C. S. Lewis's Christian Apologetics

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

C. S. Lewis's Christian Apologetics C. S. Lewis’s Christian Apologetics Value Inquiry Book Series Founding Editor Robert Ginsberg Executive Editor Leonidas Donskis VOLUME 286 Philosophy and Religion Edited by Kenneth A. Bryson The titles published in this series are listed at brill.com/par C. S. Lewis’s Christian Apologetics Pro and Con Edited by Gregory Bassham LEIDEN | BOSTON Cover illustration: Morguefile. Library of Congress Control Number: 2015943879 This publication has been typeset in the multilingual “Brill” typeface. With over 5,100 characters covering Latin, ipa, Greek, and Cyrillic, this typeface is especially suitable for use in the humanities. For more information, please see www.brill.com/brill-typeface. issn 0929-8436 isbn 978-90-04-30125-2 (paperback) isbn 978-90-04-30165-8 (e-book) Copyright 2015 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands. Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Brill Hes & De Graaf, Brill Nijhoff, Brill Rodopi and Hotei Publishing. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, translated, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without prior written permission from the publisher. Authorization to photocopy items for internal or personal use is granted by Koninklijke Brill NV provided that the appropriate fees are paid directly to The Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Suite 910, Danvers, MA 01923, USA. Fees are subject to change. This book is printed on acid-free paper. Philosophy and Religion (PAR) Kenneth A. Bryson Editor Other Titles in PAR Alana M. Vincent. Jewish Thought, Utopia, and Revolution. 2014. VIBS 274 David C. Bellusci. Amor Dei in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries. 2013. VIBS 265 Jim Kanaris, Editor. Polyphonic Thinking and the Divine. 2013. VIBS 257 William Sweet and Hendrik Hart. Responses to the Enlightenment: An Exchange on Foundations, Faith, and Community. 2012. VIBS 241 Avi Sagi. Tradition vs Traditionalism: Contemporary Perspectives in Jewish Thought. Translated from Hebrew by Batya Stein. 2008. VIBS 197 Brendan Sweetman. The Vision of Gabriel Marcel: Epistemology, Human Person, the Transcendent. 2008. VIBS 193 Constantin V. Ponomareff and Kenneth A. Bryson. The Curve of the Sacred. 2006. VIBS 178 Deane-Peter Baker and Patrick Maxwell. Editors. Explorations in Contemporary Continental Philosophy of Religion. 2003. VIBS 143 Rem B. Edwards. What Caused the Big Bang? 2001. VIBS 115 Editorial Board of PAR Rod Nicholls (webmaster) Harriet E. Barber Deane-Peter Baker Stephen Clark Alana M. Vincent Gwen Griffith-Dickson G. Elijah Dann Jim Kanaris Russ Dumke William Sweet Carl Kalwaitis Pawel Kawalec Ruby Ramji Esther McIntosh Gregory MacLeod Ludwig Nagl To Alvin Plantinga, wisest and best of my official teachers CONTENTS EDITORIAL FOREWORD xii KENNETH A. BRYSON PREFACE xv INTRODUCTION: OXFORD'S BONNY APOLOGIST 1 GREGORY BASSHAM Part One: THE ARGUMENT FROM DESIRE ONE Pro: A Defense of C. S. Lewis’s Argument from Desire 27 PETER S. WILLIAMS TWO Con: Quenching the Argument from Desire 45 GREGORY BASSHAM THREE Reply to Gregory Bassham 57 PETER S. WILLIAMS FOUR Reply to Peter Williams 69 GREGORY BASSHAM Part Two: THE ARGUMENT FROM REASON FIVE Pro: The Argument from Reason Defended 75 VICTOR REPPERT SIX Con: Naturalism Undefeated 91 DAVID KYLE JOHNSON SEVEN Reply to David Kyle Johnson 105 VICTOR REPPERT EIGHT Reply to Victor Reppert 113 DAVID KYLE JOHNSON x Contents Part Three: THE MORAL ARGUMENT NINE Pro: The Moral Argument is Convincing 121 DAVID BAGGETT TEN Con: A Critique of the Moral Argument 141 ERIK J. WIELENBERG ELEVEN: Reply to Erik Wielenberg 153 DAVID BAGGETT TWELVE Reply to David Baggett 163 ERIK J. WIELENBERG Part Four: THE TRILEMMA ARGUMENT THIRTEEN Pro: A Defense of C. S. Lewis’s “Trilemma” 171 DONALD S. WILLIAMS FOURTEEN Con: Lewis’s Trilemma: