Download Full Book

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Download Full Book Ideas about Substance Hammond, Albert L. Published by Johns Hopkins University Press Hammond, Albert L. Ideas about Substance. Johns Hopkins University Press, 1969. Project MUSE. doi:10.1353/book.72710. https://muse.jhu.edu/. For additional information about this book https://muse.jhu.edu/book/72710 [ Access provided at 2 Oct 2021 03:26 GMT with no institutional affiliation ] This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. HOPKINS OPEN PUBLISHING ENCORE EDITIONS Albert L. Hammond Ideas about Substance Open access edition supported by the National Endowment for the Humanities / Andrew W. Mellon Foundation Humanities Open Book Program. © 2019 Johns Hopkins University Press Published 2019 Johns Hopkins University Press 2715 North Charles Street Baltimore, Maryland 21218-4363 www.press.jhu.edu The text of this book is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International License: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. CC BY-NC-ND ISBN-13: 978-1-4214-3696-8 (open access) ISBN-10: 1-4214-3696-5 (open access) ISBN-13: 978-1-4214-3694-4 (pbk. : alk. paper) ISBN-10: 1-4214-3694-9 (pbk. : alk. paper) ISBN-13: 978-1-4214-3695-1 (electronic) ISBN-10: 1-4214-3695-7 (electronic) This page supersedes the copyright page included in the original publication of this work. IDEAS ABOUT SUBSTANCE SEMINARS IN THE HISTORY OF IDEAS Editorial Board George E. Owen Neville Dyson-Hudson George Boas Earl R. Wasserman Covenant: The History of a Biblical Idea Delbert R. Hillers Ideas About Substance Albert L. Hammond Vox Populi: Essays in the History of an Idea George Boas IDEAS ABOUT SUBSTANCE ALBERT L. HAMMOND � THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS • BALTIMORE COPYRIGHT @ 1969 BY THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS BALTIMORE, MARYLAND 21218 ALL RIGHTS RESERVED MANUFACTURED IN THE UNITED STATES OF AMERICA LIBRARY OF CONGRESS CATALOG CARD NUMBER 69-13537 STANDARD BOOK NUI\IBER 80 I 8-1012-4 ( CLOTHBOUND EDITION) STANDARD BOOK NUl\!BER 8018-1013-2 (PAPERBACK EDITION) ORIGINALLY PUBLISHED, 1969 JOHNS HOPKINS PAPERBACKS EDITION, 1969 To Virginia, without whom not Ill at press time, the author is especially grateful for the editorial help of his wife, Victor Lowe, Victoria Lincoln Lowe, John Young, and the Press. CONTENTS Publisher's Note, ix Preface, xi Chapter I. Pre-Socratic Pre-emptions, I Chapter II. Athenian Elaboration, 26 Chapter III. Cartesian Simples, 66 Chapter IV. The English Way of Ideas, 92 Chapter V. Phenomenalism and Postphenomenalism, 117 Index, 143 PUBLISHER'S NOTE The history of ideas as a form of scholarly inquiry took shape at The Johns Hopkins University in the first half of the century. The man chiefly responsible was Arthur 0. Lovejoy, whose twenty-eight years as professor of philosophy were spent promoting the historiography of the intellect. With two colleagues, George Boas and Gilbert Chinard, he founded the History of Ideas Club, where, in an atmosphere at once congenial and critical, visiting scholars might offer their interpretations of the development of the great ideas that have influenced civilization. Lovejoy was instrumental in founding the Journal of the History of Ideas in pursuit of the same end. And in his own writings he persistently and patiently charted the transformations which a seminal idea might undergo-over time, across disciplines, or within the intellectual development of an individual thinker. When, with Carnegie Corporation support, The Johns Hopkins University inaugurated an imaginatively new pro­ gram of adult education in 1962, it was a happy inspiration to build it around a set of graduate seminars in the history of ideas; for the History of Ideas Club itself had long before been described as "a sort of seminar where mature men and women learned new and valuable lessons." To be sure, this evening program has followed Lovejoy's spirit of inquiry rather than his own actual practice. Not