Michael Fried and Philosophy: Modernism, Intention, and Theatricality
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Doing Justice to Traditional Aesthetic Theories: Weitz Reconsidered
TRAMES, 2002, 6(56/51), 3, 266–279 DOING JUSTICE TO TRADITIONAL AESTHETIC THEORIES: WEITZ RECONSIDERED Marek Volt University of Tartu Abstract. In the very first lines of his famous article – ‘The Role of Theory is Aesthetics’ – Morris Weitz tells us that each of the great art theories (Emotionalism, Voluntarism, Formalism, Intuitionism, Organicism) converges in a logically vain attempt to provide the defining properties of art. He tries to examine some of the aesthetic theories in order to see if they include adequate statements about the nature of art. But instead of giving us exact descriptions of these theories, he provided us with only a very scant summary. Thus, even if Weitz were correct in thinking that all theories converged in an essential definition of art, he does not provide any further arguments for his conviction. Some aestheticians (Diffey, Tilghman, Matthews, Snoeyenbos) have tried to do justice to the traditional theories by suggesting that aesthetic theories were not attempting to offer essentialist definitions of art. Unfortunately, those critics left untouched the aesthetic theories offered by Weitz. Therefore, in order to evaluate (1) Weitz’s account of aesthetic theories and (2) to see if the criticisms concerning his account strike home, it is necessary to consider just theories mentioned by Weitz. My paper confirms a view that within aesthetic theories a variety of purposes can be recognised. For instance, the explanation and re-evaluation of art, and the completion of metaphysical system. I. Weitz and his critics The famous article of Morris Weitz (1968) – ‘The Role of Theory in Aesthetics’ – has raised many objections since it was published.1 Perhaps the chief objection is that Weitz did not take into account the possibility that art can be defined in terms of non-manifest properties. -
The New Role of Theory in Aesthetics
RECOGNITION AND RECONCILIATION: THE NEW ROLE OF THEORY IN AESTHETICS by Kristin Amber Hrehor A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy In conformity with the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Queen’s University Kingston, Ontario, Canada (September, 2007) Copyright © Kristin Amber Hrehor, 2007 Abstract George Dickie’s institutional theory of art has been subject to extensive debate over the past 30 years. It has been both revered and deplored, garnering such attention for the seemingly controversial way in which Dickie answers the question, “What is art?” In Dickie’s view, an object derives its existence as a work of art in the context of the informal institution of the “artworld,” a concept which was borrowed from Arthur Danto’s earlier work on the theoretical context surrounding works of art. Whether one finds the idea appealing or appalling, it is one that quite simply cannot be ignored, since the empirical validity of the institutional structure of art and the sorts of problems it can cause, especially in our particular time, are so remarkably clear. Another significant feature of Dickie’s institutional theory is that it provides a definition of art, a problem that philosophers of art have attempted to solve for the past few centuries. Dickie’s theory inclines one to dismiss other candidates for definitions as implausible, such as those put forth by R.G. Collingwood and Leo Tolstoy, since, as Dickie insists, an acceptable definition of art must be able to account for the many different kinds of practices that are all referred to as “art.” Both Collingwood and Tolstoy advance restricted conceptions of art that are meant to confine the use of the term “art” to a specific kind of creative activity. -
Aesthetics (HSA020N207A) | University of Roehampton