Case Not Proven 191 ADAM BARKMAN FIFTEEN Reply to Adam Barkman 201 DONALD S. WILLIAMS SIXTEEN Reply to Donald Williams 205 ADAM BARKMAN Part Five: THE PROBLEM OF EVIL SEVENTEEN Pro: The Problem of Pain Defended 211 PHILIP TALLON EIGHTEEN Con: C. S. Lewis on Evil: At Best a Likely Story 227 DAVID L. O’HARA NINETEEN Reply to David L. O’Hara 237 PHILIP TALLON Contents xi TWENTY Reply to Philip Tallon 243 DAVID L. O’HARA WORKS CITED 249 THE CONTRIBUTORS 267 INDEX 269 EDITORIAL FOREWORD The work of C. S. Lewis is challenging because it contains several layers of complexity. The problem of the suffering of innocent victims is a case in point. Lewis’s approach to the problem of evil faces one of the central problems of Theodicy: how can we reconcile the existence of an unlimitedly powerful and perfectly good God with the suffering of innocent victims? At first brush, Lewis’s explanation in The Problem of Pain sounds overly simplistic. Human suffering is the result of the fall from God’s grace; no need for a forced choice between divine attributes. Once we decided to rely on self- will rather than on God’s will “we fell under the control of ordinary biochemical laws and suffered whatever the inter-workings of those laws might bring about in the way of pain, senility and death” (77). But Lewis raises the argument to a deeper level when he wonders why we presume to know how God thinks. We cannot be sure why God permits evil. We are familiar with the ways we cause suffering by disempowering the environment and other persons, but this behavior is at odds with God’s grace and forgiveness of sin. In my opinion, the deepest layer of Lewis’s apologetics surfaces in his humble recognition of the consequence of not knowing the ways of the divine mind. This is clearest in A Grief Observed as he attempts to make sense of the suffering and death of his wife. Why would a good and loving God permit this? We cannot presume to identify our experience of pain with the role God provides for pain in the lives of animals and humans. In final analysis, Lewis’s grief enables him to identify with Job’s mystical experience as Job presses God to explain the suffering of the innocent (himself). Lewis’s passionate reflection on the loss of his dear wife brings him to the same place; an existential place in subjectivity where he moves beyond intellectualization to recognize his own insignificance and necessary dependence on the Almighty. I am delighted to welcome Gregory Bassham’s volume on Lewis’s Christian Apologetics to the Philosophy and Religion family of scholarly books. This book is a great catch, not only for Rodopi-Brill, but for lovers of C. S. Lewis worldwide. Kenneth A. Bryson Editor PAR special series Value Inquiry Book Series PREFACE C. S. Lewis is unquestionably the most influential Christian apologist over the past century. It is therefore surprising that—with a few notable exceptions— his arguments for Christian belief have received so little sustained scholarly attention. This book seeks to fill that gap. Here five leading defenders of Lewis’s apologetics go head-to-head with five acute critics in a pro/con debate format that permits in-depth discussion of the relevant issues. Our aim has been to produce a book that examines Lewis’s main arguments for Christianity with depth and rigor but is also accessible to general readers. The result, we hope, is a book that gives readers a clearer understanding of Lewis’s arguments and permits them to draw their own informed conclusions about whether those arguments are properly convincing. In editing this book, I have accumulated many debts. I am grateful to Dave Baggett, Erik Wielenberg, and Adam Barkman for advice on how to structure the book; to the contributors for their patience, professionalism, and grace under fire (friendly and otherwise); to my colleague Bernard Prusak for judicious feedback on various parts of the manuscript; to Robert Arp