temporal Modifiers EISS 12 iii Preface This is the twelfth volume of the series Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics (EISS), which, like the preceding eleven volumes of the series, is closely related to the conference series Colloque de Syntaxe et Sémantique à Paris (CSSP). The nine papers included in the present volume are based on presentations given at CSSP 2017, which took place on 23–25 November 2017 at École Normale Supérieure (http: //www.cssp.cnrs.fr/cssp2017/index_en.html). CSSP 2017 had a small thematic session entitled Discourse particles, but since the number of papers from the thematic session submitted to the volume was low, they are not grouped separately. I would like to take this opportunity to thank the reviewers, whose comments aided the authors in revising the first drafts of their pa- pers, sometimes substantially.
    [Show full text]
  • Donkey Anaphora Is In-Scope Binding∗
    Semantics & Pragmatics Volume 1, Article 1: 1–46, 2008 doi: 10.3765/sp.1.1 Donkey anaphora is in-scope binding∗ Chris Barker Chung-chieh Shan New York University Rutgers University Received 2008-01-06 = First Decision 2008-02-29 = Revised 2008-03-23 = Second Decision 2008-03-25 = Revised 2008-03-27 = Accepted 2008-03-27 = Published 2008- 06-09 Abstract We propose that the antecedent of a donkey pronoun takes scope over and binds the donkey pronoun, just like any other quantificational antecedent would bind a pronoun. We flesh out this idea in a grammar that compositionally derives the truth conditions of donkey sentences containing conditionals and relative clauses, including those involving modals and proportional quantifiers. For example, an indefinite in the antecedent of a conditional can bind a donkey pronoun in the consequent by taking scope over the entire conditional. Our grammar manages continuations using three independently motivated type-shifters, Lift, Lower, and Bind. Empirical support comes from donkey weak crossover (*He beats it if a farmer owns a donkey): in our system, a quantificational binder need not c-command a pronoun that it binds, but must be evaluated before it, so that donkey weak crossover is just a special case of weak crossover. We compare our approach to situation-based E-type pronoun analyses, as well as to dynamic accounts such as Dynamic Predicate Logic. A new ‘tower’ notation makes derivations considerably easier to follow and manipulate than some previous grammars based on continuations. Keywords: donkey anaphora, continuations, E-type pronoun, type-shifting, scope, quantification, binding, dynamic semantics, weak crossover, donkey pronoun, variable-free, direct compositionality, D-type pronoun, conditionals, situation se- mantics, c-command, dynamic predicate logic, donkey weak crossover ∗ Thanks to substantial input from Anna Chernilovskaya, Brady Clark, Paul Elbourne, Makoto Kanazawa, Chris Kennedy, Thomas Leu, Floris Roelofsen, Daniel Rothschild, Anna Szabolcsi, Eytan Zweig, and three anonymous referees.