all the seminars are concerned to pursue in detail the transformations of a single unit-idea. Rather, there is a shared view that no the­ ory-at any time, in any field-is simply self-generated, but that it springs by extension or opposition from earlier the­ ories advanced in the field, or is borrowed from theories in cognate fields, or is derived from the blending of hitherto X / PUBLISHER'S NOTE separate fields into one. To pursue the unfolding of any theory in these terms ( so the teachers in the seminars be­ lieve) allows a sophisticated and rigorous discussion of con­ temporary scholarship with an audience lacking previous specified knowledge. These notions are an extension, not an abuse, of Lovejoy's concern; he had never wasted effort on being unduly prescriptive except to call, hopefully, for cooperative scholarship in a venture so clearly beyond the reasonable capabilities of a single scholar. This series of books, Seminars in tlle History of Ideas, is intended to provide a wider audience with a chance to participate in "a sort of seminar" similar to those in the Uni­ versity's program. Just as the teaching seminars themselves draw on the spirit rather than merely the letter of Love­ joy's original enterprise, so this published series extends be­ yond those topics already offered in the University's program. But all, nonetheless, reflect that intent with which Lovejoy so long persisted in his own work: "the endeavor to investi­ gate the history, and thereby, it may be hoped, to understand better the nature, of the workings of the human mind." PREFACE The Animals They Come One By One During the long years the Yankees were winning the pennants I used to ask Yankee lovers, or occasionally a Yankee hater, what it was he supposed he was admiring or deploring. The owners changed, the front office changed, the ground crew changed, managers, coaches, and of course play­ ers came and went. What was it that always won? One answer, not as bad as some, was that the pinstripes stayed. Yes, and the pinstripes did something. But a day came when the pinstripes lay inert on the shoulders, and the Yankees were just another ball club. A more dangerous attack on man's reality was from the other side: not from the collection to which he belongs but from the ultimate very-little materials that are parts of him. This attack was classically mounted by Democritus: All is atoms in the void, plus their supervenient arrangements, ar­ rangements of which neither the atoms nor the void has any care, pride, or record. We escaped this through the sophistica­ tion of Athens, especially the sagacity of Aristotle. Aristotle, known for his doctrine that the soul is the "form" of the living thing, could take time to be derisive of Socrates' reincarnating soul; but he makes it clear that the soul must be the form of a living thing and that any mere arrangement of atoms ( which he calls the doctrine of Democ­ ritus) cannot be soul, life, knowledge, goodness, or indeed anything except a spatial arrangement of atoms. And Aris­ totle makes this emphatic in what I take to be a most au­ thoritative statement of his basic position ( Parts of Animals, Book I). xii / PREF ACE But that was 2,300 years ago, and since the dominance of modern mathematical physics the attack has been renewed, constant; and the defense has been unsure. The defense, as often in modern philosophy, also suffers a bit of odd con­ fusion when the old-time chief defender turns up somewhat ambiguously as an enemy agent or perhaps double-agent. For several generations there has been an easy fashion, coming chiefly I think from Bertrand Russell and "general seman­ tics," of referring to Aristotelian logic and the subject-predi­ cate proposition as a semeiotic excuse for our believing so obviously an unanalyzed familiarity as that the names of our children stand for continuingly real and separate persons. And, indeed, the subject-predicate Aristotelianism is also sometimes supposed to make us sure that when we have come into possession