Project Description

Xenotransplantation (in the following XTP), or animal-to-human transplantation involves the transplantation of animal organs, tissues or cells into humans. XTP is based on several medical and scientific developments, in particular: (a) progress in transgenics and immunology, which have made possible the production of genetically modified animal organs which are more compatible with the human immune system, and (b) improvements in regulating the human immune response.

XTP raises important ethical problems XTP, like many developments in modern science and technology, is associated with new risks (Bonß 1995) and raises a number of major ethical problems. Whilst XTP could help solve the shortage of organs from human donors and save the lives of many patients waiting for transplantation1, there is a serious risk that viruses which cause animal diseases might cross the species barrier and spread through human populations (Guenzburg/ Salmons 2000).

Ethical questions of XTP still to be resolved include:

1. Is it in principle acceptable for reasons of religious believe, cultural values and animal welfare to use animals to provide organs and tissues for transplantation into human beings?

2. Which animals could be used (primates or non-primates)?

3. Is it acceptable to save the life of an individual whilst putting at risk health care professionals, relatives and the general population?

4. Is it acceptable to restrict the individual freedom2 of xenograft recipients to protect public health?

5. Is it acceptable to neglect alternative approaches to solving the donor organ shortage3 and to invest limited research resources into a technology, the success of which is highly insecure?

Limited public awareness and debate on XTP in many European countries EU Member States vary considerably in the public awareness and discussion of XTP (Council of Europe 2000). While some countries have already set up expert commissions to investigate the problems of XTP and have started to issue related guidelines - e.g. for the UK (Advisory Group 1996), for the (Gezondheidsraad 1998) and for (Petermann/ Sauter 1999) - many other countries have yet to address XTP (Council of Europe 2000).

How can modern societies debate ethical problems of XTP? Apart from the lack of a well developed public debate on the ethical issues raised by XTP, a basic and still unresolved problem in many modern societies is: who can legitimately discuss

1 By the end of 1997 the waiting lists for transplantation in selected European countries totaled to: kidneys 30.392, heart 1.853, liver 1.755, lung 705, heart-lung 319, kidney and pancreas 267, pancreas 197. Numbers include: , , , Germany, , Luxembourg, , North-, , Slovenia, and UK (ETCO: 2000) 2 Proposed measures include e.g. long term or even lifelong monitoring and quarantine which might not only affect the patients but also their relatives and close contacts (Petermann/ Sauter 1999). 3 Alternatives involve measures to increase the numbers of human donors, prevention and improved therapy of diseases leading to organ failure, the development of artificial and bio-artificial organs and therapeutic cloning (Petermann/ Sauter 1999). and resolve ethical problems of science and technology? Is it sufficient to only include professional bio-ethicists or do we need a broader ethical debate, which also involves other actors in the field including the concerned public (c.f. e.g. Chadwick 1999). Furthermore, if a broad public discourse on the ethical problems of modern science and technology is both necessary and desirable, how can these questions be debated and resolved, and what decision- making procedures can legitimately be used to resolve ethical questions?

So far a number of approaches of Participatory Technology Assessment (PTA) (Hennen 1999, Joss 1999) such as citizen’s juries (Stewart et al. 1994) focus groups (Hörning 1999) and consensus conferences (Joss/ Durant 1995) have been applied to foster public discussion of emerging technologies.

It is the aim of this project to introduce and evaluate a well-established method for resolving ethical issues - the Neo Socratic Dialogue– into debates on technological risks in modern societies. The Neo Socratic Dialogue traces back to the Socratic Dialogue, which has been developed by Leonard Nelson in the 1920s (Nelson 1922, 1965).4

The problem of effective and legitimate resolution of the ethical problems raised by XTP is aggravated by the fact that the development of the technology is international in scope and likely to have a global impact. As a consequence, there is a strong case for common international standards and the harmonisation of European legislation and guidelines regulating the development of XTP.

Examining the barriers to developing a common European approach to XTP However, the harmonisation of ethical standards across Europe is impeded by national differences in the perception of the ethical foundations and implications of XTP. Survey data shows that citizens in different European countries vary considerably in their attitude towards XTP and the issues it raises (Ward 1997, Durant et al. 1998, Sanner 1998, Schlitt et al. 1999, Julvez et al. 1999). Furthermore, these surveys only describe differences and do not explain why these variations exist and how they are embedded in and framed by different cultures/discourses, regulatory regimes and socio-economic contexts. An understanding of these factors is therefore central to both the task of developing a common European policy on XTP, as well as defining the limits of any moves towards international harmonisation. It is another aim of this project is to explore these limits and examine how a common European position might be developed.

