Common Sense Biblical Hermeneutics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Common Sense Biblical Hermeneutics Studia Gilsoniana 3:supplement (2014): 547–562 | ISSN 2300–0066 Michael B. Mangini, Esq. Adler–Aquinas Institute Manitou Springs, CO, USA COMMON SENSE BIBLICAL HERMENEUTICS The chief aim, the final cause, of this study is to foster a better un- derstanding of how noetic, metaphysical, and semiotic preconditions rooted in the philosophy of Aristotle and St. Thomas Aquinas contribute to a common sense biblical hermeneutic. The efficient cause is wonder over the divergent opinions of the meaning and significance of one perfect reve- latory unit and the possibility of discovering how many revelatory acts constitute one unified revelatory act. The material cause is composed of (a) the noetic aspects of moderate realism; (b) the actions of sign relations in communication and interpretation; (c) the problem of the one and the many; and (d) God’s revealed word. The formal cause is movement from a nominalistic method of biblical interpretation toward a method that finds truth as revealed in God’s Word, the proper object of Christian faith, and becomes, in fact, the object of our faith. This study finds a metaphysical justification for a theologically derived principle of scriptural unity; thus showing how reason serves faith. The interpretive principles of nominalism are the interpreter’s ideas that the interpreter combines and divides at will and which terminate in the interpreter’s mind. The interpretive principles identified in this paper are: (a) the noetics of moderate realism ground the hope of successfully discerning the meaning of Scripture; (b) the nature and activity of sign relations ground the hope of successfully discovering and communicating the significance of Scripture, beyond its meaning; (c) sign relations also make possible error and deceit; and (d) respect for the metaphysics of the relationship between and among a multitude and to a chief aim encourages correct interpretation by minimizing errors in dis- cerning meaning and significance. Before exploring this further, an expla- nation of the compound term ‘common sense hermeneutics’ is appropriate, but first a brief note on nominalism and principles. 548 Michael B. Mangini For the nominalist a sign relation is a mind-dependent being of pure objectivity with no actual counterpart in what is signified.1 One who en- gages in a nominalistic reading of the Bible expressly or implicitly tends to take liberties with the text by associating the wrong signified being with a sign vehicle. Respecting the sign relation’s grounding in mind- independent reality will tend to inhibit the personal musings of the inter- preter. A principle is a point of beginning of being, change, or knowledge.2 Hermeneutics3 is the speculative science4 of biblical interpretation, the chief aim of which is to know how to interpret God’s word. Its subject- matter5 is composed of three species: (1) Scripture; (2) the art6 of interpre- tation; and (3) human cognition. The three species are inextricably related, but they can stand on their own, so it is reasonable to view each of them as a distinct genus composed of species ordered to a chief aim and chief act, 7 but within the genus of hermeneutics they are species ordered to a chief aim. Scripture as a revelatory species is the proximate principle of the sci- ence, and the science is the proximate principle of the art. The species of human cognition, comprising the active and passive powers of the human soul that unequally contribute to the chief aim of knowing God’s word, enables human beings to study the Bible and study how we study the Bible. The speculative genus studies how the cognitive species unites with the 1 John Deely, Four Ages of Understanding: The First Postmodern Survey of Philosophy from Ancient Times to the Turn of the Twenty-First Century (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2001), 389. 2 Aristotle, Metaphysics, Bk. V, 1012b34–1013a23, in Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle’s “Metaphysics,” trans. John P. Rowan (Notre Dame: Dumb Ox Books, 1995), 276; Peter A. Redpath, A Not-So-Elementary Christian Metaphysics (Manitou Springs: Adler– Aquinas Institute, Socratic Press, 2012), 138; Bernard Wuellner, Summary of Scholastic Principles (Chicago: Loyola University Press, 1956), 1–9. 3 See D.G. Burke, “Interpret; Interpretation,” in The International Standard Bible Encyclo- pedia, vol. 2, ed. Geoffrey W. Bromiley (Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmanns Publishing Company, 1982), 863. But there is also a practical aspect that falls into the category of art. Milton S. Terry, Biblical Hermeneutics (Grand Rapids: Zondervan Publishing House, 1983), 20. 4 Wuellner defines science in its strict philosophical sense as “certain intellectual knowledge of something in its causes” under “Science” in Wuellner, Dictionary of Scholastic Philoso- phy, 112. 5 “Subject-matter” refers to what a science studies or considers. Redpath, 137–138. 