09/23/21 Aesthetics (HSA020N207A) | University of Roehampton Aesthetics (HSA020N207A) View Online (Module Validation) 156 items Further Reading - additional to the weekly readings (53 items) The birth of tragedy and other writings - Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche, Raymond Geuss, Ronald Speirs, 1999 Book | Further Reading The Disjunctive Theory of Art: The Cluster Account Reformulated - F. Longworth, A. Scarantino, 2010-03-10 Article | Further Reading The Lyotard reader - Jean-Franc ̧ ois Lyotard, Andrew E. Benjamin, 1989 Book | Further Reading On photography - Sontag, Susan, 1979 Book | Essential Reading The principles of art - Collingwood, R. G., 1938 Book | Further Reading The century of taste: the philosophical odyssey of taste in the eighteenth century - Dickie, George, 1996 Book | Further Reading Aesthetics: a critical anthology - Dickie, George, Sclafani, R. J., Roblin, Ronald, c1989 Book | Further Reading An introduction to the philosophy of art - Richard Thomas Eldridge, 2014 Book | Further Reading Schopenhauer - Patrick Lancaster Gardiner, 1963 Book | Further Reading The Routledge companion to aesthetics - Gaut, Berys Nigel, Lopes, Dominic, 2005 Book | Further Reading Languages of art: an approach to a theory of symbols - Goodman, Nelson, 1968 Book | Further Reading Philosophy of the arts: an introduction to aesthetics - Graham, Gordon, 1997 1/11 09/23/21 Aesthetics (HSA020N207A) | University of Roehampton Book | Further Reading The sociology of art - Arnold Hauser, 2013 Book | Further Reading Emotion and the Arts - Mette Hjort, -
31762100154713.Pdf (2.570Mb)
Working papers : the artist as critical consciousness by Larry Eugene Shelby A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF APPLIED ARTS Approved: airman ,''Exaiftining Committee Montana State University © Copyright by Larry Eugene Shelby (1975) Abstract: I. An Inquiry into the Definition of Art and Artist. This paper inquires into the nature and relevance of ex-isting definition of "Art" and "Artist." There is an analogy between the manner which art as an institution and a dictionary definition function. If language (or art) is to remain viable, it must be open to the continual revision necessary as part of the constantly changing social environment. In the sense that a dictionary is a reference book, an "inbuilt" dictionary is part of each of our mental equipment. The inbuilt dictionary is best altered through the educational system. Lexical items which have become irrelevant to the situations which they are to describe should be restructured. II. On the De-Definition/Re-Definition of Art. This essay is a rebuttal to Harold Rosenberg's article "On The De-Definition of Art" chosen because it is typical of arguments for defining art by morphological characteristics (i.e., formalist criticism). Approaches of this type have failed to deal with questions raised by "conceptual" artists regarding the existence, function and future of art, and, by implication, the education of the artist. III. Art: An Open Textured Concept. A condensed version of Morris Weitz' essay "The Role of Theory in Aesthetics" was provided. As a theory of aesthetics it is quite sufficient but Weitz presupposes that art is always of an aesthetic nature. -
If Materialism Is Not the Solution, Then What Was the Problem? a Response to Harman Robert Jackson
If Materialism Is Not the Solution, Then What Was the Problem? A Response to Harman Robert Jackson abstract What follows is a cursory response to Graham Harman’s article “Materialism is Not the Solution.” It seeks to branch out his conception of ‘form’ and more specifically, ‘aesthetic form’ whilst expanding on Harman’s principal objections to the materialist account of change, and how this may challenge the contemporary aesthetic trajectory of relational encounter: par- ticularly Bourriaud’s Relational Aesthetics (2002). Quite generally, Harman’s Object Oriented Ontology might be understood through two chief aesthetic mechanisms; the contingency of counterfactuals complimented with the preliminary development of a nonmodern formalism. The latter is briefly cashed out in a philosophical juxtaposition to Greenberg and Fried’s mod- ernist principles. keywords Formalism, Materialism, Clement Greenberg, Michael Fried, Graham Harman, Object Oriented Ontology, Relational Aesthetics, Specula- tive Realism Counterfactuals Navigating any contemporary philosophical system is hard, as it is navi- gating a new computing language or cityscape. No-one really knows what it can do, at least not without experimentation. Systems of thought do not operate any differently. Object Oriented Ontology (hereby referred to as OOO) requires a good deal of navigation, and playful experimentation before it can be used as a platform for doing things with other things. Amongst many pragmatist experiments, one of the more famous OOO devices is the ‘Latour Litany’ (coined by fellow OOO veteran Ian Bogost), to describe Bruno Latour’s strange ontographical practice of list naming: the rhetorical function of which reveals the “inherent partition between things.”1 And it is a use- ful practice for sure: enumerating different, potentially infinite lists of things before critique can inspect their ontological validity. -