and Ken Bryson for much helpful advice on formatting issues; and to my wife, Mia, for her love, support, and generous spirit over a long period as this volume took shape. The book is dedicated to Alvin Plantinga, with whom I had the great good fortune to study in graduate school. Al was more than just an extraordinary scholar and a gifted teacher; he was a delightful companion, a fountain of whimsical good humor, and a model of how the Christian intellectual life should be lived. No one has contributed more to the remarkable flowering of philosophy of religion and Christian philosophy over the past half-century than Al has. My debt to him, both personal and professional, is great. Gregory Bassham King’s College INTRODUCTION: OXFORD’S BONNY APOLOGIST Gregory Bassham C. S. Lewis (1898-1963) is the world’s best-known and most-admired Christian apologist. More than fifty years after his death, his books continue to sell in the millions, and countless readers around the globe have been influenced and inspired by his writings. In a 2004 Christianity Today survey, Lewis’s Mere Christianity (1952) was named the best religious book of the twentieth century. Yet, curiously, Lewis is not generally considered a major figure by academic theologians (MacSwain & Ward, 2010, pp. 1-2). There are very few books that discuss his religious writings with the scholarly depth and rigor they deserve (but cf. Purtill, 2004; Beversluis, 2007; Williams, 2013; Baggett, Habermas, and Walls, 2008). This book attempts to do just that. Lewis himself was not a professional theologian or philosopher, but a highly regarded professor of English at Oxford and Cambridge, specializing in medieval and Renaissance literature. After being an atheist for many years, Lewis converted to Christianity in his early thirties. Over a period of approximately two decades, Lewis published a series of widely-read works of Christian apologetics, including The Pilgrim’s Regress (1933), The Problem of Pain (1940), The Abolition of Man (1943), Miracles (1947), and Mere Christianity (1952).
Recommended publications
  • The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: a Version of the Argument from Reason
    University of Calgary PRISM: University of Calgary's Digital Repository Graduate Studies The Vault: Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2019-04-30 The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: A Version of the Argument from Reason Hawkes, Gordon Hawkes, G. (2019). The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: A Version of the Argument from Reason (Unpublished master's thesis). University of Calgary, Calgary, AB. http://hdl.handle.net/1880/110301 master thesis University of Calgary graduate students retain copyright ownership and moral rights for their thesis. You may use this material in any way that is permitted by the Copyright Act or through licensing that has been assigned to the document. For uses that are not allowable under copyright legislation or licensing, you are required to seek permission. Downloaded from PRISM: https://prism.ucalgary.ca UNIVERSITY OF CALGARY The Argument from Logical Principles Against Materialism: A Version of the Argument from Reason by Gordon Hawkes A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF GRADUATE STUDIES IN PARTIAL FULFILMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS GRADUATE PROGRAM IN PHILOSOPHY CALGARY, ALBERTA APRIL, 2019 © Gordon Hawkes 2019 i Abstract The argument from reason is the name given to a family of arguments against naturalism, materialism, or determinism, and often for theism or dualism. One version of the argument from reason is what Victor Reppert calls “the argument from the psychological relevance of logical laws,” or what I call “the argument from logical principles.” This argument has received little attention in the literature, despite being advanced by Victor Reppert, Karl Popper, and Thomas Nagel.
