PHAEDO, SOCRATES, and the CHRONOLOGY of the SPARTAN WAR with ELIS I. Why Phaedo?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

PHAEDO, SOCRATES, and the CHRONOLOGY of the SPARTAN WAR with ELIS I. Why Phaedo? Methexis Il (1989) p. ]·]8 PHAEDO, SOCRATES, AND THE CHRONOLOGY OF THE SPARTAN WAR WITH ELIS E. I. MCQUEEN·· C. J. ROWE I. Why Phaedo? The origin 01' this paper lies in an attempt to understand the rea­ son or reasons (if any) why Plato chose to cast Phaedo of Elis as narra­ tor for the dialogue which goes by his name, and which ends by describ­ ing Socratcs' death. There were evidently a number of people present on the occasion.' What special qualifications, thcn, did Phaedo have, which other potential narrators lacked? (Socrates was obviously not a candidate, nor was Plato hirnself, 2 whether or nut we are supposed to be1ieve Phaedo's hesitant re port that he was ill.) That Phaedo was a non-Athenian -and that his report of the proceedings takes place out­ side Athens·- 110 doubt helps to underline the implicit irony of the si­ tuation: the execution by the city of Athens of the very man who was in Plato's eycs its own best citizen. 3 But five other foreigners were also there. 4 It is of course quite possible that the choice of Phaedo was largcly random. It was, we might suppose. conveniently plausible to have Phae- I. Phac:du 591>-c. 2. [t was, ekarly, a matter ur dcliberall' policy on Plato's part not to appcar in propria persona in his dialogucs. One may spcculatc on his rl'asons; it will be sufficicnt in this contcxt to notice thc fact. 3. "That", "hacoo says in the last scntcncc of thc dialogue, "was the end of our compa· nion, a man· so \\'c should say ",ho was the best \\c knew of his generation, and the wisest tao, and the most jus!." 4. The Thcb,ms Simmias, Cebes, and Phaidondes, and Fuclides and Tcrpsion from Mega­ ra (Phaedo 59cl-2). It is 01' course by no means certain that thc list Phaedo gives is authentie -··and there arc certainly many other features of thc dialogue which are not. But a) Phaedo is allowed to stress thdt his list is complete (59c5-6); aild b) some 01' those listcd as present play no individual rol<' in thc dialogue, so that unless we can dctcct some hidden reason for Plato's mcntioning their names, it seems rcasonable to suppose that he rnentions them because they werc actually there. (The prisoll regime seems to havc beeil extremely lax by modern standards: Phaedo's description 01' the rcgular visits made by his friends make it seem less Iike a prison than a hospital. But of course Socrates' was not a custodial sentcnce.) do returning horne to Elis and stopping off on the way to give a full account of events to the philosophical community in Phlius -since (as Echecrates teils him and us) the town had recently been starved of news from Athens.s The explanation of this latter state of affairs was presu­ mably Phlius' involvement on the Spartan side in the Peloponnesian War and its aftermath: when Echecrates says that "no one much from Phlius gocs to Athens nowadays", that perhaps is an ironie reference to the situation a few years before, when Phliasians would have formed part of the Peloponnesian forces which regularly invaded Attica. But this then raises the question why Phaedo hirnself was in Athens in 399. At about this time there occurred a war betwecn Sparta and Elis, in which the Athenians themselves fought as allies of Sparta und er the terms of the treaty forced on them at the end of the Peloponnesian War. 6 How was it then that Phaedo -apparently an able-bodied man of 7 military age - should have found hirnself in a city wh ich was either still engaged,8 or had very recently been engaged, in open hostilities with his own mother-city?9 An answer is provided by Diogenes Laertius, who teils us that Phaedo was a prisoner-of-war who turned to philosophy after being 5. 57a·b. 6. Xcnophon, Hellenica" 2.20, Diodorus XIII 107,4. 