6 Wuellner primarily defines art as “correct knowledge joined to skill in making things” under “Art” in Wuellner, Dictionary of Scholastic Philosophy, 9. 7 The analogical predication of genus and species to the same unit is dependent on the unit’s relations to other units. Scripture in se is a genus, but as a subject of study it is a species of the science or art. Common Sense Biblical Hermeneutics 549 revelatory species in the interpretive species. The speculative genus is where the reflexive aspect of the cognitive species considers the relation of the revelatory, interpretive, and cognitive species. Stated another way, the art of interpretation is the activity that joins the knower to the known through sign relations, and the science is the study of the activity’s causes so that the knower and known truly unite. Hermeneutics is necessary, be- cause one cannot interpret well absent the knowledge of the conditions necessary for correct interpretation. Common sense is more difficult to define. Étienne Gilson observes that the ambiguity of the term ‘common sense’ has caused grievous phi- losophical harm. Cicero used the term to refer to the sensibilities of an audience of which an orator must be aware in order to move the audience. It may refer to human moral intuition. One may attribute the sanctity of his pet postulate to common sense to defend against further inquiry.8 According to Thomas, the common sense, one of the interior senses, is the common root or principle of the five exterior, proper senses.9 Each of the five exterior senses has an object proper to it. Sight senses white, taste senses sweetness, but neither sight nor taste can distinguish white from sweet. The common sense perceives the intentions of the proper senses and judges them.10 The common sense can know all sensations and distinguish them.11 The common sense is reflexive; it permits one to perceive that he is using his external senses. It is aware of the external sense impressions themselves and of the differences between the objects of each proper sense. “It is by the common sense that we are aware of our own life, and that we can distinguish between the objects of different senses, e.g., the white and the sweet.”12 The external senses feed the internal senses (common sense, imagination, and memory), which cooperate to unify, preserve, and recall the image of the object of sense experience. The three acts of the intellect (apprehension, judgment, and reason)13 work with these images to give us knowledge. The common sense is a necessary condition precedent to ap- prehension, judging, and reasoning, without which we would not have 8 This treatment of common sense relies on the first chapter of Étienne Gilson, Thomist Realism And The Critique of Knowledge (San Francisco: Ignatius Press, 1986), 27–53. 9 Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I, 78, 4, ad. 1. 10 Id., ad. 2. 11 Aristotle, De Anima, III, 2 (426b8–427a15). 12 Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle’s “De Anima,” II, lect. 13, para. 390; III, lect. 2, para. 584. 13 Peter Kreeft, Socratic Logic (South Bend: St. Augustine’s Press, 2004), 28. 550 Michael B. Mangini concepts, judgments, and arguments.14 Even so, the common sense does not assure that human beings will (1) rightly understand what they receive through the external senses; (2) correctly judge what they do understand; and (3) build sound arguments with their correct judgments. The common sense merely makes good hermeneutics and revealed knowledge possible. In this paper the denotation of common sense is synecdochic; the in- ternal common sense, a part of the noetic process, represents the whole noetic process, which begins in the external sense impressions and ends in the conclusions of arguments. It should also connote the commonality of specific noetic potential among human beings as well as self-evident propositions that proceed from the right use of human noetic powers (the denial of which would result in self-refutation). Into this category of propositions I put the law of con-contradiction and its corollaries; funda- mental statements about the organizational structure of composed being; and averments concerning the action of signs as the foundation of commu- nication and error. Common sense hermeneutics respects the primacy of being and the inter-subjective and supra-subjective relations among beings that permit communication. The noetics of moderate realism provide a firm foundation upon which to build a hermeneutic of common sense, so in the first part of this paper I shall adopt Thomas Howe’s argument that the noetical aspect of moderate realism is a necessary condition for correct, universally valid biblical interpretation, but I will add, “insofar as it gives us hope in discov- ering the true meaning of a given passage.” In the second part, I’ll rely on John Deely’s work to show how semiotics may help interpreters go beyond meaning and seek the significance of the persons, places, events, ideas, etc.