    [Show full text]
  • C.S. Lewis' Case Against Naturalism
    C.S. Lewis’ Case Against Naturalism Mechanism, like all materialist philosophies, breaks down on the problem of knowledge. If thought is the undesigned and irrelevant product of cerebral motions, what reason have we to trust it? C.S. Lewis 1 The man who represents all thought as an accident of environment is simply smashing and discrediting all his own thoughts – including that one. G.K. Chesterton 2 The subject to be explored in this chapter is a complex one, and one on which much more could be written than I am qualified to write. The issue is the rational value of a certain argument that Lewis presented against Naturalism. We shall refer to this argument as the argument from reason. 3 This argument became the centre of a fascinating debate between Lewis and another philosopher, G.E.M. Anscombe (1919- 2001). Many Lewis scholars have had something to say about this debate, but the majority have taken only a biographical interest in it, and have had little to say about the debate’s philosophical content. Indeed, it has been widely assumed, almost without discussion, that Anscombe conclusively refuted Lewis’ argument. 4 As we shall see, Lewis admitted that Anscombe had shown the argument must be either reformulated or abandoned. However, Lewis clearly held his argument to contain an important insight and subsequently rewrote the offending chapter of Miracles . While I am uncertain about the cogency of the argument from reason, it is not so easily rebutted as Anscombe and others seem to have supposed. The argument comes in a variety of forms, and each one highlights the existence of philosophical issues of great complexity.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophia Christi
    Phil. Christi 5.1.qxd 9/4/03 12:41 PM Page 1 VOLUME 5, NUMBER 1 2003 PHILOSOPHIA CHRISTI EDITOR’S INTRODUCTION CRAIG J. HAZEN 5 SYMPOSIUM ON THE ARGUMENT FROM REASON Several Formulations of the Argument from Reason VICTOR REPPERT 9 Several Unsuccessful Formulations of the Argument from Reason: A Response to Victor Reppert THEODORE M. DRANGE 35 What About a Sensible Naturalism? WILLIAM HASKER 53 Need Reasons Be Causes? KEITH PARSONS 63 Some Supernatural Reasons Why My Critics Are Wrong: A Reply to Drange, Parsons, and Hasker VICTOR REPPERT 77 ARTICLES ON REASON AND NATURE Correspondence Theories, Natural-Selective Truth, and Unsurmounted Skepticism DOUGLAS V. H ENRY 93 Is Methodological Naturalism Question-Begging? ROBERT A. LARMER 113 Alvin Plantinga’s Pox on Metaphysical Naturalism JAMES K. BEILBY 131 Beyond Skinnerian Creatures: A Defense of the Lewis and Plantinga Critiques of Evolutionary Naturalism ANGUS J. L. MENUGE 143 Does Evolutionary Science Rule out the Theistic God? The Johnson-Pennock Debate DAN D. CRAWFORD 167 ARTICLES Neo-Molinism and the Infinite Intelligence of God GREGORY A. BOYD 187 Open Theism and Middle Knowledge: An Appraisal of Gregory Boyd’s Neo-Molinism DAVID WERTHER 205 PHILOSOPHICAL NOTES On Behalf of a Suarezian Middle Knowledge DEAN A. KOWALSKI 219 Suarezian Middle Knowledge: A Response to Dean A. Kowalski CHARLES F. KIELKOPF 229 Phil. Christi 5.1.qxd 9/4/03 12:41 PM Page 2 Kielkopf’s Compromise: A Reply to Charles F. Kielkopf on Suarezian Middle Knowledge DEAN A. KOWALSKI 233 Counterfactuals and Evil: A Final Reply to R. Douglas Geivett WILLIAM HASKER 235 Free Will Defense: Do the Ends Justify the Means? TIMOTHY CHAMBERS 251 On Whether God Can Sin DAVID J.
    [Show full text]
  • Angus Menuge, AGENTS UNDER FIRE: MATERIALISM and the RATIONALITY of SCIENCE and Victor Reppert, C.S
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 26 Issue 3 Article 6 7-1-2009 Angus Menuge, AGENTS UNDER FIRE: MATERIALISM AND THE RATIONALITY OF SCIENCE and Victor Reppert, C.S. LEWIS'S DANGEROUS IDEA: IN DEFENSE OF THE ARGUMENT FROM REASON John M. DePoe James C. McGlothlin Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation DePoe, John M. and McGlothlin, James C. (2009) "Angus Menuge, AGENTS UNDER FIRE: MATERIALISM AND THE RATIONALITY OF SCIENCE and Victor Reppert, C.S. LEWIS'S DANGEROUS IDEA: IN DEFENSE OF THE ARGUMENT FROM REASON," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 26 : Iss. 3 , Article 6. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil200926318 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol26/iss3/6 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. BOOK REviEWS Agents Under Fire: Materialism and the Rationality of Science, by Angus Menuge. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 2004. Pp. 233. $37.50 (cloth). C. S. Lewis’s Dangerous Idea: In Defense of the Argument from Reason, by Victor Reppert. Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press, 2003. Pp. 132. $14.00 (paper). JOHN M. DePOE, University of Iowa, and JAMES C. McGLOTHLIN, Ohio State University Philosophical naturalism often threatens to eliminate theism as an unnec- essary and undesirable hypothesis.