7. In the dialogue as a wholc, he appears to speak and to bc tn:atcd oS an adult. He i, young enough for the 70 year·old Socratcs to play with his hair (89b): on the othcr hund hc refers to Simmias and Cebcs as Ileaniskoi (89a). K. von hitz, in Paul.1'· Wissowa, Vol. XIX 2. Stuttgart 1938, col. 1538, asserts on the contrary that Plato rcprescnts Phacdo us "ganz jung": he claims that this is consistent with the story (reported by Diogenc, lacrtius Mldothcrs: sec below) of Phacdo's bcing forced into prostitution in Athens in 400. which in his vic\\" Ilnplies that he must then have been between 16 and 18 years of age. But a) he does not dt'cumcnt his assertion about the Phaedo; b) it is an unsafe assumption that all male prostitutes were bel\veen 16 and 18 years old (see e.g. K. J. Dover, Creek Homosexuality, New York 1980, p. 86). The best solution may perhaps be a compromisc between the two views: see n. 65 below. (Another and quite different position is represented by H. Dörrie, Der Kleine Pauly, Vol. IV, Munich 1972, cols. 691-692, who says that Phaedo may have come ("in jungen Jahren") to Athens as early as 418. This is largely in consequence of this outright rejection of Diogenes' story: see nn. 13 and 62 below.) 8. Sec below for the various dates which have rccently bcen assigncd tu the war. 9. Jt is or course in prindple possiblc that Plato might have inventcd Phacdo's prcscncc. and eithcr ignored or failed to notice the chronological difficulty. He certainly ducs not alway, get things right: so for example, as has recently bcen shown, there is no possible dramatic date for the Phaedrus (M. C. Nussbaum, The Fragility of Goodness, Cambridgc 1986, p. ·212). But temporal loeation is actually im material to the discussion in the Phaedrus, whcreas the Phacdo centres around a historie event of great significancc, and in this case Plato seems Iikcly to have been more careful -unless he had some special reason fur introducing him. But as will becomc immediately apparent, if there is any sueh reason, it is in fact intimately connected with the Spartan·F.lean war. 2 .
Recommended publications
  • Biology and Philosophy. VII. Sokrates, the Demigod
    https://doi.org/10.31871/WJRR.9.1.9 World Journal of Research and Review (WJRR) ISSN:2455-3956, Volume-9, Issue-1, July 2019 Pages 26-30 Biology and Philosophy. VII. Sokrates, the Demigod Juan S. Gómez-Jeria His diverse pupils, though proclaiming themselves similarly Abstract—I use the cylinder-ladder model presented in the faithful, presented opposing images of him. And in each of previous paper of this series to present and defend the thesis them, legend and history are probably mixed. Some that Sokrates was placed in a step much higher than those that well-known biographic details follow. There is a certain were occupied by almost all mortals regarding the degree of perception of reality and that he could perfectly be situated in possibility that some facts are not exactly as they are told, the category of ‘demigod’ as defined in this paper. Plato´s even that some are just gossip, but that is not important in this Apology is considered the most probable and unique context. Sokratic-like text. Furthermore, I claim that Sokrates knew that he was (relatively) wiser than those around him due to its higher position on the cylinder-ladder. This last statement opens new questions about the response of the Pythia. Sokrates was clear that his discourse would be understood by his listeners accordingly to the place they occupied in the cylinder-ladder model. This is the reason because, after Sokrates death, so many different Socratic schools appeared. Finally, I firmly hold the idea that one day we will discover that our knowledge of Sokrates has not grown one iota since his death.
    [Show full text]
  • Faunal Remains
    This is a repository copy of Faunal remains. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/169068/ Version: Published Version Book Section: Halstead, P. orcid.org/0000-0002-3347-0637 (2020) Faunal remains. In: Wright, J.C. and Dabney, M.K., (eds.) The Mycenaean Settlement on Tsoungiza Hill. Nemea Valley Archaeological Project (III). American School of Classical Studies at Athens , Princeton, New Jersey , pp. 1077-1158. ISBN 9780876619247 Copyright © 2020 American School of Classical Studies at Athens, originally published in The Mycenaean Settlement on Tsoungiza Hill (Nemea Valley Archaeological Project III), by James C. Wright and Mary K. Dabney. This offprint is supplied for personal, noncommercial use only. Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Copyright © 2020 American School of Classical Studies at Athens, originally published in The Mycenaean Settlement on Tsoungiza Hill (Nemea Valley Archaeological Project III), by James C.