Objectives The proposed interdisciplinary project has the following interrelated objectives:

1. To raise public awareness of and to involve the public in selected EU-Member Countries into the debate of ethical questions of XTP. 2. To develop and evaluate by cross-country comparison a new mechanism of public debate to reflect the ethical foundations and consequences of XTP in three EU Member States. 3. The Neo Socratic Dialogue on XTP has the following goals: a. to raise awareness and sensitivity of actors in the field and the interested/concerned public for ethical problems of XTP b. to reflect the ethical basis and consequences of XTP (“ethical impact assessment”), c. to clarify responsibilities of researchers, policy makers, economic actors and citizens concerning ethical questions of XTP, d. to provide information for decision makers about the ethical basis and

4 For detailed description of the Neo Socratic Dialogue c.f. p. 15 and 12. consequences of XTP, e. to improve communicative patterns and capabilities of actors in the field to cope with ethical questions arising from modern science and technology, f. to create material for qualitative analysis of different cultural, regulative and socio- economic and contexts which affect attitudes towards XTP. XENO will use a broad spectrum of methods to evaluate whether the Neo Socratic Dialogue on XTP reached these goals.

State of the art and innovative aspects

Although state of the art and innovative aspects of the project are not explicitly mentioned in the Guide for Proposers they are nevertheless explicit evaluation criteria mentioned in the “eligibility and evaluation criteria”. Therefore the following section will describe the innovative aspects of XENO.

XENO is innovative in two aspects:

1. XENO will increase public debate on XTP and complement existing studies on XTP by focussing on the ethical aspects of XTP. Moreover, it will contribute to a timely debate on ethical issues of XTP and will broaden the debate to experts/stakeholders and laypersons.

2. XENO will contribute to the development of mechanisms of Participative Technology Assessment (PTA) by introducing a communication technique of social learning (Neo Socratic Dialogue), which is well tested in primary education, higher education, professional ethics and business consultancy. Furthermore XENO will contribute to fulfilling the present need research for comparative evaluation research in the area of PTA (in particular impact evaluation). The experiences gained in XENO can be transferred to public debate in other controversial technologies.

The following section will describe the innovative aspects of XENO in more detail:

Ad 1. Increasing and broadening public debate on ethical aspects of XTP

So far a number of international organisations (Council of Europe 1997 and 2000, OECD 1997, WHO 1998) and national bodies (Advisory Group 1996, Nuffield Council of Bioethics 1996, Gezondheidsraad 1998, Hüsing et al. 1998, Petermann/ Sauter 1999, Swedish Committee on Xenotransplantation 1999) have carried out Technology Assessment (TA) on XTP. In comparison to these research efforts XENO is innovative in the following respect: Increasing public debate on XTP In countries, which carried out TA on XTP, debate is often restricted to experts. Furthermore, many countries lack public awareness and debate on XTP (Council or Europe). XENO will help to increase public discussion of this important issue.

Focussing on ethical questions of XTP Existing national and international TA studies on XTP focussed primarily on technical questions (e.g. safety) of XTP and vary regarding the weight they gave to ethical questions. Some reports raised hardly any ethical questions and others treated them rather briefly. XENO will concentrate on ethical questions of XTP and in this way complement existing TA on XTP. Contributing to a timely debate on XTP In the past the ethical and legal problems raised by scientific and technical progress have often been addressed with considerable delay. Consequently, issues of social conflicts surrounding, for example, brain death (e.g. Hoff/ in der Schmitten 1995), prenatal diagnostics (e.g. Chadwick/ Levitt 1996) and reproductive medicine (e.g. Harris/ Holms 1998) have been left undecided for years. In contrast, the debate on XTP offers a realistic chance that different interest groups might discuss the possible consequences and risks of this technology at the same time as the technology’s medical and scientific development. A broad debate about the risks of XTP will create transparency and might help to prevent unfounded negative attitudes towards its application. Without open public debate, XTP as well as allo-transplantation might face serious problems created by a lack of public confidence. XENO will therefore support attempts to increase public awareness and involve the public in the XTP debate.