Recommended publications
  • Modernity and the (Im)Possibility of Transcendence
    Modernity and the (Im)Possibility of Transcendence A Cognitive Map for Liberation: From Nietzsche and Modern Binaries to Ghazalian Noetics by Fareah Fysudeen A thesis presented for the BA degree with Honors in Philosophy The Department of Philosophy University of Michigan Winter 2021 Advisors: Daniel Herwitz and Alexander Knysh i ii Acknowledgments This thesis wouldn’t have been possible without the continued support of my primary advisor, Dr. Daniel Herwitz, and my secondary advisor, Dr. Alexander Knysh. It is with their guidance, feedback, and encouragement that I was able to undertake what still seems to me a mammoth task. I would like to thank the Philosophy Department for being my first love at the University of Michigan and for housing a particularly astounding group of faculty who have allowed me the creative and intellectual freedom to critique, challenge, and wonder about the world and its meaning, especially David Baker, Laura Reutsche, James Joyce, Andreas Gailus, and again Daniel Herwitz. I also thank my professors Samer Ali, Su’ad Abdul Khabeer, and Debotri Dhar for revolutionizing my understanding of Islam and/or liberation. My intellectual journey in my undergraduate career began with the particularly plucky group of young philosophers in the Society of Deontology (run by the inspirational Guus Duindam) whose conversations I will always remember fondly; and it led me all the way to Morocco where I met an Islamic environmentalist who set my life down a surprising and wonderful trajectory. For both, I am incredibly grateful. I thank my Muslim community at the University of Michigan and at home for reminding me where love and home truly is.
    [Show full text]
  • History of Medieval Philosophy - En-Cours-2017-Lfilo1281 Lfilo1281 History of Philosophy 2: History of 2017 Medieval Philosophy
    Université catholique de Louvain - History of philosophy 2: History of medieval Philosophy - en-cours-2017-lfilo1281 lfilo1281 History of philosophy 2: History of 2017 medieval Philosophy 3 credits 30.0 h Q1 This biannual learning is being organized in 2017-2018 Teacher(s) Counet Jean-Michel ; Language : French Place of the course Louvain-la-Neuve Prerequisites / The prerequisite(s) for this Teaching Unit (Unité d’enseignement – UE) for the programmes/courses that offer this Teaching Unit are specified at the end of this sheet. Main themes The course will carefully examine the genesis of philosophy in the Middle Ages. The links to doctrines from Antiquity are very strong. However, we notice also that an interiority characteristic of Augustinian Christianity begins to gain ground, as does a type of rational questioning based on faith. Authors such as Augustine, Boethius, and Pseudo- Dionysius are revealing in this respect. Having examined the links to Antiquity, we shall move on to an examination of the impact that Arab thought had on Medieval thinking: the rediscovery of Aristotle through Arabic and Greek translations; the emergence of the University as an institution devoted to philosophical reflection. Finally, we shall examine the impact of the condemnations of 1277: these dealt a fatal blow to radical Averroism and, in the end, gave birth to a class of intellectuals who thought outside of a direct reference to the Church. Aims By the end of the course, the student should be able to give an account of the main problems Medieval philosophers confronted (the problem of universals, reason and faith, logic and the knowledge of God, Aristotelianism and Neo-Platonism, transitions-from antiquity and into the Renaissance, etc.).
    [Show full text]
  • Noetics Lawrence Krader
    Noetics Lawrence Krader ©2010 Cyril Levitt Editor’s Introduction Lawrence Krader passed away on November 15, 1998, after having produced what he considered to be the antepenultimate draft of his magnum opus on noetics. He planned to prepare the final draft for publication in the following year. In August 1998, during our last face- to-face meeting in Berlin, he reviewed the theory of noetics with me and felt confident that the manuscript he had completed to that point contained all the major ideas that he wished to present to the reading public. It was then a matter of fine-tuning. In preparing this manuscript for publication, I have exercised my editorial privilege and decided not to second guess the author in terms of clarifying ambiguities in the text, smoothing out cumbersome con- structions of language that would have surely been changed in the final draft, eliminate repetitive thoughts or passages, or adding and specifying further bibliographic detail that might be of help to the reader. I’ve performed some light editing, correcting spelling and grammar mistakes such as they were, and obvious errors, for example, where one thinker was identified in the text when it was clear that another was meant. I decided upon this strategy not only because I didn’t want to second-guess the intention of the author in matters of detail; in addition, I felt that the reader should wrestle with Krader’s words as he left them. The book will be a “rougher” and less elegant read, but the reader will hopefully benefit from this encounter with a manuscript in statu nascendi, a whole lacking the finishing touches and some elegant turns of phrase in a polished draft of which the author could say “this is my final product.” In a strange way, as the reader will discover, the lack of synthesis is a theme of noetics.