of a substantial subject we have some­ thing that cannot possibly change at all. I know Lord Russell has read Aristotle. But Lord Rus­ sell has a charming ability to read in a text, especially a great one, less and other than most of us. Some of the others, I often feel, are just using slogans. Aristotle there was. And he was a logician. So there is an Aristotelian logic. But I do not profess to know who now knows a very great deal about it. But Aristotle tells us a sub­ tance can be in the subject, cannot be predicated; and in the simplest sense is something like this man, or this horse. Its chief mark that it is a substance is that it can and does change. I think Aristotle is in danger of not being properly wary of the doctrine of the unchangingness of the predicate. This is Pythagoras, "the number theory of the idea," from which Aristotle dissociated himself in the Academy and of which he grew less wary once he was out of the controversy. Predicates as opposed to substances can be unchanging, and the glory of mathematical science probably rests on this. The number 2 PREF ACE / xiii is eternal and, with change for example, we can stipulate pre­ cision or set up a field-within-which so that what changes for Pythagoras is also changing for Robert Boyle or for Albert Einstein. Precision and abstraction are high mental abilities that we can, in the predicate, apply to the existent substances of the subject. (The common noun may do a similar trick in the subject.) But "I am tired" is a good subject-predicate proposition: and what is more changeable than the I or than the tiredness with which I am tired? That is a pleasant sen­ tence because when it is used the subject is necessarily a sub­ stance, the statement is true, and a somewhat different state­ ment is also being truthfully made: "I am at work." If I conclude, as I do, that the world is composed of substantial individuals, existing with the characters they actu­ ally have, with parts they actually have, and in the media of the relationships of time, space, and causal connections which they actually have, is it of great import where we allot the word "substance," as nearer part or whole? I am convinced it is.
Recommended publications
  • Who Was Protagoras? • Born in Abdêra, an Ionian Pólis in Thrace
    Recovering the wisdom of Protagoras from a reinterpretation of the Prometheia trilogy Prometheus (c.1933) by Paul Manship (1885-1966) By: Marty Sulek, Ph.D. Indiana University Lilly Family School of Philanthropy For: Workshop In Multidisciplinary Philanthropic Studies February 10, 2015 Composed for inclusion in a Festschrift in honour of Dr. Laurence Lampert, a Canadian philosopher and leading scholar in the field of Nietzsche studies, and a professor emeritus of Philosophy at IUPUI. Adult Content Warning • Nudity • Sex • Violence • And other inappropriate Prometheus Chained by Vulcan (1623) themes… by Dirck van Baburen (1595-1624) Nietzsche on Protagoras & the Sophists “The Greek culture of the Sophists had developed out of all the Greek instincts; it belongs to the culture of the Periclean age as necessarily as Plato does not: it has its predecessors in Heraclitus, in Democritus, in the scientific types of the old philosophy; it finds expression in, e.g., the high culture of Thucydides. And – it has ultimately shown itself to be right: every advance in epistemological and moral knowledge has reinstated the Sophists – Our contemporary way of thinking is to a great extent Heraclitean, Democritean, and Protagorean: it suffices to say it is Protagorean, because Protagoras represented a synthesis of Heraclitus and Democritus.” Nietzsche, The Will to Power, 2.428 Reappraisals of the authorship & dating of the Prometheia trilogy • Traditionally thought to have been composed by Aeschylus (c.525-c.456 BCE). • More recent scholarship has demonstrated the play to have been written by a later, lesser author sometime in the 430s. • This new dating raises many questions as to what contemporary events the trilogy may be referring.