Final Thesis
A DEFENSE OF AESTHETIC ANTIESSENTIALISM: MORRIS WEITZ AND THE POSSIBLITY OF DEFINING ‘ART’ _____________________________ A Thesis Presented to The Honors Tutorial College Ohio University _____________________________ In Partial Fulfillment Of the Requirements for Graduation from the Honors Tutorial College with the degree of Bachelor of Arts in Philosophy and Art History _____________________________ By Jordan Mills Pleasant June, 2010 ii This thesis has been approved by The Honors Tutorial College and the Department of Philosophy ___________________________ Dr. Arthur Zucker Chair, Department of Philosophy Thesis Advisor ___________________________ Dr. Scott Carson Honors Tutorial College, Director of Studies Philosophy ___________________________ Jeremy Webster Dean, Honors Tutorial College iii This thesis has been approved by The Honors Tutorial College and the Department of Art History ___________________________ Dr. Jennie Klein Chair, Department of Art History Thesis Advisor ___________________________ Dr. Jennie Klein Honors Tutorial College, Director of Studies Art History ___________________________ Jeremy Webster Dean, Honors Tutorial College iv Dedicated to Professor Arthur Zucker, without whom this work would have been impossible. v Table Of Contents Thesis Approval Pages Page ii Introduction: A Brief History of the Role of Definitions in Art Page 1 Chapter I: Morris Weitz’s “The Role of Theory in Aesthetics” Page 8 Chapter II: Lewis K. Zerby’s “A Reconsideration of the Role of the Theory in Aesthetics. A Reply to Morris Weitz” -
Morris Weitz Aili W
University of Dayton eCommons Philosophy Faculty Publications Department of Philosophy 2014 Morris Weitz Aili W. Bresnahan University of Dayton, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://ecommons.udayton.edu/phl_fac_pub Part of the History of Philosophy Commons eCommons Citation Bresnahan, Aili W., "Morris Weitz" (2014). Philosophy Faculty Publications. 4. https://ecommons.udayton.edu/phl_fac_pub/4 This Encyclopedia Entry is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Philosophy at eCommons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of eCommons. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. Word Count: 2,494 [Main body text: 1,189; Bibliography: 1,305] Weitz, Morris (1916-1981), American philosopher of aesthetics who focused primarily on ontology, interpretation, and literary criticism. Weitz’ Initial Theory of Art. Morris Weitz’ initial theory of art was provided in his book, Philosophy of the Arts (Weitz 1950). Here Weitz calls his theory of art “empirical” and “organic,” and he defined “art” as “an organic complex or integration of expressive elements embodied in a sensuous medium” (51). By “empirical” he means that his theory answers to the evidence provided by actual works of art. “Organic,” for Weitz, means that each element is to be considered in relation to the others in a living and not merely mechanical way. Weitz also has a broad understanding of “expressive,” which refers to an artistic property that functions as a semiotic sign, either of a specific emotional feeling, an emotional quality, or another sign of an emotional feature. -
The Fear of Aesthetics in Art and Literary Theory Sam Rose