Broadening debate on XTP Most national and international TA studies on XTP focussed so far on classical TA, which strived for the improvement of decision-making by the production and provision of knowledge (Nuffield Council on Bioethics 1996, Council of Europe 1997 and 2000, OECD 1997, Gezondheidsraad 1998, WHO 1998, Petermann/ Sauter 1999, Swedish Committee on Xenotransplantation 1999). TA research in the last 15 years criticized this TA-approach as ineffective (e.g. Albaek 1995, Klüver et al. 2000), because it would simplify policy-making processes and overvalue the potential impact of TA on these processes. Policy-making does not follow rational choice but is a chaotic process (Cohen et al. 1972, March/ Olsen 1989) in which scientific knowledge is only one resource among others. As a consequence PTA advocates for broadening TA and to include the perspectives of experts/stakeholders as well as laypersons (Klüver 2000). This would improve the TA process on a cognitive5, normative6 and pragmatic level7.

In contrast to that, very few existing national and international TA studies on XTP have involved the public in any significant way. Some studies have attempted to involve public actors and Non Governmental Organisations (NGOs) (Nuffield Council on Bioethics 1996, Hüsing et al.: 1998), whilst others have involved members of Parliament or public committees (Swedish Committee on Xenotransplantation 1999, Advisory Group 1996). In summary, however, most studies rely completely on experts from science, medicine and government or are compiled by just one author (Council of Europe 1997, OECD 1997). In contrast, XENO, which can be regarded as a PTA project with focus on ethical questions will increase public involvement and broaden public XTP-debate by actively involving experts/stakeholders and laypersons in a series of dialogues.

Involving ethical actors into the debate on XTP Ethical questions relating to modern science and technology are not only within the competence and responsibilities of (bioethics) experts, but are the responsibility of people directly involved in relevant practical fields. We will call these groups “ethical actors”, i.e. professionals from research, medicine, nursing, social work, public administration, insurance companies and interest groups (including environmental as well as animal welfare groups), as well as patients and their relatives, who each will have to deal with the ethical questions raised by XTP in their everyday life (Chadwick 1999). XENO will broaden the debate on

5 PTA strives for completeness and balance in analysis by including the knowledge from those affected. 6 PTA strives for democratisation by involvement of those previously excluded from decision making. 7 PTA creates space for social learning. ethical questions of XTP by actively involving these ethical actors from the following groups: research8, industry, professional groups (e.g. surgeons, nurses), ministries, governmental bodies, NGOs (patient organizations, self help groups, religious groups, animal welfare and environmental groups), statutory health insurance and private insurance companies, media. Thus, unlike other forms of PTA the Neo Socratic Dialogue will not involve randomly selected laypersons. Instead, deliberately selected key (ethical) actors will be chosen to participate and will be encouraged to reflect on the ethical implications of XTP for their everyday life and work.

Ad 2. Developing a methodology for Participatory Technology Assessment of ethical questions raised by modern technologies

In the last 30 years a number of approaches of Participative Technology Assessment, (PTA) have been explored, such as citizens’ jury processes (Crosby 1996), citizens’ juries (Stewart et al. 1994), citizen panels (Hörning 1999) and consensus conferences (Joss/ Durant 1995). In comparison with these broadly similar approaches and the existing TA studies on XTP, XENO is innovative in the following respect:

Contributing to comparative evaluation of PTA PTA needs some kind of tested procedure to discuss ethical implications of XTP. Although a wealth of PTA have been carried out so far on various technologies in the USA and Europe9, at present comparative evaluation of PTA does hardly exist. A recent TSER-Project funded by the EU compared 16 PTA-projects in EU-Member-States (Klüver et al. 2000). However, these case studies used different PTA-methods at different points in time, in different institutional settings, on different technologies. XENO will contribute to the development of PTA methods because it will evaluate and compare the application of one and the same methodology (Neo Socratic Dialogue), at one and the same time, in different European countries, on one technology (XTP). At present there is a lack of evaluation data on the impact of PTA (Klüver et al. 2000). XENO will create such data, in particular by systematically interviewing participants before and after the NSD about their expectation and experiences. Furthermore XENO will document and analyse the “resonance” (c.f. p. 14) of the NSD in the public debate. Thus, comparative evaluation will assess the value of the Neo Socratic Dialogue for PTA in international perspective and its possible use in the debates surrounding other fields of technology.