    [Show full text]
  • Index of Passages General Index
    BmLIOGRAPHY INDEX OF PASSAGES GENERAL INDEX BmLIOGRAPHY Allen, Reginald E., ed. 1965. Studies in Plato's Metaphysics. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. --- 1970. Plato's HEuthyphro' and the Earlier Theory ofForms. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. --- 1971. "Plato's Earlier Theory of Forms." In Vlastos (1971: 329-334). 1980. Socrates and Legal Obligation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. --- 1983. Plato's Parmenides. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. --- 1984. Euthyphro; Apology; Crito; Meno; Gorgias; Menexe1Uls. The Dialogues of Plato I. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. --- 1991. The Symposium. The Dialogues ofPlato II. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. Annas, Julia 1981. An Introduction to Plato's Republic. Oxford: Clarendon Press. -- 1992. "Plato the Sceptic." In Klagge and Smith (1992: 43-72). Arnim, H. von 1896. De Platonis Dialogis Quaestiones Chronologicae, Vorlesungsver- zeichnis der Universitiit Rostock fUr das W.-Semester 1896. Barnes, Jonathan 1991. "Socrates the Hedonist." In Boudouris (1991: 22-32). Beck, Robert H. 1985. "Plato's Views on Teaching." Educational Theory 35:2, 119-134. Benardete, S. 1991. The Rhetoric of Morality and Philosophy: Plato's Gorgias and Phaedrus. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Benson, Hugh H. 1987. "The Problem of the Elenchus Reconsidered." Ancient Philosophy 7,67-85. ---, ed. 1992. Essays on the Philosophy of Socrates. New York: Oxford University Press. Bernal, Martin 1987. Black Athena: The Afroasiatic Roots ofClassical Civilization. Vol. I: The Fabrication ofAncient Greece 1785-1985. London: Free Association Books. Beversluis, John 1993. "Vlastos's Quest for the Historical Socrates." Ancient Philosophy 13,293-312. Boudouris, K. 1., ed. 1991. The Philosophy ofSocrates. Athens: International Center for Greek Philosophy and Culture.
    [Show full text]
  • DL Socrates Handout
    ISSS Virtual Socrates Colloquium 2021 Afterlives of an Eminent Philosopher: Socrates in Diogenes Laertius Stephen White, University of Texas at Austin, 9 June 2021 I. Socrates in the Lives: philosophy’s genealogy and a founder’s legacy 1. Plan of the Lives B1. Origins: Thales, sages, Pherecydes Ionic branch from Thales in Books 2-7 B2. Anaximander, Anaximenes, Anaxagoras, Archelaus B2. Socrates: Socratics Xenophon, Aeschines Aristippus: Cyrenaics; Phaedo (Eretriacs); Euclides: Megarics Crito (4 sons), Simon, Glaucon, Simmias, Cebes B3. Plato: Academics & Peripatetics B4. Academics B5. Aristotle: Peripatetics B6. Antisthenes: Cynics B7. Zeno: Stoics Italic branch from Pherecydes in Books 8-10 B8. Pythagoras: Pythagoreans B9. Heraclitus; Eleatics, Atomists, Protagoras … Pyrrho: Pyrrhonists B10. Epicurus: Epicureans 2. Preview of Lives organized by teacher-student succession: Lives 1.13-15 φιλοσοφίας δὲ δύο γεγόνασιν ἀρχαί, (B2) ἥ τε ἀπὸ Ἀναξιµάνδρου καὶ (B8) ἡ ἀπὸ Πυθαγόρου· τοῦ µὲν Θαλοῦ διακηκοότος, Πυθαγόρου δὲ Φερεκύδης καθηγήσατο. καὶ ἐκαλεῖτο ἡ µὲν Ἰωνική, ὅτι Θαλῆς Ἴων ὤν, Μιλήσιος γάρ, καθηγήσατο Ἀναξιµάνδρου· ἡ δὲ Ἰταλικὴ ἀπὸ Πυθαγόρου, ὅτι τὰ πλεῖστα κατὰ τὴν Ἰταλίαν ἐφιλοσόφησε. [14] καταλήγει δὲ ἡ µὲν εἰς (B4) Κλειτόµαχον καὶ (B7) Χρύσιππον καὶ (B5) Θεόφραστον ἡ Ἰωνική· ἡ δὲ Ἰταλικὴ εἰς (B10) Ἐπίκουρον. (B2) Θαλοῦ µὲν γὰρ Ἀναξίµανδρος, οὗ Ἀναξιµένης, οὗ Ἀναξαγόρας, οὗ Ἀρχέλαος, οὗ Σωκράτης ὁ τὴν ἠθικὴν εἰσαγαγών· οὗ οἵ τε ἄλλοι Σωκρατικοὶ καὶ (B3) Πλάτων ὁ τὴν ἀρχαίαν Ἀκαδηµίαν συστησάµενος· (B4) οὗ Σπεύσιππος καὶ Ξενοκράτης, οὗ Πολέµων, οὗ Κράντωρ καὶ Κράτης, οὗ Ἀρκεσίλαος ὁ τὴν µέσην Ἀκαδηµίαν εἰσηγησάµενος· οὗ Λακύδης ὁ τὴν νέαν Ἀκαδηµίαν φιλοσοφήσας· οὗ Καρνεάδης, οὗ Κλειτόµαχος. καὶ ὧδε µὲν εἰς Κλειτόµαχον.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Phaedo Phil 310 – Syllabus