    [Show full text]
  • The “Atomic Theory” of Leucippus, and Its Impact on Medicine Before Hippocrates
    Selected Brief Contribution The “atomic theory” of Leucippus, and its impact on medicine before Hippocrates Gregory Tsoucalas MD, MSc, MS(c), PhD, Konstantinos Laios PhD, Marianna Karamanou MD, MSc, PhD, George Androutsos MD History of Medicine Department, Medical School, University of Athens, Greece Gregory Tsoucalas, Kononos Str. 62-64, P.C. 11633, Pagrati, Athens, Greece. Mobile: 6945298205, Email: [email protected] Hell J Nucl Med 2013; 16(1): 68-69 Published on line: 10 April 2013 Leucippus, teacher of Democritus, was the first to describe Among Leucippus works stand the “Great Cosmology” (in the “atomic theory” in an attempt to explain the genesis of greek: Μέγας Διάκοσμος: About Great Cosmos) and On the the matter. Although only a fraction of his work was saved, Mind (in greek: Περί Νού). Of this second treatise, only one the “atom”, the smallest and indivisible particle of matter, but very significant fragment has survived, where we can enclosing a vacuum in which other particles move, still re- read: “nothing is in vain, but everything happens because mains the funtamental element of modern physics. of a reason and necessity”. This aphorism, not only encap- Leucippus (5th century BC, ca 430 BC) (Fig. 1), was born sulates the rationalism of the Ionian Greek School philoso- most probably in the city of Avdera, in Southern Thrace, phy, but also constitutes the basic axiom of ancient Greek Greece, where also Democritus was born. The island of Mi- medicine concerning the rational interpretation of diseases los, the Greek colony in Italy, Elea and the Greek city of Mile- and their therapy, which was later taught and described in tus in Asia Minor, were also mentioned as his birthplace [1- “Corpus Hippocraticum” [21].
    [Show full text]
  • The Mathematical Anti-Atomism of Plato's Timaeus
    The mathematical anti-atomism of Plato’s Timaeus Luc Brisson, Salomon Ofman To cite this version: Luc Brisson, Salomon Ofman. The mathematical anti-atomism of Plato’s Timaeus. Ancient Philoso- phy, Philosophy Documentation Center, In press. hal-02923266 HAL Id: hal-02923266 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-02923266 Submitted on 26 Aug 2020 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. The mathematical anti-atomism of Plato’s Timaeus Luc Brisson Salomon Ofman Centre Jean Pépin CNRS-Institut mathématique de Jussieu- CNRS-UMR 8230 Paris Rive Gauche École normale supérieure Sorbonne Université Paris Sciences Lettres Paris Université Abstract. In Plato’s eponymous dialogue, Timaeus, the main character presents the universe as an almost perfect sphere filled by tiny invisible particles having the form of four regular polyhedrons. At first glance, such a construction may seem close to an atomic theory. However, one does not find any text in Antiquity tying Timaeus’ cosmology to the atomists, and Aristotle made a clear distinction between Plato and the latter. Despite the cosmology in the Timaeus is so far apart from the one of the atomists, Plato is commonly presented in contemporary literature as some sort of atomist, sometimes as supporting a so-called form of ‘mathematical atomism’.
    [Show full text]
  • A Short History of Greek Mathematics
    Cambridge Library Co ll e C t i o n Books of enduring scholarly value Classics From the Renaissance to the nineteenth century, Latin and Greek were compulsory subjects in almost all European universities, and most early modern scholars published their research and conducted international correspondence in Latin. Latin had continued in use in Western Europe long after the fall of the Roman empire as the lingua franca of the educated classes and of law, diplomacy, religion and university teaching. The flight of Greek scholars to the West after the fall of Constantinople in 1453 gave impetus to the study of ancient Greek literature and the Greek New Testament. Eventually, just as nineteenth-century reforms of university curricula were beginning to erode this ascendancy, developments in textual criticism and linguistic analysis, and new ways of studying ancient societies, especially archaeology, led to renewed enthusiasm for the Classics. This collection offers works of criticism, interpretation and synthesis by the outstanding scholars of the nineteenth century. A Short History of Greek Mathematics James Gow’s Short History of Greek Mathematics (1884) provided the first full account of the subject available in English, and it today remains a clear and thorough guide to early arithmetic and geometry. Beginning with the origins of the numerical system and proceeding through the theorems of Pythagoras, Euclid, Archimedes and many others, the Short History offers in-depth analysis and useful translations of individual texts as well as a broad historical overview of the development of mathematics. Parts I and II concern Greek arithmetic, including the origin of alphabetic numerals and the nomenclature for operations; Part III constitutes a complete history of Greek geometry, from its earliest precursors in Egypt and Babylon through to the innovations of the Ionic, Sophistic, and Academic schools and their followers.