8 e.g. researchers active in the development of XTP, virologists, immunologists, epidemiologists, economists, psychologists, sociologists 9 Including the scenario workshop approach used by European Commission, c.f. www.cordis.lu/easw.hoke.html Introducing a well tested communication technique into PTA Existing PTA often define the role and qualifications of the facilitator as well as the methodology of discussion between experts/stakeholders and laypersons only vaguely (Klüver et al. 2000). XENO introduces a communication methodology (Neo Socratic Dialogue) into PTA, which is well established and tested in primary education (Murris 2000, Krohn et al. 2000), higher education (Gronke/ Stary 1998), medicine (Birnbacher 1999), as well as business consultancy (Kessels 1996 and 1997, Gronke 2000). Furthermore, the formalized training and certification of facilitators of the Neo Socratic Dialogue assures that they have the necessary qualifications to moderate such a process (c.f. p. 14). XENO will investigate the possibilities of this method to discuss ethical questions of modern technology to underpin policy making. Emphasizing social learning Ethical questions of new technologies challenge our existing decision making mechanism. The questions in this context are not only: Who is going to decide? And: On which basis are we going to decide? But also: In which way can we debate these complex issues? Recent comparative research on PTA (Klüver et al. 2000) stressed the significance and potential of social learning processes of PTA. XENO stands in line with these efforts. The Neo Socratic Dialogue is a communicative method, which fosters social learning. XENO will create a discursive space where experts/stakeholders and laypersons will be able to reconcile conflicting claims and deliberate the ethical implications of XTP. The main emphasis of a Neo Socratic Dialogue is consensus building and the fostering of trust in an open and rational dialogue between ethical actors. Stimulating improvement of communicative patterns and abilities The proposed Neo Socratic Dialogue on XTP differs from other methods of PTA in its goals. Like other approaches, Neo Socratic Dialogue opens a discursive space that enables choice. The Neo Socratic Dialogue, however, is innovative in its attempt to engender an open ethical debate and to make ethical actors more aware of and sensitive to ethical questions of XTP as well as to improve their ability to cope with and to communicate these questions to other actors. References Advisory Group (1996): Animal Tissue into Humans. The Advisory Group on the Ethics of Xenotransplantation. Albaek, Erik (1995): Between knowledge and power: Utilisation of social science in public policy maing. In: Policy Sciences, Vol. 28, pp. 79-100. Beck U., Bonß, W. (1984): Soziologie und Modernisierung. Zur gesellschaftlichen Ortsbestimmung der Verwendungsforschung. In: Soziale Welt. Vol. 35, pp. 381-406. Birnbacher, D. (1982): Review of Heckmann. Das sokratische Gespräch. Erfahrungen in philosophischen Hochschulseminaren. Zeitschrift für Didaktik der Philosophie 4, pp. 43-45. Birnbacher, D. (1999): The Socratic method in teaching medical ethics: Potentials and limitations. In: Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 2. pp. 219-224. Bogner, A. (2000): Bioethik und Rassismus. Neugeborene und Koma-Patienten in der deutschen Euthanasie- Debatte. Argument. Hamburg. Bonß, W. (1995): Vom Risiko. Unsicherheit und Ungewißheit in der Moderne. Hamburger Ed., Hamburg. Bourdieu, P., Wacquant, L.J. (1992): An invitation to reflexive sociology. Chicago Ill. Chadwick, R. (1999): Professional Ethics. In: Craig, E. (Ed.): Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Routledge. Chadwick, R., Levitt, M. (1996): EUROSCREEN: Ethical And Philosophical Issues Of Genetic Screening In Europe, Journal of the Royal College of Physicians of London, (1996) 30(1), pp.67-69. Coffman, K.L., Sher, L., Hoffmann, A. et al. (1998): Survey Results of Transplant Patients' Attitudes on Xenografting. Psychosomatics, 39(4), July-August, 1998, pp 379-383. Cohen, M.D., March, J.G., Olsen, J.P. (1972): A garbage can model of