    [Show full text]
  • CS Lewis and the Poverty of Naturalism
    Mere Economic Science: C. S. Lewis and the Poverty of Naturalism David J. Theroux Founder and President, The Independent Institute Independent Institute Working Paper Number 67 March 6, 2007 100 Swan Way, Oakland, CA 94621-1428 • 510-632-1366 • Fax: 510-568-6040 • Email: [email protected] • http://www.independent.org Mere Economic Science: C.S. Lewis and the Poverty of Naturalism Page 2 “Good is indeed something objective, and reason the organ whereby it is apprehended.” —C.S. Lewis1 “Religion without science is lame, but science without religion is blind.” —Albert Einstein For many years, much of the sciences, both natural and social (including economics), has been dominated by a naturalist (or modernist or structuralist) worldview that generally assumes that the universe and life are purposeless and that mankind is simply a more complex, material version of all else in the natural world. In other words, an individual human is viewed as no more and no less than a system of molecular processes determined by natural physical laws. In this system, all human endeavor and ideas are determined solely as the product of a mechanistic, causal process of physical events. The philosopher Dallas Willard describes naturalism as a form of monism: “It holds, in some order of interdependence, that reality, knowledge and method . are of only one basic kind. That is, there are not two radically different kinds of reality or knowledge or method. [Naturalism] is fundamentally opposed to Pluralism, and most importantly to Dualism as traditionally understood (Plato, Descartes, Kant).” True to this form of monism, “[t]he one type of reality admitted by it is that of the sense-perceptible world and its constituents.
    [Show full text]
  • The Abolition of Man in Retrospect Paul E
    Inklings Forever Volume 6 A Collection of Essays Presented at the Sixth Frances White Ewbank Colloquium on C.S. Lewis & Article 14 Friends 5-29-2008 The Abolition of Man in Retrospect Paul E. Michelson Huntington University Follow this and additional works at: https://pillars.taylor.edu/inklings_forever Part of the English Language and Literature Commons, History Commons, Philosophy Commons, and the Religion Commons Recommended Citation Michelson, Paul E. (2008) "The Abolition of Man in Retrospect," Inklings Forever: Vol. 6 , Article 14. Available at: https://pillars.taylor.edu/inklings_forever/vol6/iss1/14 This Essay is brought to you for free and open access by the Center for the Study of C.S. Lewis & Friends at Pillars at Taylor University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Inklings Forever by an authorized editor of Pillars at Taylor University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INKLINGS FOREVER, Volume VI A Collection of Essays Presented at the Sixth FRANCES WHITE EWBANK COLLOQUIUM on C.S. LEWIS & FRIENDS Taylor University 2008 Upland, Indiana The Abolition of Man 1943-2008 Paul E. Michelson Abstract: The paper reviews some of the principal contentions of C. S. Lewis's The Abolition of Man (1943) and assesses their status, relevance, and importance 65 years on. Michelson, Paul E. “The Abolition of Man 1943-2008.” Inklings Forever 6 (2008) www.taylor.edu/cslewis 2 The Abolition of Man 1943-2008 I. INTRODUCTORY Sixty-five years ago, in February of 1943, C. S. Lewis delivered the Riddell Memorial Lectures at King's College of the University of Durham under the title "The Abolition of Man." The aim of the Riddell lectureship was to explore the relationship between religion and contemporary thought.1 My purpose here is to assess in retrospect C.