    [Show full text]
  • Nominal Anchoring
    Nominal anchoring Specificity, definiteness and article systems across languages Edited by Kata Balogh Anja Latrouite Robert D. Van Valin‚ Jr. language Topics at the Grammar­Discourse science press Interface 5 Topics at the Grammar­Discourse Interface Editors: Philippa Cook (University of Göttingen), Anke Holler (University of Göttingen), Cathrine Fabricius­Hansen (University of Oslo) In this series: 1. Song, Sanghoun. Modeling information structure in a cross­linguistic perspective. 2. Müller, Sonja. Distribution und Interpretation von Modalpartikel­Kombinationen. 3. Bueno Holle, Juan José. Information structure in Isthmus Zapotec narrative and conversation. 4. Parikh, Prashant. Communication and content. 5. Balogh, Kata, Anja Latrouite & Robert D. Van Valin‚ Jr. (eds.) Nominal anchoring: Specificity, definiteness and article systems across languages. ISSN: 2567­3335 Nominal anchoring Specificity, definiteness and article systems across languages Edited by Kata Balogh Anja Latrouite Robert D. Van Valin‚ Jr. language science press Balogh, Kata, Anja Latrouite & Robert D. Van Valin‚ Jr. (eds.). 2020. Nominal anchoring: Specificity, definiteness and article systems across languages (Topics at the Grammar-Discourse Interface 5). Berlin: Language Science Press. This title can be downloaded at: http://langsci-press.org/catalog/book/283 © 2020, the authors Published under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Licence (CC BY 4.0): http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ ISBN: 978-3-96110-284-6 (Digital) 978-3-96110-285-3 (Hardcover) ISSN:
    [Show full text]
  • Individual/Degree Polysemy∗
    individual/degree polysemy∗ The Emergence of Number Conference, OSU Jessica Rett June 29, 2018 1 introduction • historically, several different and distinct phenomena: { amount relatives (Carlson, 1980; Heim, 1987; Grosu and Landman, 1998) (1) a. Jane drank [DP the champagne [CP they bought that evening]] individual b. It will take us the rest of our lives to drink [DP the champagne [CP they spilled that evening]] amount { container/pseudopartitive polysemy (Chierchia, 1998) (2) a. Jane smashed [DP the bottle of wine] container b. Jane drank [DP the bottle of wine] content { measure phrase polysemy (Stavrou, 2003; Landman, 2004; Rothstein, 2009) (3) a. The [two cups of wine] on this tray are blue. substance b. The [two cups of wine] in this soup is overkill. measure noun { the `how many' ambiguity (Cresti, 1995; Romero, 1998) (4) How many books must Jane read? a. Jane was told to read specific books. How many of them? object b. Jane was told to read a specific number of books. What was it? amount • correspondingly, different and distinct formal accounts: { amount relatives (Grosu, 2009; Kotek, 2011) ∗ lots of options, all construction-specific: ∗ syntactic ambiguity from a covert maximality operator in the CP; or ∗ syntactically restricted deferred reference or polysemy { container/pseudopartitive polysemy ∗ from Chierchia 1998: a construction-specific type-shifter C from a container x to its contained substance y (5) a. John smoked two packs of cigarettes. b. rλxpsmoke(John, Cpxqqqs (2(pl(pack(ι cigarettes)))) ∗ informally: `John smoked the contents of two packs of cigarettes.' ∗ elsewhere (in line with what I will propose; Pustejovsky 1995; Pustejovsky and Bouillon 1995): this is a semantic polysemy with syntactic effects ∗The bulk of this talk is based on Rett 2014.
    [Show full text]
  • Similatives and the Argument Structure of Verbs∗
    Similatives and the argument structure of verbs∗ Jessica Rett May 2012 Abstract I begin with the observation in Haspelmath and Buchholz (1998) that languages tend to use the same morpheme to mark the standard of comparison across equation constructions. In English, it is the morpheme as, in similatives like John danced as Sue (did) and equatives like John is as tall as Sue (is). The first goal of this paper is to provide an analysis of as that accounts for its distribution across these constructions. The second goal of this paper is to provide an account of Haspelmath and Buchholz's second observation, which is that while languages can form equatives with parameter markers (the first as in John is as tall as Sue (is)), languages generally do not form similatives with parameter markers. I suggest that equation constructions are a test for lexicalized argumenthood, i.e. that the equation of a non-lexicalized argument prohibits the presence of a PM, and, for English, vice-versa. This leads to the conclusion that, contrary to recent claims (Pi~n´on2008, Bochnak forthcoming), verbs, unlike adjectives, generally do not lexicalize degree arguments. 1 Introduction This paper has a narrow empirical goal and a broader theoretical goal. The former has to do with several con- structions which form a natural morphological and semantic class across languages: equation constructions, exemplified in (1) and (2) in English. (1) a. John read the same book as Sue. same/different construction b. John is as tall as Sue. equative (2) a. John danced as Sue did. (manner) similative b.