organisational choice. In: Administrative Science Quarterly, Vol. 17 pp. 1-25 Commission of the European Communities (14.4.1998): Draft Communication from the Commission to the Council, the European Parliament, the Economic and Social Committee of the Regions on the development of public health policy in the European Community. Commission of the European Communities (without date): Industrial Policy Criteria for the Evaluation of Theme 1 Research Projects. Commission of the European Communities (without date): SANCO: Health and Consumer Protection. Council of Europe (1997): Xenotransplantation – State of the Art, Strassbourg. Council of Europe (2000): Report of the Working Party on Xenotransplantation (CDBI/CDSP-XENO), Strassbourg, Juy, 7th 2000. Crosby, N. (1996): Creating an Authentic Voice of People, Jefferson Center, Minneapolis, MN. Draft Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union, Brussels, 28. September 2000, Charte 4487/00. Durant, J., Bauer, M., Gaskell, G. (Eds.) (1998): Biotechnology in the Public Sphere. A European Sourcebook. Appendix 2. Eurobarometer 1996 survey results. London. ETCO (2000): Downloaded from www.etco.org/data/statistics/CouncilEurope/waiting_list.htm. on 27.8.2000. Geertz, C. (1975): The Interpretation of Culture, Cambridge. Geertz, C. (1995): After the fact: two countries, four decades, one anthropologist. Cambridge, Mass. Gezondheidsraad (1998): Xenotransplantatie. Gronke, H. (2000): Die „ökologische“ Krise und die Verantwortung gegenüber der Natur. Zu den Grundlagen einer ökologischen Wirtschaftsethik. In: Böhler, D. Stritzel, M. et al. (eds.): Zukunftsverantwortung in der Marktwirtschaft. Münster: LIT, pp. 159-193 Gronke, H., Stary, J. (1998): “Sapere aude!”. Das Neosokratische Gespräch als Chance für die universitäre Kommunikationskultur. In: Handbuch Hochschullehre, Informationen und Handreichungen aus der Praxis für die Hocschullehre, Losebalttsammlung, 19. Ergänzungslieferung, Kap. 2.11., bonn: Raabe, pp. 1 – 34. Guenzburg, W.H., Salmons, B. (2000): Xenotransplantation: is the risk of viral infection as great as we thought? In: Molecular Biology Today, May 2000 (Vol. 6) pp. 207-216. Harris, J., Holm, S. (Eds. 1998): The Future of Human Reproduction. Ethics, Choice and Regulation, Oxford. Health (1999): Survey on human organ donation and xenotransplantation. Downloaded from: www.hc- sc.gc.ca on 25.7.2000. Heckmann, G. (1993): Erfahrungen in philisophischen Hochschulseminaren. Herausgegeben von der Philosophisch-Politischen Akademie. Dipa-Verlag, Frankfurt am Main. Hennen, L. (1999): Partizipation und Technikfolgenabschätzung. In: Bröchler, St., Simonis, G., Sundermann, K. (Hg.): Handbuch Technikfolgenabschätzung, edition Sigma, Berlin, pp. 565-573. Hoff, J., in der Schmitten, J. (Eds. 1995): Wann ist der Mensch tot? Organverpflanzung und „Hirntod“-Kriterium, Reinbeck. Hörning (1999): Citizens’ panel as a form of deliberative technology assessment. In: Science and Public Policy, Volume 26, number 5, October. Hüsing, B., Engels, Eve-Marie, Frick, Th., Menrad, K., Reiß, Th. (1998): Xenotransplantation. Technology Assessement, TA 30/1998. Schweizerischer Wissenschaftsrat, Program TA, Bern. Hüsing, B.; Engels, E.-M.; Gaisser, S.; Zimmer, R. (2001): Technologiefolgen-Abschätzung Zelluläre Xenotransplantation. Bern: Zentrum für Technologiefolgen-Abschätzung beim Schweizerischen Wissenschafts- und Technologierat (in preparation) Hüsing, Bärbel; Schicktanz, Silke (2000): Bestandsaufnahme von aktuellen FuE-Aktivitäten und -Trends auf dem Gebiet der Xenotransplantation von Organen. Karlsruhe : ISI, 2000, 121 S. Joss, S. (1999): Public participation in science and technology policy – and decision making – ephemeral phenomenon or lasting change. In: Science and Public Policy, Volume 26, number 5, October (pp. 290-294). Joss, S., Durant, J. (Eds. 1995): Public Participation in Science: The Role of Consensus Conferences in Europe, Science Museum, London. Julvez, J., Tuppin, P., Cohen, S. (1999): Survey in France of responses to xenotransplantation. Lancet, Feb 27, 353, 1999, p 726 Kessels, J. (1996): The Socratic dialogue as a method of organizational