    [Show full text]
  • The Origin of Life:Ahistory of Ancient Greek Theories
    Curriculum Units by Fellows of the Yale-New Haven Teachers Institute 1980 Volume V: Man and the Environment The Origin of Life:Ahistory of Ancient Greek Theories Curriculum Unit 80.05.11 by Joyce Puglia This unit presents a history of scientific thought relating to the origin of life as explained mainly by early Greek scientific philosophers. The unit begins with Greek science during the eighth century B.C. and proceeds quickly into the seventh century B.C., concluding with the fourth century B.C. Since the scope is limited to this time period the unit will end with information that is presently, for the most part, outdated. The teacher must constantly remind the students of this fact. The purpose of this unit is not to impart scientific knowledge for its own sake. Rather, it is to show how scientific thinkers came to their conclusions based upon how science was viewed in the scheme of history. There are various high school courses taught, yet no specific course has been designed to relate the development of the academic disciplines to each other. Many science textbooks include the names of scientists who contributed valuable information upon which specific ideas were developed. Yet, most textbooks provide a minimum amount of information relating to the scientists themselves. It is my feeling that students will better understand the development of scientific thought if an opportunity can be provided in which a connection can be made between science and history. There are four general objectives for this unit. Upon completing the unit students will: 1. be familiar with the ideas of early scientific minds, 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Democritus and Protagoras
    “Man is the measure of cosmos” Democritus and Protagoras: Values and Beliefs on Naturalism By Anastasia Theologou Submitted to Central European University Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts Supervisor: Istvan Bodnar CEU eTD Collection Budapest, Hungary 2015 Table of contents ABSTRACT ....................................................................................................................................... iii ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS ................................................................................................................ iv Introduction .......................................................................................................................................... 1 1. Democritus’ philosophy in Diodorus Siculus .......................................................................... 4 1.1. Democritus’ cosmogony ................................................................................................. 6 1.2. The primary state of human beings ................................................................................. 8 1.3. Living the bestial life .................................................................................................... 10 1.4. Fear................................................................................................................................ 10 1.5. Language ....................................................................................................................... 11
    [Show full text]
  • Diogenes Laërtius: a Moderate Skeptic in the History of Philosophy (Book IX)∗
    Philosophy Study, April 2021, Vol. 11, No. 4, 293-302 doi: 10.17265/2159-5313/2021.04.005 D D AV I D PUBLISHING Diogenes Laërtius: A Moderate Skeptic in the History of Philosophy (Book IX)∗ Ramón Román-Alcalá University of Córdoba, Córdoba, Spain This paper presents the keys and reasons for Diogenes Laërtius’ alleged scepticism, based on an analysis of the general design of his work The Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers. I believe that it would be manifestly erroneous to seek confirmation of this scepticism solely in Book IX without taking into account the overall structure of the work. A convincing explanation is also provided of one of the most enigmatic and most studied phrases in this work. What did Diogenes mean when he said that Apollonides of Nicaea was ὁ παρ’ ἡμῶν (“one of us”)? Keywords: scepticism, Diogenes Laërtius, sextus, Pyrrho, The Lives of Philosophers The Singular Book IX of “The Lives” Diogenes Laërtius’ work Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers was already relatively well-known in antiquity, due not only to the author’s popularity but also to the singularity of the work, in which he had succeeded in faithfully characterising much of ancient historiography. Moreover, and this is important to highlight in our introduction, taking into account the structure of many of the books and sources mentioned by Diogenes, this work began a new and highly original historiographic genre, which could be called “successions”. Diogenes’ Lives of Philosophers is a singular work. It starts with an introduction focusing on the origins of philosophy (which were undoubtedly Greek), the different classifications of philosophy and philosophers.
