God and Morality Michael Lacewing from Objectivity to God Some

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

God and Morality Michael Lacewing from Objectivity to God Some [email protected] © Michael Lacewing God and morality Michael Lacewing From objectivity to God Some philosophers believe that morality is objective, and that this cannot be explained unless God exists. For example, in The Moral Argument for Christian Theism, H P Owen argues that the only way to explain how values can exist independently of us is if morality is about our relationship to God. First, moral demands seem impersonal, not deriving from any particular person or other, yet the ideas of obligation, duty, etc. suggest a personal constraint, while the idea of a moral command or law implies a commander or law giver. Who do we owe moral duties to? Why would we feel guilty or have a sense of responsibility about what we do unless we are responding to someone? Any attempt to explain these apparently ‘personal’ aspects of morality naturalistically, e.g. in terms of society, fails to account for the authority of morality. However, an explanation of morality in terms of God secures both authority and the personal nature of morality. Second, persons exert moral claims because they are persons. However, they couldn’t exert absolute claims, as it seems they do. People are are only finitely good, hence not (as Kant thought) of unconditional worth. If being good was the only thing that entitled them to be treated well, we could treat many people badly. Yet people have certain ‘rights’ independently of how good they. The respect we owe people as persons is, we rightly believe, distinct from that deserved by their goodness. It must therefore relate to something of absolute worth; God’s valuing of persons would explain this. Third, reverence of the moral law can’t be reverence of something impersonal. First, it doesn’t make sense to revere moral claims themselves. Yet, second, the moral law transcends human persons, so it isn’t reverence for them either. But we value the personal more highly than the impersonal. So for our reverence of the moral law to make sense it must have a personal source greater than human persons. Of course, these arguments can be responded to by invoking a Freudian notion of conscience (which would explain the personal nature of moral demands) and by arguments that undermine the claim that morality is objective. But I put those to one side for now, and turn instead to question whether it can be right to argue that morality is dependent on God. The Euthyphro dilemma A form of the problem was outlined by Plato in the Euthyphro. In his version, the question was ‘what is piety?’. Our variation is ‘what is good/right?’. If ‘X is right’ means ‘X is commanded by God’, then anything that God commanded would be right, and God’s commands would be morally arbitrary. There is nothing, no pre-existing values, that God is responding when God commands some action. God invents morality. This doesn’t seem right: it would not be right to slaughter innocent children even if God did command it. God’s commands don’t (generally) make an action right or wrong. On the other hand, if God commands certain actions because they are independently right, then morality is independent of God, and we must wonder what invoking God actually explains about morality. It would seem, then, that it is only right to obey God if God (and God’s commands) is good. But how are we to say God is good? The problem repeats itself. If God is the standard of goodness, then to say ‘God is good’ is just to assert a tautology, which tells us nothing substantial about God, goodness, or the sort of commands we might expect (God’s commands would be good by definition, no matter what those commands were). On the other hand, if ‘God is good’ is not a tautology, several problems arise. First, to understand it, we must have some independent understanding of goodness. Second, the only way we could come to know God is good is through God’s manifestations; but then, again, we must be able to realise that these are good. So (the standard of) goodness is independent of God. But then morality is surely founded on goodness, not God. Once again, moral values exist independently of God, and the puzzle of their personal nature returns. Owen tries to solve this conundrum by appealing to the idea that God is love. But we may then ask ‘is what is loving morally good’? If so, then isn’t morality still independent of God, as it is based on the value of love? This is a slippery argument, for one can respond that it is not the value of love, but of God’s love, that morality is responsive to. God’s will, then, is responsive to God’s love (that seems right!), but there is no further ground to morality than God’s love. This leaves the problem that God is good is a tautology, and the question of whether we have any independent standard by which to judge God’s love as truly loving. The ‘supernaturalistic’ fallacy The Euthyphro argument suggests that no fact, even the fact of being commanded or loved by God, is equivalent to the moral idea of being ‘good’ or what we ‘ought to do’. The philosopher G E Moore presented a general argument of this kind. His main argument for believing that it is a fallacy – a mistake – to identify goodness with any other property (though Moore focused on natural properties) has been called the ‘open question’ argument. If goodness just is what God commands, say, then it wouldn’t make sense to ask ‘Is it good to do what God commands?’ because this would be like asking ‘Is doing what God commands doing what God commands?’. This second question isn’t a real question (the answer has to be ‘yes’), but ‘Is it good to obey God’s commands?’ is a real question – the answer can logically be ‘yes’ or ‘no’. And so goodness cannot be the same as obeying God’s commands. Goodness cannot be any other property; it is just goodness. Recently, philosophers have argued that Moore’s argument doesn’t work. Here is a similar argument. ‘The property of being water cannot be any property in the world, such as the property of being H2O. If it was then the question ‘Is water H2O?’ would not make sense – it would be like asking ‘Is H2O H2O?’. But it does make sense. So water is a simple, unanalysable property.’ This is not right, as water just is H2O. The reason Moore’s argument doesn’t work is because it confuses concepts and properties. As we have just seen, two different concepts – water and H2O – can pick out the same property in the world. (You learned about water long before you knew it was H2O – during this time, you had the concept of water, but not the concept of H2O. So they are different concepts, but they both refer to the same thing.) Likewise, the concept ‘goodness’ is a different concept from ‘what God commands’, but perhaps they are exactly the same property in the world. They are just different ways of thinking of the same thing. What’s interesting about this response, one that Owen endorsed, though he didn’t formulate it in these terms, is that it accepts that moral ideas and language are autonomous – they aren’t dependent on ideas about God – but that morality, and the status of morality as objective, is dependent on God. Kant’s argument Kant presented quite a different argument from morality to God. He rejected the idea that morality is founded on God or God’s commands, instead claiming that morality is founded upon reason. (In Owen’s terms, Kant is good, therefore, at explaining the impersonal authority of morality, but not its personal nature.) However, Kant argued that we need the idea of God to make sense of our moral duty. Our duty is to seek the highest good, i.e. one in which moral laws are obeyed and people receive what they morally deserve. Our happiness is not the be all and end all of morality, but it is important. In the best possible situation, acting morally would make us happy; acting immorally would not. Obviously, that situation doesn’t exist; but could it possibly? The only way to make sense of the possibility of the highest good is to suppose there exists a supreme being capable of bringing nature (natural events, human happiness) into line with morality. If that alignment doesn’t happen in this life, then we may suppose it happens in the next. Kant does not intend this to be a proof of the existence of God. We should act morally whether or not the highest good is possible; but it becomes questionable how much sense it makes to strive after a goal that we do not think possible. So we need the idea of God to make sense of our practical lives. Since morality is founded on rationality, and God is necessary to make full sense (subjectively, practically) of morality, it is at least rational to believe in God. Kant’s first premise, however, is questionable: is it our duty to seek the highest good? If this is impossible, because God does not exist, then it would indeed seem irrational to pursue it. But this raises no difficulty for duty if we have no duty to pursue it. Perhaps our duty is to pursue as great a good as we can achieve, i.e.
Recommended publications
  • Chapter Two Religions and Ethical Value
    Chapter Two Religions and Ethical Value 57 2.1 Philosophy and Religious Belief Introduction What should be the role of philosophy with respect to religious belief? The question is hard to answer since people have different ideas as to what constitutes philosophy and religion. A traditional answer, however, is that philosophy can help us to see whether or not religious beliefs are worthy of acceptance'. The idea here is that philosophers can single oi;t particular religious beliefs and ask questions like Ts this belief rationally 4efensible?’ or ‘Can this belief be supported by argument or appeal to evidence?’ lying behind such questions is the assumption that religious beliefs ar^ either true or false and that their truth or falsity can be settled or discussed at an intellectual level. Is there any relationship between ethics and religion? Is there any substantially based objective ethical code or not? Does God exist? How about the view that God’s Will determines what is morally obligatory? To an outside observer, .these, debates, among.. Western philosophers, and theologians concerning the relationship between religion and morality may seem culture-bound. The emergence of ethics as a separate fieldl of inquiry, the effort to distinguish morality from religion, and the countervailing effort to reassert a place for religion in human life all arise from a very particular cultural and social context. Nevertheless, the fact that systematic thinking about ethics emerged in the West, and that it generated a series of divergent explorations of the relationship between religion and morality, does not mean that this thinking or aspects of these views have no validity across 58 cultural lines.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Religion
    Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Religion INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY: PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION BEAU BRANSON, MARCUS WILLIAM HUNT, TIMOTHY D KNEPPER, ROBERT SLOAN LEE, STEVEN STEYL, HANS VAN EYGHEN, BEAU BRANSON (BOOK EDITOR), AND CHRISTINA HENDRICKS (SERIES EDITOR) Rebus Community Introduction to Philosophy: Philosophy of Religion by Beau Branson, Marcus William Hunt, Timothy D Knepper, Robert Sloan Lee, Steven Steyl, Hans Van Eyghen, Beau Branson (Book Editor), and Christina Hendricks (Series Editor) is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, except where otherwise noted. DEDICATION To Roger Branson — the best dad I ever had. For all the sacrifices I know ouy made. And for all the ones I don’t. CONTENTS What is an Open Textbook? ix Christina Hendricks How to Access and Use the Books xi Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Series xiii Christina Hendricks Praise for the Book xvi Acknowledgements xviii Beau Branson and Christina Hendricks Introduction to the Book 1 Beau Branson 1. The Intertwining of Philosophy and Religion in the Western Tradition 7 Beau Branson 2. Reasons to Believe – Theoretical Arguments 18 Marcus William Hunt 3. Non-Standard Arguments for God’s Existence 30 Robert Sloan Lee 4. Reasons Not to Believe 49 Steven Steyl 5. Debunking Arguments against Theistic Belief 62 Hans Van Eyghen 6. From Philosophy of (Mono)theism to Philosophy of Religions 74 Timothy D Knepper Glossary 87 About the Contributors 91 Feedback and Suggestions 94 Adoption Form 95 Licensing and Attribution Information 96 Review Statement 98 Accessibility Assessment 99 Version History 101 WHAT IS AN OPEN TEXTBOOK? CHRISTINA HENDRICKS An open textbook is like a commercial textbook, except: (1) it is publicly available online free of charge (and at low-cost in print), and (2) it has an open license that allows others to reuse it, download and revise it, and redistribute it.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Heaven Is for Real John 14:1-3 / 10-28-20 / Wed I. Why
    1 HEAVEN IS FOR REAL JOHN 14:1-3 / 10-28-20 / WED I. WHY DON’T NON-RELIGIOUS PEOPLE BELIEVE HEAVEN IS REAL OR THERE IS AN AFTERLIFE? A. For us Baptists and other Christians the Bible is proof enough. But what about people who don’t accept our Bible? B. There are at least six non Biblical arguments for the existence of God, heaven and the afterlife. 1. The Argument From Design also called the “Teleological Argument”. 2. The Argument From Anthropology. 3. The Argument from Cause-Effect also called the “Cosmological Argument”. 4. The Argument From Ontology. 5. The Argument From Morality . 6. Pascal’s Wager. II. WHAT DOES THE BIBLE TELL US ABOUT THE REALITY OF HEAVEN? A. There are many people who have said they had a “near-death” experiences then went on to write books and make movies about them. B. Although such movies tickle our curiosity, Billy Graham once said “GoD may give some people a glImpse of heaven, although I belIeve such Instances are rare and need to be treated with caution.” (Answers Dec. 6, 2012). C. Let’s consider 7 things the Bible says about heaven. 1. First, Jesus is in heaven right now—1 Peter 3:21-22. 2. Second, Jesus is preparing a place in heaven for Christians—John 14:2. 3. Third, there millions of angels in heaven—Heb. 12:22. 4. Fourth, our ultimate residence as Christians is to be heaven—Phil. 3:20-21. 5. Fifth, heaven is a place where there will be no more sorrow or pain—Rev.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 UNIT 1 INTRODUCTION to THEISM Contents 1.0 Objectives
    UNIT 1 INTRODUCTION TO THEISM Contents 1.0 Objectives 1.1 Introduction 1.2 Types of Theism 1.3 Kinds of Theism 1.4 Let Us Sum Up 1.5 Key Words 1.6 Further Readings and References 1.0 OBJECTIVES Is there a God? God is one or many? Do celestial beings (gods, angels, spirits, and demons) exist? Is there life after death? Is religion a need for modern human? If there is a God then why evil exists? Can man comprehend God? Can the human communicate with God? Does God answer prayers? There are many existential questions raised by humans in the realm of religion, spirituality and metaphysics. Theism is a philosophical ideology which answers the questions arose above in its affirmative. In simple words theism is an ideology that propagates belief in the existence of God or gods. The term ‘theism’ is synonymous to “having belief in God”. In the broadest sense, a theist is a person with the belief that at least one deity (God) exists. This God can be addressed as The Absolute, The Being, Ground of Being, The Ultimate, The World-Soul, the Supreme Good, The Truth, The First Cause, The Supreme Value, The Thing in Itself, The Mystery etc. Theism acknowledges that this god is a living being having personality, will and emotions. Theists believe in a personal God who is the creator and sustainer of life. The answers for the questions ‘Who is god?’ ‘What is god?’ are attempted by the theists. In discussing theism there arises another important question. It is like when was the human mind started to think about God? Many theistic theologians believe that “God consciousness” is innate in the human mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Creation: God Makes