The Fear of Aesthetics in Art and Literary Theory Sam Rose New Literary History, Volume 48, Number 2, Spring 2017, pp. 223-244 (Article) Published by Johns Hopkins University Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/nlh.2017.0011 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/663805 Access provided at 2 May 2019 15:33 GMT from University of St Andrews The Fear of Aesthetics in Art and Literary Theory Sam Rose eading the preface to the new edition of the Encyclopedia of Aesthetics, one might think that the battle over the status of aes- Rthetics is over. According to the narrative of its editor Michael Kelly, aesthetics, held in generally low esteem at the time of the 1998 first edition, has now happily overcome its association with “an alleg- edly retrograde return to beauty,” or its representation as “an ideology defending the tastes of a dominant class, country, race, gender, sexual preference, ethnicity, or empire.”1 The previously “rather pervasive anti- aesthetic stance” of the 1990s passed away with that decade.2 Defined as “critical reflection on art, culture, and nature,” aesthetics is now a respectable practice once again.3 The publication of the Encyclopedia’s latest iteration is a timely moment to review the current state of its much-maligned subject. The original edi- tion of 1998 faced major difficulties, with Kelly writing that his requests for contributions were greeted not only with silence from some, but also with responses from angry callers keen to tell him how misguided the entire project was.4 And while Kelly emphasizes the change toward a more positive view, in some critics, it seems, the fear of aesthetics in art and literary theory has only increased. -
Part I: Classic Sources
^Xn I ill Mb Alternative Table of Contents ix Preface and Acknowledgments xvi Source Acknowledgments xvii Part I: Classic Sources 1 Introduction 3 Paul Oskar Kristeller 2 Ion 16 Plato 3 The Republic 24 Plato 4 Symposium 34 Plato 5 Poetics 41 Aristotle 6 Ennead I, vi 57 Plotinus 7 De Musica 64 St. Augustine 8 On the Reduction of the Arts to Theology 72 St. Bonaventure 9 Characteristics of Men, Manners, Opinions, Times 77 Third Earl of Shaftesbury VI CONTENTS 10 An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue 87 Francis Hutcheson 11 Of the Standard of Taste 103 David Hume 12 A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful 113 Edmund Burke 13 Laocoon 123 Gotthold Lessing 14 Critique of Judgement 131 Immanuel Kant Part II: Modern Theories 15 Introduction 163 Christopher Janaway 16 Letter of an Aesthetic Education of Man 167 Friedrich Schiller 17 Philosophy of Art 170 Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von Schelling 18 The Philosophy of Fine Art 180 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel 19 The World as Will and Representation 193 Arthur Schopenhauer 20 The Beautiful in Music 217 Eduard Hanslick 21 The Birth of Tragedy 222 Friedrich Nietzsche 22 What is Art? 233 Leo Tolstoy 23 "Psychical Distance" as a Factor in Art and an Aesthetic Principle 243 Edward Bullough 24 Art 261 Give Bell 25 Aesthetics 270 Benedetto Croce 26 The Principles of Art 282 JR. G. Collingwood 27 Art as Experience 296 John Dewey CONTENTS VI1 28 Feeling and Form 317 Susanne hanger 29 The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction 327 Walter Benjamin 30 The Origin of the Work of Art 344 Martin Heidegger 31 Aesthetic Theory 358 TheodorA dorno 32 Truth and Method 370 Hans-Georg Gadamer 33 Introduction 391 Susan L. -
Barry University
MORAVIAN COLLEGE COURSE SYLLABUS Spring 2012 PHIL 199 Special Topics: Introduction to Aesthetics 3b (TR 10:20-11:30) Office Hours: Tuesdays 1-2 and Wednesdays 1-2 Instructor: Dr. Bernie Cantens Visiting Instructor: Dr. Arash Naraghi Classroom: Comenius 218 Office: Comenius Hall 107 Phone/E-Mail: (610) 861-1589/ [email protected] Web Page: http://berniephilosophy.com/ Text (PAB) Philosophies of Art and Beauty: Selected Readings in Aesthetics from Plato to Heidegger Edited by Albert Hofstadter and Richard Kuhns. University of Chicago Press, 1964. ISBN 0-226-34812-1 (IA) Introduction to Aesthetics: An Analytic Approach George Dickie.Oxford University Press, 1997. ISBN 978-0-19-511304-4 * Make sure you bring the text to every class! Course Description The course is a historical and contemporary introduction to the philosophy of beauty and art. Central questions include: What is the nature of beauty? What is art? Are there objective aesthetic values? Are there objective criteria for the evaluation of art? Are there objective interpretations of art? 100-Level Course This course is meant as a first course in philosophy. It will introduce students to basic vocabulary and basic philosophical concepts and theories. Course Goals The objectives of this course are the following: 1) to study the origin and nature of theories of beauty in ancient Greece; 2) to survey the historical development and evolution of the theories of beauty from ancient Greece to the present; 3) to study theories of art from Plato and Aristotle to the present; 4) to study aesthetic-attitude theories of beauty; 5) to study metacriticism theories of beauty; 6) to develop a framework of some of the central problems in aesthetics through four issues: (i) intentionalist criticism, (ii) symbolism in art, (iii) metaphor, and iv) expression; 7) to apply theoretical knowledge about art and beauty to practical examples of art and beauty; and 8) to study some of the contemporary theories of evaluating art. -