    [Show full text]
  • Everything Flows Πάντα Ῥει̃: Antony N
    | DOI: 10.3933/APPLRHEOL-24-52918 | WWW.APPLIEDRHEOLOGY.ORG Everything Flows πάντα ῥει̃: Antony N. Beris1, A. Jeffrey Giacomin2* 1 Department of Chemical and Biomolecular Engineering, University of Delaware, Newark, DE 19716, USA 2 Chemical Engineering Department, Polymers Research Group, Queen’s University, Kingston, ON K7L 3N6, Canada * Corresponding author: [email protected] Received: 12.3.2014, Final version: 27.4.2014 Abstract: This historical study deepens the rheologist’s understanding of the motto of The Society of Rheology, of its history, and of its many typographies. The motto “ ” is not verbatim something written or said by the ancient Greek Ionian philosopher παντα ῥει̃ Heraclitus, ca. 540 – 480 BCE. Rather it is first encountered much later, in the writings of the Roman Simplicius ca. 490 – 560 CE. Thus, although it is uniformly agreed by Greek scholars that it correctly and concisely distills Heraclitian philosophy, that of con- stant change, and although this is appropriately used as the motto of The Society of Rheology, there is little point in trying to rewrite it into another form (for example to capitalize it) in an effort to be more faithful to an ancient prototype. Rather, we sug- gest simply reinstating the two missing diacritical marks, and thus, to express it as “ “ which is the form in which the πάντα ῥει̃ motto was introduced in 1929. This is also consistent with current typography of ancient Greek writings, in use since the ninth century CE, following the byzantine scholars. We provide Table 1 to facilitate accurate typesetting of the motto. Zusammenfassung: Diese historische Studie liefert dem Rheologen ein vertieftes Verständnis des Leitspruchs der Rheologischen Gesellschaft, seiner Geschichte, und seinen unterschiedlichen Schreibweisen.
    [Show full text]
  • La Rivoluzione Dimenticata (The Forgotten Revolution)
    La Rivoluzione Dimenticata (The Forgotten Revolution) by Lucio Russo Feltrinelli, Milan, 2001 [This remarkable book, published by Feltrinelli in Milan, first in 1996 and then in a new edition in 2001, is still available only in Italian. An English language edition is in preparation, and will appear with Springer Verlag. The excerpt below, Chapter I, is translated by Mark A. Peterson after correspon- dence with the author. ] 1 The Birth of Science 1.1 The suppression of the scientific revolution The central role of science in the development of our civilization is gener- ally recognized. One might therefore expect that its birth, the scientific revolution, would be considered a fundamental turning point in human his- tory. Instead, the importance of this event is almost never noticed. The history of scientific thought typically obscures it, by blurring the differ- ences among Hellenistic science, the pre-scientific knowledge of ancient Egyp- tian and Mesopotamian civilizations, and the natural philosophy of classi- cal Greece. Books on ancient history usually say nothing about it at all. Most of the time we are told only that in the Hellenistic period certain “sci- ences” flourished. One can typically find more attention to Archimedes or Aristarchus of Samos in a book on the Renaissance, dealing with their redis- covery, than in a book on classical civilization. The student of the modern age thinks of the Renaissance or the 17th century with an eye to present – what came after. Thus she cannot ignore the importance of the “Rebirth of Science.” The student of antiquity, on 1 the other hand, feels obliged (more so in the past, it is true) to compare Hellenism with the supposed perfection of classical Greece, or with Rome.