    [Show full text]
  • QCI Interview: Dr. Victor Reppert on the "Argument from Reason"
    QCI Interview: Dr. Victor Reppert on the "Argument from Reason" Quality Christian Internet: Dr. Reppert, of what importance is the "Argument from Reason", in your opinion? Why should thinking Christians and non-Christians be interested in it? Dr. Victor Reppert: The Argument from Reason does two things. First of all, it challenges the primary paradigm that has stood in the philosophy of mind for many years, and that is the physicalist paradigm. If the Argument from Reason is correct, any attempt to provide a complete account of cognition in physicalist terms is bound to fail, because in the last analysis it will show that reasoning is really something other than reasoning, and is not caused in the way that reasoning must be caused if it is worthy of the name. [In other words,] I think that the physicalists, in using reason, presuppose it to be what common sense suggests that it is, and that requires that their thoughts be about something, that they be causally efficacious in virtue of their content, that it is possible to perceive logical relationships, and that the obtaining of those logical relationships has something to do with what beliefs they hold. With respect to some of their beliefs they must presuppose that they inferred them from others, especially given the importance of inference in science and philosophy. But in analyzing reason in terms of something nonrational (which is what they are committed to doing) they invariably end up changing the subject and talking about feedback loops, or inputs and outputs, and in one way or another the reality of reason gets hidden.
    [Show full text]
  • By John M. Depoe, Western Michigan University Substance Dualism Is Not
    “A Defense of Dualism” by John M. DePoe, Western Michigan University Substance dualism is not among the most popular theories of mind in contemporary philosophy. Although, a number of significant contemporary philosophers maintain that property dualism1 or substance dualism2 is true. In philosophy, however, truth is not decided by the popularity of a theory but by the arguments that support it. In this essay, I will attempt to provide arguments that support substance dualism. I will also consider counterarguments to dualism at the end of this essay. What do I mean by “dualism”? For my purposes, dualism is the theory that there are two separate classes of properties: material and immaterial. If these distinct properties are understood to have substantial, enduring existence, then the theory can be called substance dualism. Insofar as substance dualism relates to humans, it means that humans consist of two connected substances: the material body and the immaterial mind. The popular alternative to dualism is monism, the view that only material substances and properties exist.3 My case for dualism follows, to some degree, on the grounds that monism fails to account for all of the features of the mind. 1 For example, Thomas Nagel, What is it Like to be a Bat? Philosophical Review 83, no. 4 (1974): 435-50; Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity in Donald Davidson and Gilbert Harmon, eds ., Semantics of Natural Language (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1974), 253-355 and 763-69; Frank Jackson, Epiphenomenal Qualia, Philosophical Quarterly 32 (1982): 127-36; David Chalmers, The Conscious Mind (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996). 2 For example, W.
    [Show full text]
  • The Argument from Reason Defended
    Five PRO: THE ARGUMENT FROM REASON DEFENDED Victor Reppert Over the past century and a half, philosophical naturalism has certainly become more prevalent. It has been frequently hailed as the philosophical perspective that takes science more seriously than its rivals do. Its prevalence, it seems to me, is based to large extent on a certain mental picture. To use Daniel Dennett’s terminology, the idea is that science progresses by replacing skyhooks with cranes (Dennett, 1995, p. 73) Whereas a skyhook is a mind- first explanation, a crane is a bottom-up explanation that is, at its base, nonmental. Thus, rainbows were first thought to be the result of God’s telling Noah that he would not flood the earth anymore (a skyhook), but is now explained as the result of mindless light refraction (a crane). The greatest triumph of naturalistic explanation came with Darwin’s theory of evolution. There, in a domain in which nearly all educated people saw marks of intelligent design, Darwin was able to provide a bottom-up account of speciation through the trial and error of evolution by natural selection. Richard Dawkins famously said that while one could have been an atheist before Darwin, Darwin showed how to be an intellectually fulfilled atheist, freeing atheism from its most serious explanatory problem (Dawkins, 1986, p. 6). The successes of brain science and artificial intelligence show that our mental life can be fully treated in the same way. Instead of thinking of the mind as independent of matter, we can expect the mind to be explained as simply the activity of a part of the physical world we call the brain.