KATHARINE M.J. LARSON Department of Art and Art History | Baylor University Hooper-Schaefer Fine Arts Center | Waco, Texas 76706 E-Mail: Katie [email protected]
KATHARINE M.J. LARSON Department of Art and Art History | Baylor University Hooper-Schaefer Fine Arts Center | Waco, Texas 76706 e-mail: [email protected] EDUCATION 2017 Ph.D., History of Art, Johns Hopkins University Dissertation: “Alberto Burri in Rome, 1946-1960” Supervisors: Michael Fried and Molly Warnock 2011 M.A., History of Art, Johns Hopkins University 2008 B.A., History of Art, Honors Program, University of Michigan Honors Thesis: “Burri and Fontana: Different Approaches to Materiality in Post War Art” Supervisor: MattheW Biro ACADEMIC APPOINTMENTS 2019- Assistant Professor of Modern and Contemporary Art History, Allbritton Art Institute, Department of Art and Art History, Baylor University 2018-2019 Postdoctoral FelloW, Department of Art History, Theory, and Criticism, Maryland Institute College of Art SELECTED AWARDS, HONORS, AND FELLOWSHIPS 2021 Summer Sabbatical Research Grant, Baylor University 2020 Summer Sabbatical Research Grant, Baylor University 2016-2017 Ph.D. Scholar, Gerda Henkel Stiftung 2015-2016 Chuck Close Pre-Doctoral Rome Prize, Modern Italian Studies, American Academy in Rome 2015 Singleton FelloW, Johns Hopkins University 2014 Dean’s Teaching FelloW, Johns Hopkins University Hall Teaching FelloW, Johns Hopkins University Cropper Summer Travel AWard for research in Rome, Italy 2013 Top 10 Finalist, Johns Hopkins University Excellence in Teaching AWard, “Best Teaching Assistant” Cropper Summer Travel AWard for research in Rome, Italy 2012 Sadie and Louis Roth Summer Travel AWard for research in Milan, Italy 2011 Katzenellenbogen Award for research in Paris, France 2009-2014 Gilman FelloW, Johns Hopkins University 2009-2012 OWens Scholar AWard, recruiting grant, Johns Hopkins University 2008 Initiation, Phi Kappa Phi, University of Michigan Chapter Initiation, Phi Beta Kappa, University of Michigan Chapter Henry P. -
No Time for Art? Marc Augã©, Michael Fried, Jeff Wall
No Time for Art? Marc Augé, Michael Fried, Jeff Wall Emer O’Beirne In the essay Le Temps en ruines published in 2003, Marc Augé turned his attention to the place and role of art in the contemporary period he calls supermodernity. His prescription is surprisingly specific: art should address the passage of time and the discontinuities and loss it involves: ‘Les artistes d’aujourd’hui […] pressentent […] que c’est à l’art de sauver ce qu’il y a de plus précieux dans les ruines et dans les œuvres du passé: un sens du temps d’autant plus provocant et émouvant qu’il est irréductible à l’histoire, qu’il est conscience du manque, expression de l’absence, pur désir’.1 The statement surprises only for its narrow prescriptiveness; the outlook it articulates chimes fully with the elegiac thrust of Augé’s diagnosis of life in today’s western and western-style economies as he has elaborated it ever since La Traversée du Luxembourg in 1985, the moment of his professional transition to ‘l’anthropologie du proche’. Since then, Augé has described a world exemplified by the ‘non-place’ and envisaged in terms of loss (of cultural identities, histories, and relations) brought about by paradoxical excess (of decontextualized snatches of world events encountered in mass-mediated isolation rather than experienced collectively). Lives dominated by the non-lieu are lives, as he famously put it almost twenty years ago, ‘où l’on naît en clinique et où l’on meurt à l’hôpital’; between these poles one navigates a world ‘promis à l’individualité solitaire, au passage, au provisoire et à l’éphémère’.2 Of course, art need not be bound to an evocation of 1.