    [Show full text]
  • 40.Frana.Concealed Questions
    Forthcoming in L. Matthewson, C. Meier, H. Rullmann and T. E. Zimmermann (eds.), Companion to Semantics, Wiley’s Linguistics Companion Series. Concealed Questions (Pre-final version) Ilaria Frana University of Enna “Kore” [email protected] Abstract Concealed questions (CQs) are determiner phrases that are interpreted as if they were embedded questions. For instance, Eve’s phone number in Adam knows Eve’s phone number is interpreted as having the meaning of the question what Eve’s phone number is. CQs raise two preliminary challenges. First, it is not clear how such cases should be integrated into a uniform analysis of predicates that select for questions, canonically realized by CPs, not DPs. Second, it has to be explained how a definite description, which would normally be used to pick out an entity in the world acquires this question- like meaning. More generally, since it is not obvious how the truth-conditions of CQ- sentences should be computed, this construction raises a challenge for the principle of compositionality, according to which the literal meaning of a sentence is a function of the meanings of its parts and of the way they are syntactically combined. Keywords: attitude ascriptions, individual concepts, questions, selection, type-shifters 1. Introduction When the nominal argument of (certain) question-selecting verbs gives rise to a question- like interpretation, it goes with the name of concealed question (henceforth, CQ); some examples and their paraphrases are given below.1 (1) a. Mary knows Joan’s phone number. b. The X-ray revealed the gender of the baby. c. Your airline ticket price depends on when and where you travel.
    [Show full text]
  • The Semantics of the Czech Demonstrative Ten I Propose A
    The semantics of the Czech demonstrative ten I propose a semantic analysis of the demonstrative ten in Czech, in which ten (i) is a type-flexible and type-preserving operator, (ii) does not involve the presuppositional type-shifter ◆, and (iii) introduces two variables: an index i that “points at” some entity in the discourse (or extra-linguistic reality) and a relational variable Rj, whose value determines the relation between i and the denotation of the NP modified by the demonstrative (henceforth demonstrative NP). Core evidence Ten (glossed as dem) productively modifies NPs without a↵ecting their referential status (e.g., Berger 1993). Readings (a) of (1) and (2) show that the canonical referential reading (of Mirkem in (1)) and the canonical predicative reading (of pr´avn´ık ‘lawyer’ in (2)) can remain una↵ected by the modification by a demonstrative. Readings (b) represent the “expected” case, where the demonstrative appears to shift a predicative nominal (coerced and typically modified by a relative clause in (1)) to a referential one. The existence of readings (a) shows (i) that ten can modify both referential (type e) and predicative (type e, t ) expressions and (ii) that ten need not h i a↵ect the semantic type of the NP it modifies. (1) S t´ım Mirkem jsem nemluvil. (2) Karel je vlastnˇe ten pr´avn´ık. with dem Mirek aux.1sg neg.spoke Karel is part dem lawyer a. ‘I didn’t speak with Mirek.’ a. ‘Karel is a lawyer.’ b. ‘I didn’t speak with that Mirek.’ b. ‘Karel is the lawyer.’ Proposal The facts above could indicate either that ten is (multiply) ambiguous or that it is underspecified.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting Questions with Non-Exhaustive Answers
    Interpreting Questions with Non-exhaustive Answers A dissertation presented by Yimei Xiang to The Department of Linguistics in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the subject of Linguistics Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts May 2016 © 2016 – Yimei Xiang All rights reserved. iii Dissertation Advisor: Prof. Gennaro Chierchia Yimei Xiang Interpreting Questions with Non-exhaustive Answers Abstract This dissertation investigates the semantics of questions, with a focus on phenomena that challenge the standard views of the related core issues, as well as those that are technically difficult to capture under standard compositional semantics. It begins by re-examining several fundamental issues, such as what a question denotes, how a question is composed, and what a wh-item denotes. It then tackles questions with complex structures, including mention-some questions, multi-wh questions, and questions with quantifiers. It also explores several popular issues, such as variations of exhaustivity, sensitivity to false answers, and quantificational variability effects. Chapter 1 discusses some fundamental issues on question semantics. I pursue a hybrid categorial approach and define question roots as topical properties, which can supply propositional answers as well as nominal short answers. But different from traditional categorial approaches, I treat wh- items as existential quantifiers, which can be shifted into domain restrictors via a BeDom-operator. Moreover, I argue that the live-on set of a plural or number-neutral wh-item is polymorphic: it consists of not only individuals but also generalized conjunctions and disjunctions. Chapter 2 and 3 are centered on mention-some questions. Showing that the availability of mention-some should be grammatically restricted, I attribute the mention-some/mention-all ambi- guity of 3-questions to structural variations within the question nucleus.