    [Show full text]
  • The Argument from Reason
    THE ARGUMENT FROM REASON John M. DePoe Why does reason exist? Where does the "furniture" (i.e., logic, propositions, modality, etc.) of rationality come from? These are strange questions, but they are important ones. We use reasoning all the time. We rely on logical principles every day for decisions ranging from the trivial to the momentous. What accounts for these fundamental concepts that we depend upon for our day-to-day living? Everyone agrees that Christian theism can readily account for these entities. Some Christians, however, claim that naturalism, the leading atheistic rival to theism, cannot account for the furniture of rationality. Indeed, they claim that the existence of rational thought as we know it is evidence for the existence of God. This is what is known as "the argument from reason." C. S. Lewis formulated one type of argument from reason in his book Miracles . In chapter three, Lewis states his cardinal difficulty with naturalism: All possible knowledge, then, depends on the validity of reasoning. If the feeling of certainty which we express by words like must be and therefore and since is a real perception of how things outside our own minds really "must" be, well and good. But if this certainty is merely a feeling in our own minds and not a genuine insight into realities beyond them--if it merely represents the way our minds happen to work, then we can have no knowledge. Lewis believes that naturalism cannot account for rationality. Lewis writes that naturalism "discredits our processes of reasoning or at least reduces their credit to such a humble level that it can no longer support Naturalism itself." Keep in mind that naturalism is a worldview that requires all existing entities to be physical entities or reducible to entities in the physical world.
    [Show full text]
  • Changing Models of the Universe and CS Lewis's Defence of Truth And
    ResearchOnline@JCU This file is part of the following work: Adam, Brenda (2016) Cosmic warfare: changing models of the universe and C.S. Lewis's defence of truth and meaning. PhD thesis, James Cook University. Access to this file is available from: https://doi.org/10.4225/28/5ab33140faf9b The author has certified to JCU that they have made a reasonable effort to gain permission and acknowledge the owner of any third party copyright material included in this document. If you believe that this is not the case, please email [email protected] Cosmic Warfare: Changing Models of the Universe and C.S. Lewis’s Defence of Truth and Meaning Thesis submitted by Brenda Adam BA (Hons) in November 2016 for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the College of Arts, Society and Education James Cook University i Abstract C.S. Lewis’s interests and arguments range widely across the arts and the sciences. He noted the transience of models of the universe and described them as representations of current knowledge; composites of science, philosophy, theology and culture. He observed how they communicate meaning and influence popular thinking, and used them as a backdrop to his art. This thesis is an analytical and interpretive reading of his worldview expressed in various genres. His fantasy stories are evidence of his claim that the imaginative man within him was older and more basic than the religious writer or critic. The research investigates his fusion of intellect and imagination for dialectic, aesthetic, ethical and spiritual ends, at a time of conflict and uncertainty.
    [Show full text]
  • The Argument from Reason
    6 The Argument from Reason VICTOR REPPERT Introduction In this chapter, I will be considering the argument from reason. The argument, as we shall see, takes a number of forms, but in all instances it attempts to show that the necessary conditions of logical and mathematical reasoning, which undergird the natural sciences as a human activity, require the rejection of all broadly materialist worldviews. I will begin by examining the nature of the argument, identifying the central characteristics of a mate- rialist worldview. In so doing, I will examine the general problem of materialism, and how the argument from reason points to a single aspect of a broader problem. Second, I will examine the argument’s history, including the famous Lewis–Anscombe controversy. In so doing, I will indicate how the argument from reason can surmount Anscombe’s objections. I will also explain the transcendental structure of the argument. Third, I will examine three subarguments: the argument from intentionality, the argument from mental causation, and the argument from the psychological relevance of logical laws, showing how these demon- strate serious and unsolved diffi culties for materialism. Finally, I will examine some popular objections and show that these objections do not refute the argument. The Nature of the Argument Materialistic and mentalist worldviews “In the beginning was the word.” Although this statement, in its context, is laden with Christological implications, we can also use this statement to illustrate a central feature of various worldviews, including Christian theism. The central idea is that fundamental to reality is that which is intelligible and rational.
    [Show full text]