    Plato’s Phaedo phil 310 – Syllabus Instructor: Willie Costello Winter Quarter. Meetings on Wednesdays from 15:00 to 17:50 in Bldg 20Rm21g. Office hours on Tuesdays from 13:30 to 15:00 in Bldg 100 Rm 102m, or by appointment (email [email protected]). Course readings available from http://bit.ly/phaedobox. Course description This course is dedicated to a slow and close reading ofthe Phaedo. This dialogue, undoubtedly one of the greatest in Plato’s oeuvre, showcases the full range of his philosophical thought, touching on issues in ethics, epistemology, metaphysics, physics (or natural philosophy), psychology (in the literal sense of the word), philosophical methodology, and even the philosophy of language. The dialogue is also a literary masterpiece, featuring discussants with genuine personalities, a substantial frame dialogue which keeps reappearing throughout the work, various religious and cultic overtones, an evocative closing myth, and a final scene of as much pathos as any in Greek drama. On top of all this, the Phaedo is arguably the most “Platonic” of the dialogues; nowhere else in the corpus do we find as clear a statement of the theory of Forms and the immortality of the soul – the “twin pillars” of Platonism, as F. M. Cornford once called them. And yet, for all this, the Phaedo remains a perplexing work. For one thing, its arguments for the soul’s immortality are all generally thought to be failures; even some of the dialogue’s own participants remain not entirely convinced at the end. The basic conception of the soul on which it tacitly relies (viz., the conception of the soul as a simple particular substance) is not generally thought to be credible, either, and does not sit well with Plato’s tripartite analysis of the soul elsewhere (not to mention Aristotle’s subsequent hylomorphic analysis).
    [Show full text]
  • JOURNAL for the STUDY of Greek and LATIN
    International issue NO. 5 2018 JOURNAL FOR THE STUDY OF GREEK AND LATIN PHILOSOPHICAL TRADITIONS JOURNAL FOR THE STUDY OF GREEK AND LATIN PHILOSOPHICAL TRADITIONS Aither is the scientific, peer-reviewed electronic journal published by the Faculty of Arts at Palacký University Olomouc in association with Philosophical Institute of the Czech Academy of Sciences. It was established in the Department of Older Czech and European Philosophy – Institute of Philosophy in 2009. Aither publishes twice a year. Every fourth issue is international (papers appear mostly in English, but also in German and French). The journal is registered under ISSN 1803-7860. JOURNAL FOR THE STUDY OF GREEK AND LATIN PHILOSOPHICAL TRADITIONS CONTENT Eliška Fulínová 4 The Muses and Reflexive Nature of the World in Archaic Greek Thought Vojtěch Hladký 20 Transmigrating Soul Between the Presocratics and Plato Matúš Porubjak 50 Socrates as the Paradigmatic Figure of Practical Philosophy Pavol Labuda 66 Aristotle’s Theory of Language in the Light ofPhys. I.1 Maciej Smolak 78 Etymology and Meaning of προαίρεσις in Aristotle‘s Ethics Karel Šebela 98 Aristotle vs. Boole: A Case of the Universe of Discourse 4 ABSTRACT In Greek mythology, the Muses are not just The Muses and inspiring agents of poetical creation, but their role is first of all a cosmological one: Reflexive Nature their birth crowns the process of cosmogony, bringing the world into the manifestation. As we try to demonstrate primarily in the course of the World of Hesiod’s Theogony, the song of the Muses celebrates and thus manifests the cosmos in Archaic Greek or the world-order through its articulation by means of the musical speech.