    [Show full text]
  • The Semantics and Pragmatics of Perspectival Expressions in English and Bulu: the Case of Deictic Motion Verbs
    The semantics and pragmatics of perspectival expressions in English and Bulu: The case of deictic motion verbs Dissertation Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of The Ohio State University By Jefferson Barlew ∼6 6 Graduate Program in Linguistics The Ohio State University 2017 Dissertation Committee: Professor Craige Roberts, Advisor Professor Judith Tonhauser, Advisor Professor Marie Catherine de Marneffe Professor Zhiguo Xie c Jefferson Barlew, 2017 Abstract Researchers have long had the intuition that interpreting deictic motion verbs involves perspective-taking (see e.g. Fillmore 1965, 1966). In some sense, this perspective-taking is what differentiates deictic motion verbs from other motion verbs. It's what makes them \deictic". In this dissertation, I investigate the role perspective-taking plays in the inter- pretation of two deictic motion verbs in two typologically unrelated languages, the verbs come in English and zu `come' in Bulu, a Bantu language of Cameroon. The investigation reveals that zu `come' represents a previously undocumented type of deictic motion verb and that, differences in meanings notwithstanding, the interpretation of both verbs does involve perspective-taking. Part I of the dissertation consists of detailed investigations of the meanings of come and zu `come'. Conducting detailed investigations of their meanings makes it possible to state precisely the connection between their lexical semantics and pragmatics and perspective taking. Here it is. Interpreting either come or zu `come' requires the retrieval of a con- textually supplied perspective, a body of knowledge that represents the way a particular individual imagines things to be.
    [Show full text]
  • Negation, Questions, and Structure Building in a Homesign System
    Cognition 118 (2011) 398–416 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Cognition journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/COGNIT Negation, questions, and structure building in a homesign system a, b c Amy Franklin ⇑, Anastasia Giannakidou , Susan Goldin-Meadow a University of Texas Health Science Center Houston, School of Biomedical Informatics, Center for Cognitive Informatics and Decision Making, 7000 Fannin Suite, 600 Houston, Tx 77030, United States b University of Chicago, Department of Linguistics, 1010 E. 59th St.Chicago, IL 60637, United States c University of Chicago, Departments of Psychology and Human Development, 5730 S. Woodlawn Ave. Chicago, IL 60637, United States article info abstract Article history: Deaf children whose hearing losses are so severe that they cannot acquire spoken language, Received 13 October 2009 and whose hearing parents have not exposed them to sign language, use gestures called Revised 9 August 2010 homesigns to communicate. Homesigns have been shown to contain many of the properties Accepted 27 August 2010 of natural languages. Here we ask whether homesign has structure building devices for Available online 19 November 2010 negation and questions. We identify two meanings (negation, question) that correspond semantically to propositional functions, that is, to functions that apply to a sentence Keywords: (whose semantic value is a proposition, /) and yield another proposition that is more com- Negation plex ( for negation; ? for question). Combining with or ? thus involves sentence Questions q/
    [Show full text]