    CREATION: GOD MAKES Mark Driscoll & Dr. Gerry Breshears CREATION: GOD MAKES In the beginning, God created the heavens and the earth. GENESIS 1:1 hen I was a little boy, before my four siblings were born, my Wdad worked out of town a lot. My parents were married at a young age, and birthed me when they were just over twenty years old. To pay the bills, my hardworking construction worker dad had to sometimes take some jobs out of town, sleep in his truck, and send the money to me and my mom. For fun, my mom would load me up in an old Chevy car and take me up to the mountains to explore God’s creation. She often told me, “Marky we need a Jeep.” Many years later, as we started to have five kids of our own, the seed planted in my imagination by my mom came to mind and so I bought a Jeep. Today, I am driving my second Jeep around Scottsdale, Arizona where we live and minister. During the winters, the weather is spectacular with big blue skies, warm sunny weather, and jaw dropping sunsets exploding with color. It is life-changing to have the top off the Jeep all winter to enjoy God’s creation, and take the Jeep up into the mountains to find hidden places of beauty that God created for us to explore and enjoy. Since moving to the desert, my life has drastically changed. For most of my life, I suffered from a bad case of Seasonal Affective Disorder (S.A.D.).
    [Show full text]
  • I. Richard Swinburne's Theism
    UNIVERSITY OF NAVARRA ECCLESIASTICAL FACULTY OF PHILOSOPHY Alex Mbonimpa The Providence of God according to Richard Swinburne: A Critical Study under the Guidance of St. Thomas Aquinas. Thesis for a Doctorate supervised by Prof. Dr. Rev. Enrique Moros Pamplona 2016 TABLE OF CONTENTS TABLE OF CONTENTS ....................................................... 5 INTRODUCTION ................................................................ 11 Method.............................................................................. 15 Biographical Note............................................................. 19 Acknowledgements .......................................................... 24 I. RICHARD SWINBURNE’S THEISM ............................ 27 1. Justification and Knowledge ............................................ 29 1.1 Subjective Justification ............................................. 30 1.2 Objective Justification .............................................. 32 1.3 The Quest for an Ultimate Explanation .................... 35 a) How Explanation Works ........................................ 37 b) The Truth of an Explanation .................................. 41 c) Candidates for an Ultimate Explanation ................ 46 1.4 The Justification of Theism ...................................... 47 a) The Simplicity of Theism....................................... 47 b) The Limit of Scientific Explanation ....................... 50 2. The Attributes of God....................................................... 53 2.1 What Swinburne
    [Show full text]
  • The Existence of God: a Debate
    Abilene Christian University Digital Commons @ ACU Stone-Campbell Books Stone-Campbell Resources 1948 The Existence of God: A Debate James D. Bales Woolsey Teller Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.acu.edu/crs_books Part of the Biblical Studies Commons, Christian Denominations and Sects Commons, and the Christianity Commons Recommended Citation Bales, James D. and Teller, Woolsey, "The Existence of God: A Debate" (1948). Stone-Campbell Books. 574. https://digitalcommons.acu.edu/crs_books/574 This Book is brought to you for free and open access by the Stone-Campbell Resources at Digital Commons @ ACU. It has been accepted for inclusion in Stone-Campbell Books by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons @ ACU. -1-ALES·TELLER ,DEBATE ' THE EXISTENCE OF GOO The Bible "Last we I paused beside 11 bl11ck.smith's door Ana ht11rd the 11nvil ring the vesper chime, Thtn looking in, I saw upon the floor Old h11mmers worn with beat­ ing ye11rs of time. " H<JW many anvils have you had," said I, "To we11r and batter all these hammers so?" "Just one," he said; thtn with 11 twinkling eye, "The 11nvil we11rs the h11mmers out you know." And so, I thought, tht anvil of God's word For ages skeptics blows h11ve be11t upon; Yet though the noise of fallinG bl<JWs was htard, The 11nvil is unharmed- tht h11mmers gone!" Millennial Harbinger The Old Paths Book Club is reprodm:ing Alexander Campbell's great paper, the Millennial Harbin­ ger, which was begun in 1830 and ran for many years. It is the finest repository of the Restoration litera­ ture, dealing with all the great que.