    [Show full text]
  • Noetics in Pastoral Counselling: the Making of a Semantic Differential Analysis in Pastoral Care and Counselling
    Page 1 of 5 Original Research Noetics in pastoral counselling: The making of a semantic differential analysis in pastoral care and counselling Author: Praxis in pastoral care and counselling entails more than merely practice and practicalities 1 Daniël J. Louw (communication skills). Praxis refers to the intentionality within human action and behaviour. Affiliation: Praxis exhibits the realm of intentionality and meaning as displayed within and by human 1Department of Practical attitudes. It is hypothesised that due to the noetic dimension in human actions, the making of Theology & Missiology, a pastoral diagnosis (a qualitative assessment of the impact of Christian spirituality and the University of Stellenbosch, meaning on the system of existential, relational networking) should deal with the realm of South Africa significant and purposeful intentionality. The latter is already implied in the phenomenological Correspondence to: approach of Edmund Husserl’s eidetic observation or inspection (phenomenological Daniël Louw consciousness). In order to incorporate noetics in pastoral care and counselling, a pastoral semantic differential analysis (PSDA) within the making of a pastoral diagnosis was proposed. Email: [email protected] The PSDA was linked to the need for a qualitative approach regarding the impact of God- images on religious association and existential life experiences. Postal address: 171 Dorp Street, Stellenbosch 7600, South Africa Introduction Besides the realm of self-transcendence another important domain should get attention in pastoral Dates: care and counselling, namely noetics. Noetics differs from moral guidance in the sense that whilst Received: 24 Jun. 2010 1 Accepted: 06 May 2011 moral guidance focus on habit and virtue (Sperry 2002:70) in the formation and transformation Published: 16 Sept.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysics Or Metaphors for the Anthropocene? Scientific Naturalism and the Agency of Things
    Open Philosophy 2018; 1: 191–212 Patrick Gamez* Metaphysics or Metaphors for the Anthropocene? Scientific Naturalism and the Agency of Things https://doi.org/10.1515/opphil-2018-0014 Received June 17, 2018; accepted July 31, 2018 Abstract: In this paper, I provide the outlines of an alternative metaphilosophical orientation for Continental philosophy, namely, a form of scientific naturalism that has proximate roots in the work of Bachelard and Althusser. I describe this orientation as an “alternative” insofar as it provides a framework for doing justice to some of the motivations behind the recent revival of metaphysics in Continental philosophy, in particular its ecological-ethical motivations. In the second section of the paper, I demonstrate how ecological-ethical issues motivate new metaphysicians like Bruno Latour, Jane Bennett, Timothy Morton, Ian Bogost, and Graham Harman to impute to objects real features of agency. I also try to show how their commitments lead to deep ambiguities in their metaphysical projects. In the final section, I outline a type of scientific naturalism in Continental philosophy that parallels the sort of naturalism championed by Quine, both conceptually and historically, and suggest that it might serve our ecological-ethical purposes better. Keywords: speculative realism, vital materialism, environmental ethics, non-anthropocentrism, Bachelard, Althusser, Continental philosophy 1 Introduction 1.1 Overview The landscape of Continental philosophy has changed radically in the early 21st century. The last 15 years have seen a resurgence of speculative philosophy, rationalisms, and realisms of all stripes. We see this in the “new materialism” of Diana Coole and others, the Deleuzian realism of Manuel Delanda, the “object-oriented philosophy” of Graham Harman, and many others.
    [Show full text]
  • Background Behind Lawrence Krader's Development of Noetics
    Lawrence Krader’s Development of Noetics By Dr. Sabine Sander and Prof. Cyril Levitt The Development of Noetics The following material provides a brief overview of Krader’s development of Noetics. 1 Noetics: Investigating Human Thought and Knowledge Lawrence Krader’s scope of research was an interdisciplinary approach – philosophical, an- thropological, sociological, historical and ethnological – with regard to investigating the complex interrelation of nature and of culture, and of human being, society and person. In his magnum opus, Noetics (2010), which he began in 1937 while still an undergraduate major- ing in philosophy at the City College of New York, Krader investigated one of the central questions of the philosophy of science: What is human thinking and knowing, thought and knowledge — what are the tenets of a science of noetics and how do they relate to human emotion, desire, will, intuition, teleology, as well as to human as subject-object, and to self- knowledge. Krader argues that the discovery of the quantum realm was revolutionary in that it showed that nature was not continuous, homogeneous, solely material, absolute, universal and in this sense law-like, but that the quantum realm was a different order of nature from that of the material universe. This discovery enabled Krader to represent the human order of nature as yet a third order distinct from both the material and the quantum order. Much of noetic science deals with the nature of the human order and its interrelations with the mate- rial order. In Noetics, the assertion that man is both Homo sapiens and human being existing within the material and human orders of nature is made, and it is argued that human knowledge is not only the result of mental operations of thinking and of rational acts, but it is also acquired in daily routines with subjective, self-evident insights, emotions, feelings and values, consciously and unconsciously.