learning. Dialogue and Universalism, VI, 5-6, 53-67. Kessels, J. (1997): Socrates op de markt. Filosofie in bedrijf. Boom, Meppel/Amsterdam Kleinknecht, R. (1989): Wissenschaftliche Philosophie, philosophisches Wissen und Philosophieunterricht. In: Zeitschrift für Didaktik der Philosophie 11, (pp. 18-31). Klüver, L., Nentwich, M., Peissl, W., Torgersen, H., Gloede, F, Hennen, L., van Eijndhoven, J., van Est, J., Joss, S., Belucci, S., Bütschi, D. (2000): European Participatory Technology Assessment. Participatory Methods in Technology Assessment and Technology Decision-Making. Report to the European Commission, downloaded from www.tekno.dk/europta in January 2001. Krohn, D., Neißer, B., Walter, N. (Eds.) (2000): Das Sokratische Gespräch im Unterricht. Sokratisches Philosophieren. Schriftenreihe der Philosophisch-Politischen Akademie. Band VIII, dipa-Verlag, Frankfurt am Main. Latour, B. (1987): Science in Action, Milton Keynes. Law, J., Callon, M. (1988): Engineering and Sociology in a Military Aircraft Project: A Network Analysis of Technological Change. In: Social Problems, Vol. 35 No. 3, June, pp. 284-297. Littig, B. (1999): "Die Analyse von (Fall-)Beispielen. Gemeinsamkeiten und Unterschiede zwischen sokratischer Methode und interpretativ-hermeneutischen Verfahren der qualitativen Sozialforschung", In: Krohn, D., Neißer, B., Walter, N. (Hrsg.): Schriftenreihe der Philosophisch-Politischen Akademie Hg. v., Band VI, S. 159-173 March, J.G., Olsen, J.P. (1989): Rediscovering Institutions. The Organisational Basis of Politics. New York. MacMillan. Mochacsi, P.J. (1997): 'Patients' attitudes to xenotransplantation. Lancet, April 5, 349, 1997, p. 1031 Muñoz-Ruiz (2000b): Biotecnología: algunas cuestiones éticas y sociales relacionadas con su desarrollo", Congreso Mundial de Bioética / World Conference on Bioethics, Gijón (España), 20-24 de junio, 2000. Muñoz-Ruiz, E. (1997): Ética de la investigación y el desarrollo", Seguridad Nuclear, nº5, p. 9-15 Muñoz-Ruiz, E. (2000a): "Ética y energía", Energía y Sociedad en el Siglo XXI, págs 79-101, Consejo de Seguridad Nuclear, Madrid, Murris, K. (2000): Can Children Do Philosophy? In: Journal of Philosophy of Education. Volume 34 Issue 2 (2000). pp 261-279. National Kidney Foundation (1998): Downloaded from www.kidney.org/general/news.anim2man.cfm on 25.7.2000. Nelson, L. (1965): The Socratic Method. In: L. Nelson: Socratic Method and Critical Philosophy. Selected Essays by Leonard Nelson. New York: Dover. (pp. 1-40). Original: Die sokratische Methode (1922). In: L. Nelson. Gesammelte Schriften, vol. 1, Hamburg: Meiner 1970, pp. 269-316. Nuffield Council on Bioethics (1996): Animal-to-Human Transplants: The Ethics of Xenotransplantation. OECD (1997): Advances in Transplantation Biotechnology and Animal to Human Organ Transplants (Xenotransplantation), Paris. Petermann, Th., Sauter, A. (1999): TA-Monitoring “Xenotransplantation”. TAB-Arbeitsbericht Nr. 64, Büro für Technikfolgen-Abschätzung beim Deutschen Bundestag. Sanner, M.A. (1998): Giving and taking - to whom and from whom? Peoples’ attitude towards transplantation of organs and tissues from different sources. Clin. Transplant, 12(6), December 1998, pp 530-7 Schlitt, H. et al. (1999): Attitudes of patients towards transplantation of xenogeneic organs'. Langenbecks Arch. Surg., 384, 1999, pp 384-391. Stewart, J., Kendall, E., Coote, A. et al. (1994): Citizens’ Juries, Institute for Public Policy Research, London. Swedish Committee on Xenotransplantation (1999): From One species to another – transplantation from animals to humans. Swedish Government Official Report No. 1999: 120, Ministry of Health and Social Affairs, Stockholm. The challenges of biotechnology. General Report, (presented to the European Parliament), Fundación CEFI, 1997. Ward, E. (1997): Attitudes to Xenotransplantation, Lancet, Jun 14, 349, 1997, p 1775 Weierstraß K. (1967): Über die sokratische Lehrmethode und deren Anwendbarkeit beim Schulunterrichte. In: Weierstraß: Mathematische Werke, vol. 3, Reprint, Hildesheim: Olms pp. 315-329. WHO (1998): Xenotransplantation: Guidance on Infectious Disease Prevention and Management, Geneve.