    [Show full text]
  • 174 David Baggett and Jerry L. Walls Good God: the Theistic
    Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 3 David Baggett and Jerry L. Walls Good God: The Theistic Foundations of Morality. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press 2011. 304 pages $99.00 (cloth ISBN 978–0–19–975180–8); $24.95 (paper ISBN 978–0– 19–975181–5) Authors David Baggett and Jerry Walls have two main goals in Good God: to defend a version of an argument for the existence of God from morality and to rebut objections to their argument based on the Euthyphro Dilemma. The authors expressly intend to carry out their discussion on these topics for a much wider audience than professional academics. The reason for this, they contend, is that their subject is “far too important to be confined to the relatively narrow circles of scholars and academics” (6). While this goal is perhaps commendable, readers will not get very far into Good God – perhaps to the application of Goldbach’s conjecture to conceivability limits (59–60) – without recognizing the benefits of some formal training in philosophy (and perhaps theology, for later chapters) for a full appreciation of the discussion. While the authors have made a laudable effort to restrict more complex philosophical discussion to appendices and footnotes, the best audience for this book is still probably upper-undergraduate or graduate students and professional academics. While the authors promise to present both an argument for the existence of God from morality and a defence of this position against Euthyphro Dilemma objections, only Chapter 1 of the book is devoted to the first objective. Chapters 2 through 7 are devoted to the latter goal, Chapter 8 to the problem of evil, and Chapters 9 and 10 address the application of their view of morality to issues in traditional Christian theology (e.g., how to know God’s will, the afterlife, the resurrection, the Incarnation, and the Trinity).
    [Show full text]
  • Morality and the Personhood of God: a Moral Argument for the Existence of a Personal God
    LIBERTY UNIVERSITY JOHN W. RAWLINGS SCHOOL OF DIVINITY MORALITY AND THE PERSONHOOD OF GOD: A MORAL ARGUMENT FOR THE EXISTENCE OF A PERSONAL GOD A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE JOHN W. RAWLINGS SCHOOL OF DIVIITY IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT FOR THE DEGREE DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY IN THEOLOGY AND APOLOGETICS BY STEPHEN S. JORDAN GOODE, VIRGINIA MARCH 26, 2021 Copyright © 2021 Stephen S. Jordan All Rights Reserved APPROVAL SHEET MORALITY AND THE PERSONHOOD OF GOD: A MORAL ARGUMENT FOR THE EXISTENCE OF A PERSONAL GOD Stephen S. Jordan Read and approved by: Chairperson: ____________________________________________ David Baggett, Ph.D. Reader: ____________________________________________ Marybeth Baggett, Ph.D. Reader: ____________________________________________ Ronnie Campbell, Ph.D. Date: March 26, 2021________________________________ DEDICATION To my beautiful bride, McKenzie, and our children. Without your love, prayers, and encouragement, this project would not have happened. Thank you for all of the ways that you have supported me throughout the PhD journey. Disney World, here we come! iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Not many worthwhile things are accomplished in life apart from the help of others, and a project such as a dissertation is certainly no exception. For this reason, I have several people that I would like to thank below. First, thank you to my Lord and Savior, Jesus Christ. Without Your transforming love, I would be lost and without hope. Second, I would like to thank my wife, McKenzie, for her encouragement to pursue a PhD, and for her unwavering support of my doctoral studies over the past six years. I have said it before, and I will say it again, apart from the grace that made my salvation possible, you are the most vivid representation of grace I have experienced this side of heaven.