    [Show full text]
  • [email protected] an Annotated Bibliography of Recent Studies In
    13/7/2021 Descartes: Bibliography of the Studies in English Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon | e-mail: [email protected] An annotated bibliography of recent studies in English on the philosophy of Descartes BIBLIOGRAPHY 1. Aalderink, Mark Jan Herman. 2010. Philosophy, Scientific Knowledge, and Concept Formation in Geulincx and Descartes. Utrecht: Quaestiones Infinitae. 2. Aczel, Amir D. 2005. Descartes' Secret Notebook. New York: Broadway Books. 3. Alanen, Lilli; Knuuttila, Simo. 1988. "The Foundations of Modality and Conceivability in Descartes and his Predecessors." In Modern Modalities. Studies of the History of Modal Theories from Medieval Nominalism to Logical Positivism, edited by Knuttila, Simo, 1-69. Dordrecht: Reidel. "Descartes's view of modality is analyzed by contrast to two earlier models: the ancient realist one, defended by Boethius, where possibility and necessity are connected to natural potency, and the modern intensionalist one, which dissociates necessary and possible truths from any ontological foundation, treating them as conceptual, a priori given preconditions for any intellect. The emergence of this view is traced from Gilbert of Poitiers to Duns Scotus, Ockham and Suarez. The Cartesian theory of the creation of eternal truths, it is argued, involves a rejection of this idea of absolute conceivability and can be seen as a constructivist view of intelligibility and rationality." 4. Ariew, Roger. 1992. "Descartes and Scholasticism: The Intellectual Background to Descartes' Thought." In The Cambridge Companion to Descartes, edited by Cottingham, John, 58-90. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Revised version in: R. Ariew, Descartes and the Last Scolastics, pp. 7-35. 5. ———. 1992. "Descartes and the Tree of Knowledge." Synthese no.
    [Show full text]
  • A Priori Volume 6
    A PRIORI The Brown Journal of Philosophy Volume 6 Brown University Department of Philosophy 2021 Editor-in-ChiefEric Choi ‘21 SeniorBen Zimmerman Managing Editor ‘23 A Priori: The Brown Journal of Philosophy is AnsonEditors Berns ‘23 Josiah Blackwell-Lipkind ‘21 made possible through the generosity of the Depart- Pahz Cherelin ‘24 ment of Philosophy at Brown University. The Journal Nico Gascon ‘23 Robin Hwang ‘23 would like to offer special thanks to Professor Paul Sophie Pollack-Milgate ‘23 Guyer, Katherine Scanga, and Elliot Negin ‘21 for their Adrian Oteiza ‘23 Ezequiel Vargas ‘22 indispensible contributions. Printed by IngramSpark [email protected] Copyright © by Eric Choi All rights reserved. This journal or any portion thereof may not be reproduced or used in any manner whatsoever without the express written permission of the editor-in-chief. A Priori A Priori Letter from the Editor Table of Contents Dear Reader, Social Explanation at the Macro and Micro Level: An Explanation of the Death of George Floyd 1 I once heard that Hegel wrote that philosophers are the civil James Ewing, Butler University ‘21 servants of humanity. I confess that like many others I find Philosophy it often (if not always!) difficult to understand what Hegel means, but after having read the papers for this year’s issue Truth on the Stand: I feel like I am a little closer to what Hegel was getting at. As I take it, philosophers are often in the business of producing Fragmented Consciousness crisis. They point out the problems that lie hidden in places & The Credible “Knower” 30 where we might not ordinarily take them to rest, sometimes Devon Bombassei, Emory University ‘21 much to our annoyance.