    [Show full text]
  • Socrates (469-399 BC) John M
    From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Socrates (469-399 BC) John M. Cooper Biography Socrates, an Athenian Greek of the second half of the fifth century bc, wrote no philosophical works but was uniquely influential in the later history of philosophy. His philosophical interests were restricted to ethics and the conduct of life, topics which thereafter became central to philosophy. He discussed these in public places in Athens, sometimes with other prominent intellectuals or political leaders, sometimes with young men, who gathered round him in large numbers, and other admirers. Among these young men was Plato. Socrates’ philosophical ideas and – equally important for his philosophical influence – his personality and methods as a ‘teacher’ were handed on to posterity in the ‘dialogues’ that several of his friends wrote after his death, depicting such discussions. Only those of Xenophon (Memorabilia, Apology, Symposium) and the early dialogues of Plato survive (for example Euthyphro, Apology, Crito). Later Platonic dialogues such as Phaedo, Symposium and Republic do not present the historical Socrates’ ideas; the ‘Socrates’ appearing in them is a spokesman for Plato’s own ideas. Socrates’ discussions took the form of face-to-face interrogations of another person. Most often they concerned the nature of some moral virtue, such as courage or justice. Socrates asked what the respondent thought these qualities of mind and character amounted to, what their value was, how they were acquired. He would then test their ideas for logical consistency with other highly plausible general views about morality and goodness that the respondent also agreed to accept, once Socrates presented them.
    [Show full text]
  • Excavations at Phlius, 1924 the Prehistoric Deposits
    EXCAVATIONS AT PHLIUS, 1924 THE PREHISTORICDEPOSITS (PLATES 113-118) J N 1924 the AmericanSchool of ClassicalStudies undertooka test excavationat the site of ancient Phlius, which is situated in the Peloponnesos west of the site of ancient Nemea. Designed as a preliminary investigation prior to further excava- tions, the excavators sank numerous trenches on and around the hill which contains the acropolis of the ancient city. A large amount of material was recovered from the scattered trenches but it was never studied and only an abbreviated excavation report was published.' At the end of the season most of the finds from the excavation were packed in wooden boxes, without any preliminary washing, sorting or mending, and stored in the Old Museum at Old Corinth. They rested where they had been placed for forty years until they were unpacked and studied by this writer beginning in the summer of 1964.2 They were found to belong to practically all periods of Greek history, beginning with the Early Neolithic and extending to the Turkish. The boxes unfortunately yielded thoroughly mixed contents, due to the test nature of the excava- tion itself and the circumstances of storage where some mixing had occurred throtlglh collapses. The prehistoric material could, however, be readily identified and segre- gated for study and it is with this material that this article is concerned. A later article will treat a Votive Deposit datable to the seventh and sixth centuries B.C.which was also found on the site. THE EXCAVATION The site of Phlius is situated in a broad plain and consists of a long ridge, which extends westwards from the encircling hills, and the plain immediately around it on its north, south and west sides (Fig.
    [Show full text]
  • The Growth of Greek Cities in the First Millennium BC
    Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics The growth of Greek cities in the first millennium BC Version 1.0 December 2005 Ian Morris Stanford University Abstract: In this paper I trace the growth of the largest Greek cities from perhaps 1,000- 2,000 people at the beginning of the first millennium BC to 400,000-500,000 at the millennium’s end. I examine two frameworks for understanding this growth: Roland Fletcher’s discussion of the interaction and communication limits to growth and Max Weber’s ideal types of cities’ economic functions. I argue that while political power was never the only engine of urban growth in classical antiquity, it was always the most important motor. The size of the largest Greek cities was a function of the population they controlled, mechanisms of tax and rent, and transportation technology. © Ian Morris. [email protected] 1 The growth of Greek cities in the first millennium BC Ian Morris (Stanford) 1. Introduction Greece in 1000 BC was a world of villages. Most people lived in communities of just a few dozen souls; even the largest settlement, Athens (Figure 1), was probably just 3,000 to 4,000 strong. But at the millennium’s end, the Greek east Mediterranean boasted some of the largest cities in pre-industrial history. Alexandria, Antioch, and Seleucia-on-the- Tigris probably each had 250,000-500,000 inhabitants. Figure 1. Sites in the Aegean mentioned in this chapter In this chapter I discuss the size of Greek cities and the implications of their growth. I identify three major transitions: 2 Figure 2.