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal for Philosophy of Religion
    EUROPEAN JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION Volume 2 Number 1 Spring 2010 ARTICLES Richard SWINBURNE God as the Simplest Explanation of the Universe 1 John HICK God and Christianity according to Swinburne 25 Timothy CHAPPELL Euthyphro’s “Dilemma”, Socrates’ Daimonion, and Plato’s God 39 Linda ZAGZEBSKI Th e Rule of St. Benedict and Modern Liberal Authority 65 Louis CARUANA Is Religion Undermined by Evolutionary Arguments? 85 Graham OPPY Epistemological Foundations for Koons’ Cosmological Argument? 107 Evan SANDSMARK & Jason L. MEGILL Cosmological Argument: A Pragmatic Defense 127 Michael TOOLEY Time, Truth, Actuality, and Causation: On the Impossibility of Divine Foreknowledge 143 MICHAEL ROTA Th e Eternity Solution to the Problem of Human Freedom and Divine Foreknowledge 165 DISCUSSIONS AND REPLIES Jerome GELLMAN On God, Suff ering, and Th eodical Individualism 187 Stephen MAITZEN On Gellman’s Attempted Rescue 193 Jacek WOJTYSIAK Morality, God, and Possible Worlds 199 BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES Volker Dieringer, Kant’s Solution to the Problem of Th eodicy. A Reconstruction Reviewed by Christian Hengstermann 209 Christian Kummer, Th e Case of Darwin. Th eory of Evolution versus Belief in Creation Reviewed by Jasmin Hassel 215 James Beilby. Naturalism Defeated? Essays on Plantinga´s Evolutionary Argument against Naturalism Reviewed by Oliver Wiertz 1 GOD AS THE SIMPLEST EXPLANATION OF THE UNIVERSE RICHARD SWINBURNE University of Oxford Abstract. Inanimate explanation is to be analysed in terms of substances having powers and liabilities to exercise their powers under certain conditions; while personal explanation is to be analysed in terms of persons, their beliefs, pow- ers, and purposes. A crucial criterion for an explanation being probably true is that it is (among explanations leading us to expect the data) the simplest one.
    [Show full text]
  • Problem of Evil 1 Problem of Evil
    Problem of evil 1 Problem of evil In the philosophy of religion, the problem of evil is the question of how to reconcile the existence of evil with that of a deity who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent (see theism).[1][2] An argument from evil attempts to show that the co-existence of evil and such a deity is unlikely or impossible, and attempts to show the contrary have been traditionally known as theodicies. There are a wide range of responses that have been given to the problem of evil. These include the explanation of evil as the result of free will misused by God's creatures, the view that our suffering is required for personal growth, the denial that God is omnipotent, omniscient, or omnibenevolent, and skepticism concerning the ability of humans to understand God's reasons for permitting the existence of evil. There are also many discussions of "evil" and associated "problems" in other philosophical fields, such as secular ethics,[3][4][5] and scientific disciplines such as evolutionary ethics.[6][7] But as usually understood, the "problem of evil" is posed in a theological context.[1][2] Detailed arguments Numerous different versions of the problem of evil have been formulated.[1][2][8] Logical problem of evil One example among many of a formulation of the problem of evil is often attributed to Epicurus[9] and may be schematized as follows: 1. If an all-powerful and perfectly good god exists, then evil does not. 2. There is evil in the world. 3. Therefore, an all-powerful and perfectly good god does not exist.
    [Show full text]
  • Who Is God? a Book You’Ll Actually Read Also Available in the Series
    Who Is God? A Book You’ll Actually Read Also available in the series: Church Leadership The Old Testament The New Testament Who Is God? Mark Driscoll Who Is God? Copyright © 2015 by Mark Driscoll All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopy, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher, except as provided for by USA copyright law. Scripture quotations are from The Holy Bible, English Standard Version®, copyright © 2001 by Crossway Bibles, a publishing ministry of Good News Publishers. Used by permission. All rights reserved. All emphases in Scripture quotations have been added by the author. ISBN: 978-1-942464-24-2 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Driscoll, Mark, 1970– Who is God? / Mark Driscoll. p. cm.— Includes bibliographical references (p.) 1. God (Christianity) 2. God. 3. Christianity and other religions. I. Title. II. Series. BT103.D75 2008 231—dc22 Contents Introduction 1. Knowledge about God 2. Perspectives about God 3. Nature of God 4. Incarnation of God 5. Worship of God Appendix: Books for Further Study Endnotes Introduction “In God we trust”—that’s what our money says. However, if you were to randomly ask the people handing their money to the checkout clerk in your local grocery store, “Who is God?” it is doubtful they would be able to clearly articulate who this God is. Our predicament is not unlike the experience of Paul when he walked into the great city of Athens only to discover that it was littered with memorials to an unknown god.1 We would say that they were very spiritual people.
    [Show full text]