    [Show full text]
  • Space in Hellenistic Philosophy
    Graziano Ranocchia, Christoph Helmig, Christoph Horn (Eds.) Space in Hellenistic Philosophy Space in Hellenistic Philosophy Critical Studies in Ancient Physics Edited by Graziano Ranocchia Christoph Helmig Christoph Horn ISBN 978-3-11-036495-8 e-ISBN 978-3-11-036585-6 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A CIP catalog record for this book has been applied for at the Library of Congress. Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de. © 2014 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston Printing and binding: CPI books GmbH, Leck ♾ Printed on acid-free paper Printed in Germany www.degruyter.com Acknowledgements This volume has been published with the financial support of the European Research Council (ERC) and the National Research Council of Italy (CNR). Thanks are due to Aurora Corti for her editorial work and to Sergio Knipe for the linguis- tic revision of the manuscript. Table of Contents Abbreviations IX Introduction 1 Keimpe Algra Aristotle’s Conception of Place and its Reception in the Hellenistic Period 11 Michele Alessandrelli Aspects and Problems of Chrysippus’ Conception of Space 53 Teun Tieleman Posidonius on the Void. A Controversial Case of Divergence Revisited 69 David Konstan Epicurus on the Void 83 Holger Essler Space and Movement in Philodemus’ De dis 3: an Anti-Aristotelian Account 101 Carlos Lévy Roman Philosophy under
    [Show full text]
  • Classical Western Philosophy
    School of Distance Education UNIVERSITY OF CALICUT SCHOOL OF DISTANCE EDUCATION BA Philosophy (2011 Admission Onwards) V Semester Core Course Classical Western Philosophy QUESTION BANK 1 The original principle of this universe is------- according to Thales (a) Water (b) fire (c) air (d) ether 2 Thales is a------ philosopher (a)Milesian (b) Hebrew (c) Arab (d) German 3 -------- was counted among the Seven Wise Men (a)Plato (b) Socrates (c) Thales (d) Aristotle 4 The arche of things is apeiron, according to ------ (a)Plato (b) Socrates (c) Tales (d) Anaximander 5 According to Anaximenes--- is the first principle (a) Fire (b) water (c) infinite (d) air 6 Who said number is the essence and basis of all things? (a) Descartes (b) Pythagoras (c) Anaxagoras (d) Kant 7 Who is known as the Father of Western Philosophy? (a)Thales (b) Plato (c) Socrates (d) Aristotle Classical Western Philosophy Page 1 School of Distance Education 8. Aristotle is credited with --------- (a) Mathematical logic (b) Symbolic Logic (c) Syllogistic arguments (d) None of the above 9. Who advocated theory of atoms? (a) Plato (b) Democritus (c) Thales (d) Leibnitz 10. Who is the main atomist? (a) Leibnitz (b) Leucippus (c) Pythagoras (d) Kepler 11. Protagoras is a ------Philosopher (a) Sophist (b) spiritualist (c) Religious (d) idealist 12 Man is the measure of all things, according to ------ (a) Thales (b) Plato (c) Aristotle (d) Protagoras 13. Democritus and Leucippus are belonging to------ school (a)Ionian (b) atomist (c) idealist (d) Eleatic 14. ----- was the first Athenian born Philosopher (a) Thales (b) Plato (c) Aristotle (d) Socrates 15.
    [Show full text]
  • Before Socrates
    M01_BAIR3854_06_SE_C01.QXD 11/12/09 10:08 PM Page 1 BEFORE SOCRATES ሖሗመ Something unusual happened in Greece and the Greek colonies of the Aegean Sea some twenty-five hundred years ago. Whereas the previous great cultures of the Mediterranean had used mythological stories of the gods to explain the oper- ations of the world and of the self, some of the Greeks began to discover new ways of explaining things. Instead of reading their ideas into, or out of, ancient scriptures or poems, they began to use reason, contemplation, and sensory obser- vation to make sense of reality. The story, as we know it, began with the Greeks living on the coast of Asia Minor (present-day Turkey). These colonists, such as Thales, tried to find the one common element in the diversity of nature. Subsequent thinkers, such as Anaximenes, sought not only to find this one common element, but also to find the process by which one form changes into another. Other thinkers, such as Pythagoras, turned to the nature of form itself rather than the basic stuff that takes on a particular form. These lovers of wisdom, or philosophers, came to very dif- ferent conclusions and often spoke disrespectfully of one another. Some held the universe to be one, while others insisted that it must be many. Some believed that human knowledge was capable of understanding virtually everything about the world, while others thought that it was not possible to have any knowledge at all. But despite all their differences, there is a thread of continuity, a continuing focus: the human attempt to understand the world, using human reason.
    [Show full text]