    [Show full text]
  • The Frame of the Phaedo Matthew Hiscock
    The Frame of the Phaedo Matthew Hiscock N THE 1990S Diskin Clay and William Johnson made a new case for the significance of the frame or dramatic setting, in Phlius and Athens, of the philosophical discussion repre- I 1 sented in the Phaedo. They showed that it is one of four “com- plex” frames in the Platonic corpus; that it prefigures and reflects aspects of the philosophical debate (so Clay); and (in Johnson’s case) that it marks a gap between the “actual experience of dia- lectic […] and our experience as readers,” a gap which figures the significant (for Plato/Socrates) gap “between the act of un- derstanding in the material world and the true Understanding of the Ideal world” (591).2 This, Johnson added, does not in- validate previous readings of the frame as a means to suggest temporal distance, to underline the fictive aspects of the Phaedo, or as an expression of Plato’s “playfulness”; but it makes them seem (at least) “unsatisfactory.”3 Since the turn of the century, there has been a turn to ritual. 1 Following Friedländer, D. Clay, “Plato’s First Words,” YCS 29 (1992) 113–129, at 119–120 n.16, notes that the frames of certain dialogues have been seen as integral to their ‘philosophy’ (i.e., as more than scene-setting) since at least the time of Proclus (fifth cent.). W. A. Johnson, “Dramatic Frame and Philosophic Idea in Plato,” AJP 119 (1998) 577–598. 2 The other “complex” frames are those of Symp., Prm., and Tht. For Clay, the frame anticipates the dialectic of opposites (but see n.24 below) and sets the scene for the claim that death is a purification and release from the contagion of the body.
    [Show full text]
  • The Twentieth Century Has Been So Begrudging to Timon of Phlius That He Could Be Forgiven for Identifying Himself with His Misanthropic Namesake
    68 TIMON OF PHLIUS: PYRRHONIST AND SATIRIST The twentieth century has been so begrudging to Timon of Phlius that he could be forgiven for identifying himself with his misanthropic namesake. About a hundred and fifty of his 'glanzenden Sillen' (the phrase is Wilamowitz's) survive, but in Albin Lesky's Geschichte der griechischen Literatur Timon gets only a third of the space devoted to Anaximander from whom we possess one possible sentence.' Serious work on Timon largely came to a stop with Hermann Diels who edited the fragments and testimonia in Poetarum philosophorum fragmenta (Berlin, 1901), a book which is as difficult to come by as the older and much fuller study of Timon by C. Wachsmuth in Sillographorum Graecorum reliquiae (Leipzig, 1885).2 In spite of his skilful parody of Homer and his Aristophanic versatility in language (some sixty neologisms, many of them comic formations, occur in the fragments),3 Timon has been ignored by those who give such generous attention to Hellenistic poetry. Many fragments raise at least one major textual difficulty. A new edition and literary study of the material is badly needed.4 This neglect of Timon is all the more surprising since his subject matter, the philosophy of Pyrrho, continues to attract considerable interest.5 Pyrrho wrote nothing, and no-one who studies Pyrrho can avoid Timon, whose summary of Pyrrho's views, as reported by Aristocles in Eusebius, is often taken as the starting point for discussion of early scepticism.6 The authors of two recent books on Greek scepticism, Charlotte Stough and Mario Dal Pra, have properly appreciated the unique importance of Timon's evidence for understanding Pyrrho;7 and Dal Pra follows his chapter on Pyrrho with a useful survey of Timon.
    [Show full text]
  • The Influence of the Platonic Dialogues on Stoic Ethics from Zeno to Panaetius of Rhodes1
    chapter 2 The Influence of the Platonic Dialogues on Stoic Ethics from Zeno to Panaetius of Rhodes1 Francesca Alesse In order to delineate and understand the reception of Plato’s thought and work in early and middle Stoicism, it is necessary to make two preliminary observations. The first is that Stoic philosophy is strongly anti-Platonic in its metaphysical, psychological and epistemological foundations. Stoicism puts forth a materialistic monism based upon the principle according to which the corporeal alone exists because it alone “acts and is acted upon”.2 Stoic ontology is monistic and materialistic, openly and explicitly opposed to the Platonic. As a consequence of this ontology, Stoicism considers the human soul, in all its cognitive and moral faculties, as corporeal,3 as well as the divinity itself.4 The divinity is defined as the active principle (poioun) that generates and per- vades nature, remaining immanently present in it for the whole duration of cosmic cycle.5 From the logical and epistemological viewpoint, Stoicism holds an empirical and sensualistic theory of truth that denies any kind of existence, separate or immanent, to universal notions, reducing them to mental entities (ennoemata).6 On the psychological and anthropological plane finally, early Stoicism holds a kind of psychological monism allowing for distinct psycho- logical and physical functions but no distinction between the rational and de- siring soul,7 regarding instead passion, initially considered a vice, as a mistaken 1 I sincerely wish to thank Harold Tarrant and François Renaud who have revised the first ver- sion of my contribution, and Danielle Layne for reviewing the final version.
    [Show full text]