    [Show full text]
  • Averroes and the Philosophical Account of Prophecy Richard C
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2018 Averroes and the Philosophical Account of Prophecy Richard C. Taylor Marquette University, [email protected] Published version. Studia Graeco-Arabica, Vol 8 (2018): 287-304. Publisher link. © 2018 Pacini Editore. Used with permission. Averroes and the Philosophical Account of Prophecy Richard C. Taylor Abstract Prophecy is conspicuous by its complete absence from all three of the commentaries on De Anima by Averroes. However, prophecy and philosophical metaphysics are discussed by him in his Commentary on the Parva Naturalia, a work written before his methodological work on philosophy and religion, the Faṣl al-maqāl, generally held to have been written ca. 1179-1180. The analyses and remarks of Averroes presented in that Commentary have been characterized by Herbert Davidson as “extremely radical” to the extent that “The term prophet would, on this reading, mean nothing more than the human author of Scripture; and the term revelation would mean a high level of philosophical knowledge”. In the present article I discuss Averroes on method in matters of religion and philosophy as well as prophecy in philosophically argumentative works and in dialectical works, with particular consideration of the reasoning of his Commentary on the Parva Naturalia. I conclude that Averroes found in philosophy and its sciences the most complete and precise truth content and highest levels of knowledge and understanding and from them constructed his worldview, while he found prophecy and religion to be like an Aristotelian practical science in that they concern good and right conduct in the achievement of an end attained in action, not truths to be known for their own sake.
    [Show full text]
  • Plotinus on the Objects of Thought
    Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 3-1991 Plotinus on the Objects of Thought Eyolfur Emilsson University of Oslo, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Emilsson, Eyolfur, "Plotinus on the Objects of Thought" (1991). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 182. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/182 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. ··*■ - ' » i L,íaas\ is$oí ^ STFSl Plotinus on the Objects of Thought One of the features by which Neoplatonism diverges from the doctrines of Plato as they are generally understood nowadays is in the Neoplatonic account of intellect and its relation to the ideas. The received view is that according to Plato the ideas, even if knowable by the intellect and in fact the proper objects of thought, exist independently of any mind, whether human or divine, that may contemplate them. The Neoplatonists, on the other hand, all believed that the realm of ideas is to be identified with a realm of a divine intellect, which hence not merely thinks about the ideas, but in some sense is the ideas.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mind's Interaction with the Laws of Physics and Cosmology
    The Mind’s Interaction with the Laws of Physics and Cosmology The Mind’s Interaction with the Laws of Physics and Cosmology By Jeffrey S Keen The Mind’s Interaction with the Laws of Physics and Cosmology By Jeffrey S Keen This book first published 2018 Cambridge Scholars Publishing Lady Stephenson Library, Newcastle upon Tyne, NE6 2PA, UK British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library Copyright © 2018 by Jeffrey S Keen All rights for this book reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the copyright owner. ISBN (10): 1-5275-1364-5 ISBN (13): 978-1-5275-1364-8 To Marilyn, Alexandra, Olivia, David, and Sophia CONTENTS About the Author ......................................................................................... x Acknowledgements .................................................................................... xi Preface ....................................................................................................... xii Chapter One ................................................................................................. 1 Introduction Chapter Two ................................................................................................ 6 The Importance of Geometry Chapter Three ...........................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Noetics Essay Take
    Spencer Burch Noetics is a fascinating field of science which is trying to prove ideas that seem like they could only be found in a science-fiction novel. What if there is actually some truth to these intangible ideas? Could these findings change our world completely? The Institute of Noetic Sciences raises three very perplexing situations and ideas: the mind-body dichotomy, the “observer effect” and the idea of “the mind’s eye.” The mind is something that has been studied millennia before we knew anything about the brain. Aristotle and Plato argued that the mind is independent of the physical brain while their contemporary, Parmenides, argues that the mind and body are one and the same. Can chemical reactions in the brain really give us the ability to remember people, objects, words, memories, etc. or is there something else going on? The “mind’s eye” is the concept that refers to people being able to vividly recall a situation in which it is almost like they are actually seeing this situation through their eyes. How can simple chemical reactions recreate such an image? What about the idea that a human only uses 10% of his brain? Do we as humans have 90% more potential? Or when we die, we lose a slight amount of weight that is thought to be our soul leaving our body? Noetics attempts to answer these kinds of questions and many similar ones. Noetic science (derived from the greek word nous, which does not have a direct translation into english but is closest in meaning to “mind”) is the study of human potential.
    [Show full text]